Vienna Circle

First published Wed Jun 28, 2006; substantive revision Tue May 7, 2024

The Vienna Circle was a group of early twentieth-century philosophers who sought to reconceptualize empiricism by means of their interpretation of then recent advances in the physical and formal sciences. Their radically anti-metaphysical stance was supported by an empiricist criterion of meaningfulness and a broadly logicist conception of mathematics. They denied that any principle or claim was synthetic a priori. Moreover, they sought to account for the presuppositions of scientific theories by regimenting such theories within a logical framework so that the important role played by conventions, either in the form of definitions or of other analytical framework principles, became evident. The Vienna Circle’s theories were constantly changing. In spite (or perhaps because) of this, they helped to provide the blueprint for analytical philosophy of science as meta-theory—a “second-order” reflection on “first-order” sciences. While the Vienna Circle’s early form of logical empiricism (or logical positivism or neopositivism: these labels will be used interchangeably here) no longer represents an active research program, recent history of philosophy of science has unearthed much previously neglected variety and depth in the doctrines of the Circle’s protagonists, some of whose positions retain relevance for contemporary analytical philosophy.

1. Introductory Remarks

While it is in the nature of philosophical movements and their leading doctrines to court controversy, the Vienna Circle and its philosophies did so more than most. To begin with, its members styled themselves as conceptual revolutionaries who cleared the stables of academic philosophy by showing metaphysics not simply to be false, but to be cognitively empty and meaningless. In addition, they often associated their attempt to overcome metaphysics with their public engagement for scientific Enlightenment reason in the ever-darkening political situation of 1920s and 1930s central Europe. Small wonder then that the Vienna Circle has sharply divided opinion from the start. There is very little beyond the basic facts of membership and its record of publications and conferences that can be asserted about it without courting some degree of controversy. (For English-language survey monographs and articles on the Vienna Circle, see Kraft 1950 [1953]; Jørgensen 1951; Ayer 1959b; Passmore 1967; Hanfling 1981; Stadler 1998; Richardson 2003. Particularly rich in background and bio-bibliographical materials is Stadler 1997 [2015]. The best short introductory book has remained untranslated: Haller 1993. For popular overviews see Sigmund 2015 [2017] and Edmonds 2020.)

Fortunately, more than four decades worth of recent scholarship in history of philosophy of science now allows at least some disputes to be put into perspective. (See, e.g., the following at least in part English-language collections of articles and research monographs: Haller 1982; McGuinness 1985, 2011; Rescher 1985; Gower 1987; Proust 1989; Zolo 1989; Coffa 1991; Spohn 1991; Uebel 1991; Bell & Vossenkuhl 1992; Sarkar 1992; Uebel 1992; Oberdan 1993; Stadler 1993; Cirera 1990 [1994]; Salmon & Wolters 1994; Cartwright, Cat, Fleck, & Uebel 1996; Giere & Richardson 1996; Nemeth & Stadler 1996; Sarkar 1996; Richardson 1998; Friedman 1999b; Wolenski & Köhler 1999; Fetzer 2000; Friedman 2000; Bonk 2003; Hardcastle & Richardson 2003; Parrini, Salmon, & Salmon 2003; Stadler 2003; Awodey & Klein 2004; Reisch 2005; Galavotti 2006; Carus 2007; Friedman & Creath 2007; Nemeth, Schmitz, & Uebel 2007; Richardson & Uebel 2007; Uebel 2007; Wagner 2009; Manninen & Stadler 2010; Symons, Pombo, & Torres 2011; Creath 2012b; Wagner 2012; Frost-Arnold 2013; Blatti & Lapointe 2016; Damböck 2016; Ebbs 2017; Pihlström, Stadler, & Weidtmann 2017; Schiemer 2017; Tuboly 2017; Carus 2018; Cat & Tuboly 2019; Makovec & Shapiro 2019; Schuster 2020; Damböck & Wolters 2021; Lutz & Tuboly 2021; Damböck, Sandner, & Werner 2022; Damböck & Tuboly 2022; Ramharter 2022; Romizi, Walz, & Nemeth 2022; Uebel & Limbeck-Lilienau 2022; Bentley 2023; Morris 2023; Stadler 2023; Richardson 2024; Richardson & Tuboly 2024.) What distinguishes these works from valuable earlier collections like Schilpp 1963; Hintikka 1975; and Achinstein & Barker 1969 is the calling into question of the assumption that we understood the Vienna Circle so well that its consequences are straightforward. (Many other pieces of new Vienna Circle scholarship are spread throughout philosophical journals and essay collections with more systematic or wider historical scope; important work has also been done in German, Italian and French language publications but these remain unreferenced here.)

Two facts must be clearly recognized if a proper evaluation of the Vienna Circle is to be attempted. The first is, that, despite its relatively short existence, even some of the most central theses of the Vienna Circle underwent radical changes. The second is that its members were by no means of one mind in all important matters; occasionally they espoused perspectives so radically at variance with each other that even their ostensive agreements cannot remain wholly untouched. Behind the rather thin public front, then, quite different philosophical projects were being pursued by the leading participants with, moreover, changing alliances. One way of taking account of this is by speaking (as above) explicitly of the philosophies (in the plural) of the Vienna Circle (and to avoid the singular definite description) while using the expression “Vienna Circle philosophy” (without an article) in a neutral generic sense.

Recent scholarship has provided what the traditional view of Viennese neopositivism lacks: recognition and documentation of the sometimes sharply differentiated positions behind the generic surface. This does not invalidate all previous scholarship, including some fundamental criticisms of its positions, but it restores a depth to Vienna Circle philosophy that was absent from the standard histories. The value of this development must not be underestimated, for the recognition of the Vienna Circle’s sophisticated engagement with aspects of the philosophical tradition and contemporaneous challenges calls into question unwarranted certainties of our own self-consciously post-positivist era. While there remains support for the view that philosophical doctrines were held in the Vienna Circle that wholly merited many of the standard criticisms to be cited below, there is now also support for the view that in nearly all such cases, these doctrines were already in their day opposed within the Circle itself. While some of the Vienna Circle philosophies are dated and may even be, as John Passmore once put it, as dead as philosophies can be, others show signs of surprising vitality. Which ones these are, however, remains a matter of debate.

The lead pursued in this article is provided by the comment of a long-time associate of the Vienna Circle, C.G. Hempel, made on the occasion of the Carnap-Reichenbach centenary in 1991:

When people these days talk about logical positivism or the Vienna Circle and say that its ideas are passé, this is just wrong. This overlooks the fact that there were two quite different schools of logical empiricism, namely the one of Carnap and Schlick and so on and then the quite different one of Otto Neurath, who advocates a completely pragmatic conception of the philosophy of science…. And this form of empiricism is in no way affected by any of the fundamental objections against logical positivism…. (quoted in Wolters 2003: 117)

While differing with Hempel’s specific claim about how the two “schools” divide, the aim here is to fill out his suggestive picture by indicating what Schlick, Carnap and Neurath stand for philosophically and why the different wings of the Vienna Circle require differentiated assessments. After reviewing the basic facts and providing an overall outline of Vienna Circle philosophy (in section 2), this article considers various doctrines in greater detail by way of discussing standard criticisms with the appropriate distinctions in mind (in section 3). No comprehensive assessment of the Vienna Circle and the work of its members can be attempted here, but some basic conclusions will be drawn (in section 4).

2. The Basics: People, Activities and Overview of Doctrines

2.1 People

The Vienna Circle was a group of scientifically trained philosophers and philosophically interested scientists who met under the (nominal) leadership of Moritz Schlick for often weekly discussions of problems in the philosophy of science during academic terms in the years from 1924 to 1936. As is not uncommon with such groups, its identity is blurred along several edges. Not all of those who ever attended the discussions can be called members, and not all who attended did so over the entire period. Typically, attention is focused on long-term regulars who gained prominence through their philosophical publications, but even these do not in all cases fall into the period of the Vienna Circle proper. It is natural, nevertheless, to consider under the heading “Vienna Circle” also the later work of leading members who were still active in the 1940s, 50s and 60s. Finally, there is the so-called periphery of international contacts and visitors that prefigured the post-World War II network of analytical philosophers of science. In the present article the emphasis will be placed on the long-term regulars whose contributions will be followed, selectively, into the post-Schlick era.

According to its unofficial manifesto (see section 2.3 below), the Circle had “members” and recognized others as “sympathetic” to its aims. It included as members, besides Schlick who had been appointed to Mach’s old chair in Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences at the University of Vienna in 1922, the mathematician Hans Hahn, the physicist Philipp Frank, the social scientist Otto Neurath, his wife, the mathematician Olga Hahn-Neurath, the philosopher Viktor Kraft, the mathematicians Theodor Radacovic and Gustav Bergmann and, since 1926, the philosopher and logician Rudolf Carnap. (Even before World War I, there existed a similarly oriented informal discussion group that included Frank, Hahn and Neurath. During the time of the Schlick Circle, Frank resided in Prague throughout, Carnap did so from 1931.) Further members were recruited among Schlick’s students, like Friedrich Waismann, Herbert Feigl and Marcel Natkin, others were recruited among Hahn’s students, like Karl Menger and Kurt Gödel. Though listed as members in the manifesto, Menger and Kraft later wanted to be known only as sympathetic associates, like, all along, the mathematician Kurt Reidemeister and the philosopher and historian of science Edgar Zilsel. (Karl Popper was never a member or associate of the Circle, though he studied with Hahn in the 1920s and in the early 1930s discussed its doctrines with Feigl and Carnap.) Over the years, other participants (not listed in the manifesto) included other students of Schlick’s and Hahn’s like Bela von Juhos, Josef Schächter, Walter Hollitscher, Heinrich Neider, Rose Rand, Josef Rauscher and Käthe Steinhardt, a secondary teacher, Robert Neumann, and, as notable thinkers with independent connections, the jurist and philosopher Felix Kaufmann (also a member of F.A. von Hayek’s “Geistkreis”) and the innovative psychologist Egon Brunswik (coming, like the even more loosely associated sociologists Paul Lazarsfeld and Marie Jahoda, from the pioneering Karl Bühler’s University Institute of Psychology).

Despite its prominent position in the rich, if fragile, intellectual culture of inter-war Vienna and most likely due to its radical doctrines, the Vienna Circle found itself virtually isolated in most of German speaking philosophy. The one exception was its contact and cooperation with the Berlin Society for Empirical (later: Scientific) Philosophy (the other point of origin of logical empiricism). The members of the Berlin Society sported a broadly similar outlook and included, besides the philosopher Hans Reichenbach, the logicians Kurt Grelling and Walter Dubislav, the psychologist Kurt Lewin, the surgeon Friedrich Kraus and the mathematician Richard von Mises. (Its leading members Reichenbach, Grelling and Dubislav were listed in the Circle’s manifesto as sympathisers.) At the same time, members of the Vienna Circle also engaged directly, if selectively, with the Warsaw logicians (Tarski visited Vienna in 1930, Carnap later that year visited Warsaw and Tarski returned to Vienna in 1935). Probably partly because of its firebrand reputation, the Circle also attracted a series of visiting younger researchers and students including Carl Gustav Hempel from Berlin, Hasso Härlen from Stuttgart, Ludovico Geymonat from Italy, Jørgen Jørgensen, Eino Kaila, Arne Naess and Ake Petzall from Scandinavia, A.J. Ayer from the UK, Albert Blumberg, Charles Morris, Ernest Nagel and W.V.O. Quine from the USA, H.A. Lindemann from Argentina and Tscha Hung from China. (The reports and recollections of these former visitors—e.g. Nagel 1936—are of interest in complementing the Circle’s in-house histories and recollections which start with the unofficial manifesto—Carnap, Hahn, and Neurath 1929—and extend through Neurath 1935c; Frank 1941a, 1949a; and Feigl 1943 to the memoirs by Carnap 1963; Feigl 1969a, 1969b; Bergmann 1987; Menger 1994.)

The aforementioned social and political engagement of members of the Vienna Circle and of Vienna Circle philosophy for Enlightenment reason had never made the advancement of its associates or protegées easy in Viennese academia. From 1934 onwards, with anti-semitism institutionalized and irrationalism increasingly dominating public discourse, this engagement began to cost the Circle still more dearly. Not only was the Verein Ernst Mach closed down early that year for political reasons, but the ongoing dispersal of Circle members by emigration, forced exile and death meant that after the murder of Schlick in 1936 only a small rump was able to continue meetings for another two years in Vienna:

  • 1931: Feigl emigrated to USA after a post-doctoral year there.
  • 1934: Hahn died, Neurath fled to Holland (and in 1940 to the UK).
  • 1935: Carnap emigrated to USA.
  • 1936: Schlick was murdered.
  • 1937: Menger emigrated to USA, Waismann to UK.
  • 1938: Frank, Kaufmann, Brunswik, Bergmann emigrated to USA; Zilsel, Rand to UK, later to USA; Hollitscher fled to Switzerland, later to UK; Schächter emigrated to Palestine.
  • 1940: Gödel emigrated to USA.

See Dahms 1995, for a full chronology of the exodus.

But the end of the Vienna Circle as such did not mean the end of its influence due to the continuing development of the philosophy of former members (and the work of Kraft in the otherwise unregenerated post-World War II Vienna who nurtured such different voices as Paul Feyerabend and Ingeborg Bachmann and hosted Arthur Pap; on this see Stadler 2008). Particularly through their work in American exile (esp. Carnap at Harvard, Chicago and UCLA; Feigl at Iowa and Minnesota; less obviously so Frank at Harvard) and that of earlier American visitors (esp. Quine, Nagel), as well as through the work of fellow emigrées from the Berlin Society (esp. Reichenbach, Hempel) and their students (Hilary Putnam, Wesley Salmon), logical empiricism strongly influenced the post-World War II development of analytic philosophy of science. By contrast, Waismann had little influence in the UK where Neurath, already marginalized, had died in 1945. The full story of logical empiricism’s acculturation in the English speaking world remains to be written. (See Howard 2003; Reisch 2005; Uebel 2005a, 2010, 2020a; Douglas 2009; and Romizi 2012 for consideration of the socio-political aspects of Vienna Circle philosophy early and/or late that were neglected in the process and remained long forgotten.)

2.2 Activities

After its formative phase which was confined to the Thursday evening discussions, the Circle went public in 1928 and 1929 when it seemed that the time had come for their emerging philosophy to play a distinctive role not only in the academic but also the public sphere. In November 1928, at its founding session, Schlick accepted the presidency of the newly formed Verein Ernst Mach (Association Ernst Mach), Hahn accepted one of its vice-presidencies and Neurath and Carnap joined its secretariat. Originally proposed by the Austrian Freidenkerbund (Free Thinker Association), the Verein Ernst Mach was dedicated to the dissemination of scientific ways of thought and so provided a forum for popular lectures on the new scientific philosophy. In the following year the Circle stepped out under its own name (invented by Neurath) with a manifesto and a special conference. The publication of “The Scientific World Conception: The Vienna Circle”, signed by Carnap, Hahn and Neurath and dedicated to Schlick, coincided with the “First Conference for the Epistemology of the Exact Sciences” in mid-September 1929, organised jointly with the Berlin Society as an adjunct to the Fifth Congress of German Physicists and Mathematicians in Prague (where Frank played a prominent role in the local organising committee). (On the production history and early reception of the manifesto see Uebel 2008.) A distinct philosophical movement appeared to be emerging, one that was dedicated to ending the previous disputes of philosophical schools by dismissing them, controversially, as strictly speaking meaningless.

Throughout the early and mid-1930s the Circle kept a high and increasingly international profile with its numerous publications and conferences. In 1930, the Circle took over, again together with the Berlin Society, the journal Annalen der Philosophie and restarted it under the name of Erkenntnis with Carnap and Reichenbach as co-editors. (Besides publishing original articles and sustaining lengthy debates, this journal featured selected proceedings of their early conferences and documented the lecture series of the Verein Ernst Mach and the Berlin Society as well as their international congresses.) In addition, from 1928 until 1936, Schlick and Frank served as editors of their book series “Schriften zur wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung” (“Writings on the Scientific World Conception”), which published major works by leading members and early critics like Popper, while Neurath edited, from 1933 until 1939, the series “Einheitswissenschaft” (“Unified Science”), which published more introductory essays by leading members and sympathisers. Conference-wise, the Circle organized, again with the Berlin Society, a “Second Conference for the Epistemology of the Exact Sciences” as an adjunct to the Sixth Congress of German Physicists and Mathematicians in Königsberg in September 1930 (where Reidemeister played a prominent role in the organization and Gödel first announced his incompleteness result in the discussion) and then began the series of International Congresses on the Unity of Science with a “Pre-Conference” just prior to the start of the Eighth International Congress of Philosophy in Prague in September 1934. This, their last conference in Central Europe, was followed by the International Congresses of various sizes in Paris (September 1935, July 1937), Copenhagen (June 1936), Cambridge, England (July 1938), Cambridge, Mass. (September 1939), all in the main organized by Neurath; a smaller last gathering was held in Chicago in September 1941. By 1938 their collective publication activity began to centre on a monumentally planned International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, with Neurath as editor-in-chief and Carnap and Charles Morris as co-editors; by the time of Neurath’s death in 1945, only 10 monographs had appeared and the series was wound up in 1970 numbering 20 monographs under the title “Foundations of the Unity of Science” (notably containing Thomas Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions amongst them).

Individually, the members of the Vienna Circle published extensively before, during and after the years of the Circle around Schlick. For some (Frank, Hahn, Menger, Neurath), philosophy was only part of their scientific output, with numerous monographs and articles in their respective disciplines (mathematics, physics and social science); others (Schlick, Carnap, Feigl, Waismann) concentrated on philosophy, but even their output cared relatively little for traditional concerns of the field. Here it must be noted that two early monographs by Schlick (1918/25) and Carnap (1928a), commonly associated with the Vienna Circle, mostly predate their authors’ participation there and exhibit a variety of influences not typically associated with logical positivism (see section 3.7 below). Moreover, important monographs by Frank (1932), Neurath (1931a), Carnap (1934c [1937]) and Menger (1934) in the first half of the 1930s represent moves away from positions that had been held in the Circle before and contradict its orthodox profile. Yet the Circle’s orthodoxy, as it were, is not easily pinned down either. Schlick himself was critical of the manifesto of 1929 and gave a brief vision statement of his own in “The Turning Point in Philosophy” (1930). A long-planned book by Waismann of updates on Wittgenstein’s thought, to which Schlick was extremely sympathetic, was never completed as originally planned and only appeared posthumously (Waismann 1965; for related material see Baker 2003 and Manninen 2011). Comparison with rough transcripts of the Circle’s discussions in the early 1930s (for transcripts from between December 1930 and July 1931 see Stadler 1997 [2015: 69–123]) suggest that Waismann’s Wittgensteinian “Theses”, dated to “around 1930” (McGuinness 1967 [1979: Appendix B]), come closest to an elaboration of the orthodox Circle position at that time (but which remained not undisputed even then). Again, what needs to be stressed is that all of the Circle’s publications are to be understood as contributions to ongoing discussions among its members and associates.

2.3 Overview of Doctrines

Despite the pluralism of the Vienna Circle’s views, there did exist a minimal consensus which may be put as follows. A theory of scientific knowledge was propagated which sought to renew empiricism by freeing it from the impossible task of justifying the claims of the formal sciences. It will be noted that this updating did not leave empiricism unchanged.

Following the logicism of Frege and Russell, the Circle considered logic and mathematics to be analytic in nature. Extending Wittgenstein’s insight about logical truths to mathematical ones as well, the Circle considered both to be tautological. Like true statements of logic, mathematical statements did not express factual truths: devoid of empirical content they only concerned ways of representing the world, spelling out implication relations between statements. The knowledge claims of logic and mathematics gained their justification on purely formal grounds, by proof of their derivability by stated rules from stated axioms and premises. (Depending on the standing of these axioms and premises, justification was conditional or unconditional.) Thus defanged of appeals to rational intuition, the contribution of pure reason to human knowledge (in the form of logic and mathematics) was thought easily integrated into the empiricist framework. (Carnap sought to accommodate Gödel’s incompleteness results by separating analyticity from effective provability and by postulating that arithmetic consisted of an infinite series of ever richer arithmetical languages; see the discussion and references in section 3.2 below.)

The synthetic statements of the empirical sciences meanwhile were held to be cognitively meaningful if and only if they were empirically testable in some sense. They derived their justification as knowledge claims from successful tests. Here the Circle appealed to a criterion of meaningfulness (cognitive significance) the correct formulation of which was problematical and much debated (and will be discussed in greater detail in section 3.1 below). Roughly, if synthetic statements failed testability in principle they were considered to be cognitively meaningless (lacking evaluatability of their truth) and to give rise only to pseudo-problems (on account of the merely associative or emotive meanings they did possess). No third category of significance besides that of a priori analytical and a posteriori synthetic statements was admitted: in particular, Kant’s synthetic a priori was banned as having been refuted by the progress of science itself. (The theory of relativity showed what had been held to be an example of the synthetic a priori, namely Euclidean geometry, to be false as the geometry of physical space.) Thus the Circle rejected the knowledge claims of metaphysics as being neither analytic and a priori nor empirical and synthetic. (On related but different grounds, they also rejected the knowledge claims of normative ethics: whereas conditional norms could be grounded in means-ends relations, unconditional norms remained unprovable in empirical terms and so depended crucially on the disputed substantive a priori intuition.)

Given their empiricism, all of the members of the Vienna Circle also called into question the principled separation of the natural and the human sciences. They were happy enough to admit to differences in their object domains, but denied the categorical difference in both their overarching methodologies and ultimate goals in inquiry, which the historicist tradition in the still only emerging social sciences and the idealist tradition in philosophy insisted on. The Circle’s own methodologically monist position was sometimes represented under the heading of “unified science”. Precisely how such a unification of the sciences was to be effected or understood remained a matter for further discussion (see section 3.3 below).

It is easy to see that, combined with the rejection of rational intuition, the Vienna Circle’s exclusive apportionment of reason into either formal a priori reasoning, issuing in analytic truths (or contradictions), and substantive a posteriori reasoning, issuing in synthetic truths (or falsehoods), severely challenged the traditional understanding of philosophy. All members of the Circle hailed the end of distinctive philosophical system building. In line with the Tractatus claim that all philosophy is really a critique of language, the Vienna Circle took the so-called linguistic turn, the turn to representation as the proper subject matter of philosophy. Philosophy itself was denied a separate first-order domain of expertise and declared a second-order inquiry. Whether the once queen of the sciences was thereby reduced to the mere handmaiden of the latter was still left open. It remained a matter of disagreement what type of distinctively philosophical insight, if any, would remain legitimate. Just as importantly, however, the tools of modern logic were employed also for metatheoretical construction, not just for the reduction of empirical claims to their observational base or, more generally, for the derivation of their observational consequences. For the price of abandoning foundationalist certainty this allowed for an enormous expansion of the domain of empirical discourse. Ultimately, it opened the space for the still ongoing discussions of scientific realism and its alternatives (see section 3.4 below).

The Circle’s leading protagonists differed in how they conceptualized this reflexive second-order inquiry that the linguistic turn had inaugurated. Nevertheless, they all agreed broadly that the ways of representing the world were largely determined by convention. A multitude of ideas hide behind this invocation of conventionality. One particularly radical one is the denial of the apodicity of all apriority, the denial of the claim that knowledge justified through reason alone represents truths that are unconditionally necessary. Another one is the imputation of agency in the construction of the logico-linguistic frameworks that make human cognition possible, the denial that conventionality could only mean acquiescence in tradition. Whether such ideas were followed by individual members of the Circle, however, depended on their own interests and influences. It is these often overlooked or misunderstood differences that hold the key to understanding the interplay of occasionally incompatible positions that make up Vienna Circle philosophy. (As can be seen from some of their internal disputes, moreover, these differences were also not always obvious to the protagonists themselves.)

To see a striking example, consider their overarching conceptions of philosophy itself. Some protagonists retained the idea that philosophy possessed a separate disciplinary identity from science and, like Schlick, turned philosophy into a distinctive, albeit non-formal activity of meaning determination. Others, like Carnap, agreed on the distinction between philosophy and science but turned philosophy into a purely formal enterprise, the so-called logic of science. Still others went even further and, like Neurath under the banner of “unified science”, also rejected philosophy as a separate discipline and treated what remained of it, after the rejection of metaphysics, as its partly empirical meta-theory, to be set beside the logic of science. With Schlick, then, philosophy became the activity of achieving a much clarified and deepened understanding of the cognitive and linguistic practices actually already employed in science and everyday discourse. By contrast, for Carnap, philosophy investigated and reconstructed existing language fragments, developed new logico-linguistic frameworks and suggested possible formal conventions for science, while, for Neurath, the investigation of science was pursued by an interdisciplinary meta-theory that encompassed empirical disciplines, again with a pragmatic orientation. Thus we find in apparent competition different conceptions of post-metaphysical philosophy: the projects of experiential meaning determination, of formal rational reconstruction and of naturalistic explications of leading theoretical and methodological notions. (For roughly representative early essay-length statements of their positions see Schlick 1930, Carnap 1932a, and Neurath 1932a; later restatements are given in Schlick 1937, Carnap 1936b, and Neurath 1936a, 1936b.) In the more detailed discussions below these differences of overall approach will figure repeatedly (see also section 3.6 below).

Criticisms of the basic positions adopted in the Vienna Circle are legion, though it may be questioned whether most of them took account of the sophisticated variations on offer. (Sometimes the Circle’s own writings are disregarded altogether and “logical positivism” is discussed only via the proxy of Ayer’s popular exposition; see, e.g., Soames 2003.) But some Neo-Kantians like Ernst Cassirer may claim that they too accepted developments like the merely relative a priori and an appropriate conception of the historical development of science. Likewise, Wittgensteinians may claim that Wittgenstein’s own opposition to metaphysics only concerned false attempts to render it intelligible: his merely ineffable but uneliminated metaphysics concerned precisely what for him were essentials of ways of representing the world. The commonest criticisms, however, concerned not the uniqueness of the Vienna Circle’s doctrines, or their faithfulness to their supposed sources, but whether they were tenable at all. Prominent objects of this type of criticism include the verificationist theory of meaning and its claimed anti-metaphysical and non-cognitivist consequences as well as its own significance; the reductionism in phenomenalist or physicalist guises that appeared to attend the Circle’s attempted operationalisation of the logical atomism of Russell and Wittgenstein; and the Circle’s alleged scientism in general and their formalist and a-historical conception of scientific cognition in particular. These criticisms are discussed in some detail below in order to assess why which of the associated doctrines remain of what importance.

As noted, the Vienna Circle did not last long: its philosophical revolution came at a cost. Yet what was so socially, indeed politically, explosive about what appears on first sight to be a particularly arid, if not astringent, doctrine of specialist scientific knowledge? In a large part, precisely what made it so controversial philosophically: its claim to refute opponents not by proving their statements to be false but by showing them to be (cognitively) meaningless. Whatever the niceties of their philosophical argument here, the socio-political impact of the Vienna Circle’s philosophies of science was obvious and profound. All of them opposed the increasing groundswell of radically mistaken, indeed irrational, ways of thinking about thought and its place in the world. In their time and place, the mere demand that public discourse be perspicuous, in particular, that reasoning be valid and premises true—a demand implicit in their general ideal of reason—placed them in the middle of crucial socio-political struggles. Some members and sympathisers of the Circle also actively opposed the then increasingly popular völkisch supra-individual holism in social science as a dangerous intellectual aberration. Not only did such ideas support racism and fascism in politics, but such ideas themselves were supported only by radically mistaken arguments concerning the nature and explanation of organic and inorganic matter. So the first thing that made all of the Vienna Circle philosophies politically relevant was the contingent fact that in their day much political discourse exhibited striking epistemic deficits. That some of the members of the Circle went, without logical blunders, still further by arguing that socio-political considerations can play a legitimate role in some instances of theory choice due to underdetermination is yet another matter. This particular issue cannot be pursued further here (see references at the end of section 2.1 above), nor the general topic of the Circle’s embedding in modernism and the discourse of modernity (see Putnam 1981b for a reductionist, Galison 1990 for a foundationalist, Uebel 1996 for a constructivist reading of their modernism, Dahms 2004 for an account of personal relations with representatives of modernism in art and architecture, Carus 2007 for placing Carnap in an updated Enlightenment perspective; for a discussion of the Circle’s philosophical methodologies in the context of logical empiricism more generally see Pincock 2016).

3. Selected Doctrines and their Criticisms

Even with these outlines of Vienna Circle philosophy in hand, its controversial character is evident. The boldness of its claims made it attractive but that boldness also seemed to be its undoing. Turning to the questions of how far and, if at all, which forms of Vienna Circle philosophy stand up to some common criticisms, both the synchronic variations and the diachronic trajectories of its variants must be taken into account. This will be attempted in the sections below.

Before expectations are raised too high, however, it must also remembered that in this article only the views of members of the Vienna Circle can be discussed, even though the problematic issues were pervasive in logical empiricism generally. (Compare the SEP article on logical empiricism; for articles on Reichenbach see, e.g, Spohn 1991 and Salmon & Wolters 1994; Richardson 2005, 2006; Curiel & Padovani 2021–21; and, for the Berlin Group as a whole, Milkov & Peckhaus 2013.) Moreover, here the emphasis must lie on the main protagonists: Schlick, Carnap and Neurath. (Neither Hahn or Frank, nor Waismann or Feigl, for instance, can be discussed here as extensively as their work deserves: see, e.g., Sigmund 1995, Uebel 2005b on Hahn; Howard 2021, Reisch & Tuboly 2021 on Frank; McGuinness 2011, Makovec & Shapiro 2019 on Waismann; Haller 2003, Neuber 2011 on Feigl.) What will be noted, however, is that Vienna Circle philosophy was by no means identical with the post-World War II logical empiricism that has come to be known as the “received view” of scientific theories, even though it would be hard to imagine the latter wholly without the former (see section 3.4).

To deepen the somewhat cursory overview of Vienna Circle philosophy given above, we now turn to the discussion of the following issues: first, the viability of the conceptions of empirical significance employed by the Vienna Circle in its classical period; second, its uses of the analytic-synthetic distinction; third, its supposedly reductionist designs and foundationalist ambitions for philosophy; fourth, its stances in the debate about realism or anti-realism with regard to the theoretical terms in science; fifth, Carnap’s later ideas in response to some of the problems encountered; sixth, the issue of the status of the meaning criterion itself (variably referred to also as “criterion of significance” or “criterion of empirical significance”) and of the point of their critique of metaphysics; seventh, the Vienna Circle’s attitude towards history and of their own place in the history of philosophy.

These topics have been chosen for the light their investigation throws on the Circle’s own agendas and the reception of its doctrines amongst philosophers at large, as well as for the relative ease with which their discussion allows its development and legacy to be charted. There can be little doubt about the enormous impact that the members of the Vienna Circle had on the development of twentieth-century philosophy. What is less clear is whether any of its distinctive doctrines are left standing once the dust of their debates has settled or whether those of its teachings that were deemed defensible merged seamlessly into the broad church that analytic philosophy has become (and, if so, what those surviving doctrines and teachings may be).

It must be noted, then, that the topics chosen for this article do not exhaust the issues concerning which the members of the Vienna Circle made significant contributions (which continue to stimulate work in the history of philosophy of science). Important topics like that of the theory and practice of unified science, of the nature of the empirical basis of science (the so-called protocol-sentence debate) and of the general structure of the theories of individual sciences can only be touched upon selectively. Likewise, while the general topic of ethical non-cognitivism receives only passing mentions, the Circle’s varied approaches to value theory cannot be discussed here (for an overview see Rutte 1986, for detailed analyses see Siegetsleitner 2014). Other matters, like the contributions made by Vienna Circle members to the development of probability theory and inductive logic, the philosophy of logic and mathematics (apart from the guiding ideas of Carnap) and to the philosophy of individual empirical sciences (physics, biology, psychology, social science), cannot be discussed at all (see Friedman & Creath 2007 and Richardson & Uebel 2007 for relevant essays with further references). But it may be noted that with his “logic of science” Carnap counts among the pioneers of what nowadays is called “formal epistemology”.

3.1 Verificationism and the Critique of Metaphysics

Not surprisingly, it was the Circle’s rejection of metaphysics by means of their seemingly devastating criterion of cognitive significance that attracted immediate opposition. (That they did not deny all meaning to statements thus ruled out of court was freely admitted from early on, but this “expressive” surplus was considered secondary to so-called cognitive meaning and discountable in science (see Carnap 1928b, 1932a).) Notwithstanding the metaphysicans’ thunder, however, the most telling criticisms of the criterion came from within the Circle or broadly sympathetic philosophers. When it was protested that failure to meet an empiricist criterion of significance did not make philosophical statements meaningless, members of the Circle simply asked for an account of what this non-empirical and presumably non-emotive meaning consisted in and typically received no convincing answer. The weakness of their position was rather that their own criterion of empirical significance seemed to resist an acceptable formal characterization.

To start with, it must be noted that long before the verification principle proper entered the Circle’s discourse in the late 1920s, the thought expressed by Mach’s dictum that “where neither confirmation nor refutation is possible, science is not concerned” (1883 [1960: 587]) was accepted as a basic precept of critical reflection about science. Responsiveness to evidence for and against a claim was the hallmark of scientific discourse. Particularly the group Frank-Hahn-Neurath, who formed part of a pre-World War I discussion group (Frank 1941a, 1949a) sometimes called the “First Vienna Circle” (Haller 1985; Uebel 2003, 2022), can be presumed to be familiar with Mach’s criterion. Beyond this, still in the mid-1920s, Schlick (1926) convicted metaphysics for falsely trying to express as logically structured cognition what is but the inexpressible qualitative content of experience. Soon, however, Carnap (1928b: §7) edged towards a formal criterion of meaningfulness by requiring empirically significant statements to be such that experiential support for them or for their negation is at least conceivable. Meaningfulness meant the possession of “factual content” which could not, on pain of rendering many scientific hypotheses meaningless, be reduced to actual testability. Instead, the empirical significance of a statement had to be conceived of as possession of the potential to receive direct or indirect experiential support (via deductive or inductive reasoning).

In 1930, considerations of this sort appeared to receive a considerable boost due to Waismann’s reports of Wittgenstein’s meetings with him and Schlick. Wittgenstein had discussed the thesis “The sense of a proposition is [the method of] its verification” in conversations with Schlick and Waismann on 22 December 1929 and 2 January 1930 (see McGuinness 1967 [1979: 47 and 79]) and Waismann elaborated it in his “Theses” which were presented to the Circle as Wittgenstein’s considered views. While Wittgenstein appears to have thought of his dictum also as a constitutive principle of meaning, in the Circle it was put to work mainly as a demarcation criterion against metaphysics. Whether it was always noted that verificationism as a theory of meaning and as a criterion of cognitive significance must be distinguished (the former entails the latter, but not vice versa) may be doubted, but striking differences emerged all the same. Like Carnap’s criterion of significance of 1928, the version of the criterion which followed from Wittgenstein’s dictum also demanded only verifiability in principle (and did not demand actual verifiability): like Carnap’s notion of experiential support, it worked with the mere conceivability of verifiability. Yet Wittgenstein’s criterion required conclusive verifiability which Carnap’s did not. (The demand for conclusive verifiability was discussed in the meetings with Wittgenstein.) By 1931, however, it had become clear to some that this would not do. What Carnap later called the “liberalization of empiricism” was underway and different camps became discernible within the Circle. It was over this issue that the so-called left wing with Carnap, Hahn, Frank and Neurath first distinguished itself from the “more conservative wing” around Schlick. (See Carnap 1936/37: 422 and 1963a: §9. Carnap 1936/37: 37n dated the opposition to strict verificationism to “about 1931”.)

In the first place, this liberalization meant the accommodation of universally quantified statements and the return to salient aspects of Carnap’s 1928 conception. Everybody had noted that Wittgenstein’s criterion rendered universally quantified statements meaningless. Schlick (1931) thus followed Wittgenstein’s own suggestion to treat “hypotheses” instead as representing rules for the formation of verifiable singular statements. (His abandonment of conclusive verifiability is indicated only in Schlick 1936a.) By contrast, Hahn (1933, drawn from lectures in 1932) pointed out that hypotheses should be counted properly meaningful as well and that the criterion be weakened to allow for less than conclusive verifiability. But other elements played into this liberalization as well. One that began to do so soon was the recognition of the problem of the irreducibility of disposition terms to observation terms (more on this presently). A third element was that disagreement arose as to whether the conceivability of in-principle verifiability turned on what was merely logically possible or on what was nomologically possible, as a matter of physical law etc. A fourth element, finally, was that differences emerged as to whether the criterion of significance was to apply to all languages or whether it was to apply primarily to constructed, formal languages. Schlick retained the focus on logical possibility and natural languages throughout, but Carnap had firmly settled his focus on nomological possibility and constructed languages by the mid-thirties. Concerned with natural language, Schlick (1932, 1936a) deemed all statements meaningful for which it was logically possible to conceive of a procedure of verification; concerned with constructed languages only, Carnap (1936/37) deemed meaningful only statements for whom it was nomologically possible to conceive of a procedure of confirmation of disconfirmation.

Many of these issues were discussed at the Paris congress in 1935. Already in 1932 Carnap had sought to sharpen his earlier criterion by stipulating that those statements were meaningful that were syntactically well-formed and whose non-logical terms were reducible to terms occurring in the basic observational evidence statements of science. While Carnap’s focus on the reduction of descriptive terms allowed for the conclusive verification of some statements, it must be noted that his criterion also allowed universally quantified statements to be meaningful in general, provided they were syntactically and terminologically correct (1932a: §2). Logical Syntax (1934c [1937]: §82) then affirmed universal fallibilism, but it was not until one of his Paris addresses that Carnap officially declared the criterion of cognitive significance to be mere confirmability (1936a; its English translation combines it with extraneous material). Carnap’s new criterion required neither verification nor falsification but only partial testability and so fitted in with the latest development by including as empirically significant not only universal statements but also singular statements which now were recognized as irreducible to observation statements, like the disposition statements of science (see Carnap 1936/37; this was proposed first in another Paris congress paper: 1936c). Disposition terms were thought to be linked to observation statements by a variety of reduction postulates or longer reduction chains, all of which provided only partial definitions (despite their name they provided no eliminative reductions). Though well-motivated initially, the device of introducing non-observational terms in this way gave rise to a number of difficulties which impugned the supposedly clear distinctions between logical and empirical matters and analytic and synthetic statements (Hempel 1963). Independently, Carnap himself (1939) soon gave up the hope that all theoretical terms of science could be related to an observational base by such reduction chains. This raised a serious problem for the formulation of a criterion of cognitive significance: how was one to rule out unwanted metaphysical claims while admitting as significant highly abstract scientific claims?

Consider that Carnap (1939, 1956b) admitted as legitimate theoretical terms that are implicitly defined in calculi that are only partially interpreted by correspondence rules between some select calculus terms and expressions belonging to an observational language (via non-eliminative reductions). The problem was that mere confirmability was simply too weak a criterion to rule out some putative metaphysical claims. Moreover, this problem arose for both the statement-based approach to the criterion (taken by Carnap in 1928b, by Wittgenstein in conversations in 1929/30 [see McGuinness 1967] and by Ayer both in the first and the second editions of Language, Truth and Logic [1936 & 1946]) and for the term-based approach (taken by Carnap since 1932). For the former approach, the problem was that the empirical legitimacy of statements obtained via indirect testing also transferred to any expressions that could be truth-functionally conjoined to them (for instance, by the rule of ‘or’-introduction). Statements thus became empirically significant, however vacuous they had been on their own. For the term-based approach, the problem was that, given the non-eliminability of dispositional and theoretical terms, empirical significance was no longer ascribable to individual expressions in isolation but became a holistic affair, with little guarantee in turn for the empiricist legitimacy of all the terms now involved.

For most critics (even within the ranks of logical empiricism), the problem of ruling out metaphysical statements while retaining the terms of high theory remained unsolved. By 1950, in response to the troubles of Ayer’s two attempts to account for the indirect testing of theoretical statements via their consequences, Hempel conceded that it was “useless to continue to search for an adequate criterion of testability in terms of deductive relationships to observation sentences” (1950 [1959: 116]). The following year, Hempel also abandoned the idea of using, as a criterion of empirical significance, Carnap’s method of translatability into an antecedently determined empirical language consisting only of observational non-logical vocabulary. Precisely because it was suitably liberalized to allow abstract scientific theories with merely partial interpretations, its anti-metaphysical edge was blunted: it allowed for combination with “some set of metaphysical propositions, even if the latter have no empirical interpretation at all” (1951: 70). Hempel drew the holistic conclusion that the units of empirical significance were entire theories and that the measure of empirical significance itself was multi-criterial and, moreover, allowed for degrees of significance. To many, this amounted to the demise of the Circle’s anti-metaphysical campaign. By contrast, Feigl’s reaction (1955) was to reduce the ambition of the criterion of significance to the mere provision of necessary conditions.

Some further work was undertaken on rescuing and, again, debunking versions of the statement-based criterion, but mostly not by (former) members of the Vienna Circle. However, in response to the problem of how to formulate a meaning criterion that suitably distinguished between empirically significant and insignificant non-observational terms, Carnap proposed a new solution in 1956. We will return to discuss it separately (see section 3.5 below); for now we need only note that these proposals were highly technical and applied only to axiomatized theories in formal languages. They too, however, found not much favor amongst philosophers. Yet whatever the problems that may or may not beset them, it would seem that far more general philosophical considerations contributed to the disappearance of the problem of the criterion of cognitive significance from most philosophical discussions since the early 1960s (other than as an example of mistaken positivism). These include the increasing opposition to the distinctions between analytic and synthetic statements and observational and theoretical terms as well as a general sense of dissatisfaction with Carnap’s approach to philosophy which began to seem both too formalist in execution and too deflationary in ambition. The entire philosophical program of which the search for a precise criterion of empirical significance was a part had begun to fall out of favor (and with it technical discussions about the criterion’s latest version).

The widely perceived collapse of the classical Viennese project to find in an empiricist meaning criterion a demarcation criterion against metaphysics—we reserve judgement about Carnap’s last two proposals here—can be interpreted in a variety of ways. It strongly suggests that cognitive significance cannot be reduced to what is directly observable, whether that be interpreted in phenomenalist or intersubjective, physicalist terms. In that important but somewhat subsidiary sense, the collapse spelt the failure of many of the reductivist projects typically ascribed to Viennese neopositivism (but see section 3.3 below). Beyond that, what actually had failed was the attempt to characterize for natural languages the class of cognitively significant propositions by recursive definitions in purely logical terms, either by relations of deducibility or translatability. What failed, it seemed, was the attempt to apply a general conception of philosophical analysis as purely formal, pursued also in other areas, to the problem of characterizing meaningfulness.

This general conception can be considered formalist in several senses. It was formalist, first, in demanding the analysis of the meaning of concepts and propositions in terms of logically necessary and sufficient conditions: it was precise and brooked no exceptions. And it was formalist, second, in demanding that such analyses be given solely in terms of the logical relations of these concepts and propositions to other concepts and propositions: it used the tools of formal logic. There is also a third sense that is, however, applicable predominantly to the philosophical project in Carnap’s hands, in that it was formalist in concentrating on the analysis of contested concepts via their explication in formal languages. (Discussion of its viability is deferred until section 3.5 and section 3.6 below.) The question arises whether all Vienna Circle philosophers concerned with empirical significance in natural language were equally affected, for the perceived collapse of the formalist project may leave as yet untouched other ways of sustaining the objection that metaphysics is, in some relevant sense, cognitively insignificant. (Such philosophers in turn would have to answer the charge, of course, that only the formalist project of showing metaphysics strictly meaningless rendered the Viennese anti-metaphysics distinctive.)

Even though the formalist project became identified with mainstream logical empiricism (consider its prominence in confirmation theory and in the theory of explanation), it was not universally subscribed to in the Vienna Circle itself. In different ways, neither Schlick nor Neurath or Frank adhered to it. As noted in the overview above, Schlick’s attempts to exhibit natural language meaning abjured efforts to characterize it in explicitly formal terms, even though he accepted the demand for necessary and sufficient conditions of significance. In the end, moreover, Schlick turned away from his colleagues’ search for a criterion of empirical significance. In allowing talk of life after death as meaningful (1936a), for the very reason that what speaks against it is only the empirical impossibility of verifying such talk, Schlick’s final criterion clearly left empiricist strictures behind.

By contrast, Neurath and Frank kept their focus on empirical significance. While they rarely discussed these matters explicitly, their writings give the impression that they chose to adopt (if not retain) a contextual, exemplar-based approach to characterizing the criterion of meaninglessness and so decided to forego the enumeration of necessary and sufficient conditions (on Frank see Uebel 2011a). Mach’s precept cited earlier is an example of such a pragmatic approach, as is Peirce’s criterion of significance (1878) endorsed by Quine (1969), which claims that significance resides in the discernible difference made if a proposition is true rather than false. Mach’s pragmatic approach had been championed already before verificationism proper by Neurath, Frank and Hahn who became, like Carnap, early opponents of conclusive verifiability. (Indeed, it is doubtful whether Neurath’s radical fallibilism, clearly expressed already in 1913, ever wavered.) This pragmatic understanding found expression in Neurath’s adoption (1935a, 1937) of K. Reach’s formulation of metaphysical statements as “isolated” ones, as statements that do not derive from and hold no consequences for those statements that we do accept on the basis of empirical evidence or for logical reasons. (Hempel’s dismissal, in 1951, of this pragmatic indicator presupposes the desiderata of the formalist project.) Finally, there is Frank’s suggestion (1963), coupled with his longstanding advice to combine logical empiricism with pragmatism, that Carnap’s purely logical critique of metaphysics in (1932a) was bound to remain ineffective as long as the actual use of metaphysics remained unexamined. It would be worth investigating whether—if the critique of the alleged reductionist ambitions of their philosophy could also be deflected (see section 3.3 below)—the impetus of the anti-verificationist critique can be absorbed by those with a pragmatic approach to the demarcation against metaphysics. Much as with Quine’s Peirce, such a criterion rules out as without interest for epistemic activity all concepts and propositions whose truth or falsity make no appreciable difference to the sets of concepts and propositions we do accept already.

An entirely different moral was drawn by Reichenbach (1938) and thinkers indebted to his probabilistic conception of meaning and his probabilistic version of verificationism, which escaped the criticisms surveyed above by vagaries of its own. Such theorists perceive the failure of the formalist model to accommodate the empirical significance of theoretical terms to stem from its so-called deductive chauvinism. In place of the exclusive reliance on the hypothetical-deductive method these theorists employ non-demonstrative analogical and causal inductive reasoning to ground theoretical statements empirically. Like Salmon, these theorists adopt a form of “non-linguistic empiricism” which they sharply differentiate from the empiricism of the Vienna Circle (Salmon 1985, 2003 and Parrini 1995 [1998]).

Now against both the pragmatic and the post-linguistic responses to the perceived failure of the attempt to provide a precise formal criterion of significance serious worries can be raised. Thus it must be asked whether without a precise way of determining when a statement “makes an appreciable difference”, criticism of metaphysics based on such a criterion may be not be considered as a biased dismissal rather than a demonstration of fact and so fall short of what is needed. Likewise in the case of the anti-deductivist response, it must be noted that a criterion based on analogical reasoning will only be as effective as the strength of the analogy which can always be criticized as inapt (and similarly for appeals to causal reasoning). The very point of exact philosophy in a scientific spirit—for many the very point of Vienna Circle philosophy itself—seems threatened by such maneuvres. Acquiescence in the perceived failure of the proposed criteria of significance thus comes with a price: if not that of abandoning Vienna Circle philosophy altogether, then at least that of formulating an alternative understanding to how some of its ambitions ought to be understood. (Recent reconstructive work on Neurath and Frank may be regarded in this light.)

A still different response—but one emblematic for the philosophical public at large—is that of another of Reichenbach’s former students, Putnam, who came to reject the anti-metaphysical project that powered verificationism in its entirety. Repeatedly in his later years, Putnam called for a refashioning of analytic philosophy as such, providing, as it were, a philosophically conservative counterweight to Rorty’s turn to postmodernism. Putnam’s reasons (the alleged self-refutation of the meaning criterion) are still different from those surveyed above and will be discussed when we return to reconsider the very point of the Circle’s campaign against metaphysics (see section 3.6 below).

3.2 The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction and the Relative A Priori

Whether the verificationist agenda was pursued in a formalist or pragmatic vein, however, all members shared the belief that meaningful statements divided exclusively into analytic and synthetic statements which, when asserted, were strictly matched with a priori and a posteriori reasoning for their support. The Vienna Circle wielded this pairing of epistemic and semantic notions as a weapon not only against the substantive a priori of the Schoolmen but also against Kant’s synthetic a priori. Moreover, their notion of analyticity comprized both logical and mathematical truths, thereby extending Wittgenstein’s understanding of the former as “tautological” in support of a broadly logicist program.

It is well known that this central component of the Vienna Circle’s arsenal, the analytic/synthetic distinction, came under sharp criticism from Quine in his “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” (1951a), less so that the criticism can only be sustained by extending objections of a type first published by Tarski. The argument is more complex, but here is a very rough sketch. So as to discard the analytic/synthetic distinction as an unwarranted dogma, Quine in “Two Dogmas” argued for the in-principle revisability of all knowledge claims and criticised the impossibility of defining analyticity in a non-circular fashion. The first argument tells against the apodictic a priori of old (the eternal conceptual verities), but, as we shall see, it is unclear whether it tells against at least some of the notions of the a priori held in the Vienna Circle. The second argument presupposes a commitment to extensionalism that likewise can be argued not to have been shared by all in the Circle. By contrast, Tarski had merely observed that, at a still more fundamental level, he knew of no basis for a sharp distinction between logical and non-logical terms. (For relevant primary source materials see also Quine 1936, 1951b, 1963; Carnap 1950a, 1955, 1963b, their correspondence and related previously unpublished lectures and writings in Creath 1990a, the memoir Quine 1991, and Tarski 1936; for an account of Carnap’s and Quine’s early interaction see Verhaegh 2023.)

The central role on the Vienna Circle’s side in this discussion falls to Carnap and the reorientation of philosophy he sought to effect in Logical Syntax (1934c [1937]). It was the notion of the merely relative and therefore non-apodictic a priori that deeply conditioned his notion of analyticity and allowed him to sidestep Quine’s fallibilist argument in a most instructive fashion. In doing so Carnap built on an idea behind Reichenbach’s early attempt (1920) to comprehend the general theory of relativity by means of the notion of a merely constitutive a priori. Now Schlick had objected to the residual idealism of this proposal (see Oberdan 2009) and preferred talk of conventions instead and Reichenbach soon followed him in this (see Coffa 1991: Ch. 10). Carnap too did not speak of the relative a priori as such (in returning to this terminology present discussions follow Friedman 1994), but his pluralism of logico-linguistic frameworks furnishes precisely that.

First consider Schlick as a contrast class. Schlick (1934) appeared to show little awareness of the language-relativity of the analytic/synthetic distinction and spoke of analytic truths as conceptual necessities that can be conclusively surveyed. This would suggest that Schlick rejected Kant’s apodictic synthetic a priori but not the apodicity of analytic statements. Clearly, if that were so, Quine’s argument from universal fallibilism would find a target here. Matters are not quite so clear-cut, however. Schlick had long accepted the doctrine of semantic conventionalism that the same facts could be captured by different conceptual systems (1915): this would suggest that his analytic truths were conventions that were framework-relative and as such necessary only in the very frameworks they helped to constitute. Yet Schlick also did not countenance the possibility of incommensurable conceptual frameworks: any fact was potentially expressible in any framework (1936b). As a result, Schlick did not accept the possibility that after the adoption of a new framework the analytic truths of the old one may be no longer assertable, that they would be discarded as no longer applicable even in translation, as it were. Herein lay a point that Quine’s argument could exploit: Schlick’s analytic truths remained unassailable despite their language-relativity.

Now Carnap, under the banner of the Principle of Tolerance (1934c [1937]: §17), abandoned the idea of the one universal logic which had informed Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein before him. Instead, he recognized a plurality of logics and languages whose consistency was an objective matter even though axioms and logical rules were fixed entirely by convention. Already due to this logical pluralism, the framework-relativity of analytic statements went deeper for Carnap than it did for Schlick. But Carnap also accepted the possibility of incommensurability between seemingly similar descriptive terms and between entire conceptual systems (1936a). Accepting the analytic truths of the framework of our best physical theory may thus be incompatible with accepting those of an earlier one, even if the same logic is employed in both. Carnapian analyticities do not therefore express propositions that we hold to be true unconditionally, but only propositions true relative to their own framework: they are no longer held to be potentially translatable across all frameworks. Quine’s charge of universal revisability (which itself needs some modification; see Putnam 1978) thus misses its mark against Carnap’s analyticities.

Concerning the criticism of the circular nature of the definition of analyticity, Carnap responded that it pertained primarily to the idea of analyticity in natural language whereas he was interested in “explications” as provided by the logic of science (or better, a logic of science, since there existed no unique logic of science for Carnap). Explications are reconstructions in a formal language of selected aspects of complex expressions that should not be expected to model the original in all respects (1950b: Ch.1). Moreover, Carnap held that explication of the notion of analyticity in formal languages yielded the kind of precision that rendered the complaint of circularity irrelevant: vague intuitions of meaning were no longer relied upon. Those propositions of a given language were analytic that followed from its axioms and, once the syntactic limitations of the Logical Syntax period had been left behind, from its definitions and meaning postulates, by application of its rules: no ambiguity obtained.

So it may appear that the notion of analyticity is easily delimitable in Carnap’s explicational approach: analytic propositions would be those that constitute a logico-linguistic framework (and their deductive consequences). But complications arose from the fact that, on Carnap’s understanding, not all propositions defining a logico-linguistic framework need be analytic ones (1934c [1937]: §51). It was possible for a framework to consist not only of logical rules, so-called L-rules whose entirety determines the notion of logical consequence, but also of P-rules, which represent presumed physical laws. So let analytic propositions be those framework propositions whose negations are self-contradictory. Here a problem arose once the syntactic constraints were dropped by Carnap so as to allow semantic reasoning: now the class of analytic propositions was widened to include not only logical and mathematical truths but also those obtained by substitution of semantically equivalent expressions introduced by so-called meaning postulates. How was one now to explicate the idea that there can be non-analytic framework propositions? For opponents like Quine, responding that the negations of non-analytic framework propositions do not contradict meaning postulates, was merely to dress up a presupposed notion of meaning in pseudo-formal garb: while it provided what looked like formal criteria, Carnap’s method did not leave the circle of intensional notions behind and so seemed to beg the question. Meaning postulates (Carnap 1952), after all, could only be identified by appearing on a list headed “meaning postulates” (as Quine added in reprints of 1951a).

Here one must note that in Logical Syntax, Carnap also modified the thesis of extensionality he had previously defended alongside Russell and Wittgenstein: now it merely claimed the possibility of purely extensional languages and no longer demanded that intensional languages be reduced to them (§67). Of course, the mere claim that the language of science can be extensional still proves troublesome enough, given that in such a language a distinction between laws and accidentally true universal propositions cannot be drawn (the notion of a counterfactual conditional, needed to distinguish the former, is an intensional one). Even so, this opening of Carnap’s towards intensionalism already at the height of his syntacticism—to say nothing of his explicit intensionalism in Meaning and Necessity (1947)—seems enough to thwart Quine’s second complaint in “Two Dogmas”. Carnap did not share Quine’s extensionalist agenda, so the need to break out of the circle of intensional notions once these were clearly defined in his formal languages did not apply. That theirs were in fact different empiricist research programmes was insufficiently stressed, it would appear, by Quine and Quinean critics of Carnap (as noted pointedly by Stein 1992; cf. Ricketts 1982, 2003, Creath 1991, 2004, Richardson 1997, Carus 2010).

To sustain his critique, Quine had to revive his and Tarski’s early doubts about Carnap’s methodological apparatus and dig even deeper. (Tarski also shared Quine’s misgivings about analyticity when they discussed these issues with Carnap at Harvard; see Mancosu 2005, Frost-Arnold 2013.) Their scepticism found its target in Carnap’s ingenious measures in Logical Syntax taken to preserve the thesis that mathematics is analytic from the ravages of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems. Gödel proved that every formal system strong enough to represent number theory contains a formula that is true but neither itself or its negation is provable in that system; such formulae—known since as Gödel sentences—are provable in a still stronger system which, however, also contains a formula of its own that is true but not provable in it (and neither is its negation). Commonly, Gödel’s proof is taken to have undermined the thesis of the analyticity of arithmetic. Carnap responded by stating that arithmetic demands an infinite sequence of ever richer languages and by declaring analytic statements to be provable by non-finite reasoning (1934/37: §60a-d. For discussions of this challenge and Carnap’s response, see Friedman 1988, 1999a, 2009, Goldfarb & Ricketts 1992, Richardson 1994, Awodey & Carus 2003, 2004). Carnap’s move looked like fitting the bill on purely technical grounds, but it is questionable whether such reasoning may still count as syntactic. Nowadays, it is computational effectiveness that is taken to distinguish purely formal from non-formal, material reasoning about something. Carnap’s move highlights the tension within Logical Syntax between formal and crypto-semantic reasoning: that the rigid syntacticism officially advertised there was at the same time undermined as its failings were being compensated—illegitimately so by official standards, e.g., by considering translatability a syntactic notion—points ahead to his acceptance of semantics in 1935, only one year after the publication of Logical Syntax and contrary to his disparagement of the notion of synthetic truth there. (For a discussion of these moves by Carnap, see Coffa 1976, Ricketts 1996, Goldfarb 1997, Creath 1996, 1999.) It is no criticism that Carnap’s reconstruction of arithmetic was not standard logicism, but that Carnap unduly stretched the idea of formal reasoning is. Was it saved by his shift to semantics?

Tarski (1936) granted the language-relativity of the reconstructed notion of analyticity in Logical Syntax. He also did not object that Carnap’s procedure of circumventing the problem which the Gödel sentences presented to the thesis of the analyticity of arithmetic was illegitimate. Tarski rather questioned whether there were “objective reasons” for the sharp distinction between logical and non-logical terms and he pointed out that Carnap’s distinction between the logical and the empirical was not a hard and fast one. Since noting the absence of a sharp distinction and arguing that no distinction can be drawn in principle are two quite different reactions, however, Tarski’s point on its own does not fully support the Quinean critique. Quine’s conclusion (1940: §60) that the notion of logical truth itself is “informal” rather reflects the moral that he drew from Tarski’s observation. It appears that what motivated him (after a nominalistic interlude in the 1940s) to develop his naturalistic alternative to Carnap’s conception of philosophy was his considered rejection of Carnap’s accommodation of the thesis that arithmetic is analytic to Gödel’s result.

Different strands of Quine’s criticism of the analytic/synthetic distinction must thus be distinguished. While some of Quine’s criticisms in “Two Dogmas” do not undermine all forms of the distinction that were defended in the Vienna Circle—Carnap’s reconstructions of the notion of analyticity did not express unconditionally necessary and unrevisable propositions—others gain in plausibility even against Carnap once it is recognized that the deepest ground of contestation lies elsewhere: not in the notion of analyticity widely understood but in that of logical truth narrowly understood. Read in this way, Quine can be seen to argue that the notion of L-consequence as explication of analytic truth—as opposed to P-consequence as non-analytic, mere framework entailments—traded not only on the idea of non-finitary notions of proof but also on a distinction of logical from descriptive expressions that itself was suspect. Saunders MacLane’s review (1938) of Carnap’s Logical Syntax had focussed on this and diagnosed its failure to give a formally correct definition of logical terms (namely in §50; see Awodey 2007, 2012). This failure was not repaired by Carnap in his semantical systems either, as he frankly admitted (1942: 59). In consequence, the class of logical terms is only enumerable with regard to individual languages or frameworks. What Quine criticized then was precisely the fact that Carnap could ground the distinction between logical and non-logical terms no deeper than by that: was the distinction of logical from empirical truth therefore not quite arbitrary? Now as it happens, logical truth or validity was found to be definable in model-theoretic terms (not available to Carnap in the early 40s) as “truth in all models” by Carnap’s close collaborator at Princeton, John Kemeny (1956), which Carnap then was happy to allude to (1963b: 979). It would seem therefore that neither Mac Lane’s or Quine’s criticism of Carnap’s inability to define logical terms in full generality must count as fatal (Creath 2017). Quine’s related claim that talk of semantical rules is meaningless may likewise be considered less than decisive in light of the fact that, as Carnap noted (1990: 430) that no general language-independent definition can be given of extensional truth either (but see Ebbs 2023).

Quine’s various arguments against the distinction between logical and empirical truth in (1963) have also been found to beg the question against Carnap and his way of conceiving of philosophy (see Creath 2003). But setting aside Quine’s objection does not relieve us of specifying still more precisely just what Carnap thought he was doing when he employed the distinction between analytic and synthetic propositions. To be sure, in (1955) he gave broadly behavioural criteria for when meaning ascriptions could be deemed accepted in linguistic practice, but he also noted that this was not a general requirement for the acceptability of explicatory discourse. It bears stressing again that explications did not seek to model natural language concepts in their tension-filled vividness, but to make proposals for future use and to extract and systematize certain aspects for constructive purposes. Thus Carnap clarified (1963b: §32) that he regarded the distinction between analytic and synthetic statements—just like the distinction between descriptive or factual and prescriptive or evaluative statements—not as descriptive of natural language practices, but as a constructive tool for logico-linguistic analysis and theory construction. It is difficult to overstress the significance of this stance of Carnap’s for the evaluation of his version of the philosophical project of the Vienna Circle. Carnap’s understanding of philosophy has been aptly described as the “science of possibilities” (Mormann 2000). Perhaps most notably, his conception of the relative a priori also finds application in history of science (see section 3.7 below).

As Carnap understood the analytic/synthetic distinction, it was a distinction drawn by a logician to enable greater theoretical systematicity in the reconstructive understanding of a given symbol system, typically a fragment of a historically developed one. That fully determinative objective criteria of what to regard as a logical and what as a non-logical term cannot be assumed to be pre-given does not then in and of itself invalidate the use of that distinction by Carnap. On the contrary, it has been convincingly argued that Carnap himself did not hold to a notion of what is a factual and what is a formal expression or statement that was independent of the specification of the language in question (Ricketts 1994). The ultimate ungroundedness of his basic semantic explicatory categories, this suggests instead, was a fact that his own theories fully recognized and consciously exploited. (Somewhat analogously, that we cannot define science independently of the practice of scientists of “our culture” was admitted by Neurath 1932a, Carnap 1932d and Hempel 1935, much to the exasperation of Zilsel 1932 and Schlick 1935a.) It remained open for Carnap then to declare his notion of analyticity to be only operationally defined for constructed languages and to let that notion be judged entirely in terms of its utility for meta-theoretical reflection. Just on that account, however, a last hurdle remains: finding a suitable criterion of significance for theoretical terms that allows the distinction between analytic and synthetic statements to be drawn in the non-observational, theoretical languages of science. (This was a problem ever since the non-eliminative reducibility of disposition terms had been accepted and one that still held for Carnap’s 1956b criterion; see section 3.5 below). Only if that can be done, it may be argued, can Carnap claim his formalist explicationist project to emerge unscathed from the criticisms of both Tarski and Quine.

None of the above considerations should lead one to deny, however, that one can find understandings of the term “analytic” by members of the Vienna Circle (like Schlick) that do fall victim to the criticisms of Quine more easily. Nor should one discount the fact that Carnap’s logic of science emerges as wilfully ill-equipped to deal with the problems that exercise the traditional metaphysics or epistemologies that deal in analyticities. (Of course, unlike his detractors, Carnap considered this to be a merit of his approach.) Lastly, it must be noted that Carnap’s intensionalist logic of science holds out the promise of practical utility only for the price of a pragmatic story that remains to be told. Of what nature are the practical considerations and decisions that, as Carnap so freely conceded (1950a), are called for when choosing logico-linguistic frameworks? (Such conventional choices do not respond to truth or falsity, but instead to whatever is taken to measure convenience.) That Carnap rightly may have considered such pragmatic questions beyond his own specific brief as a logician of science does not obviate the need for an answer to the question itself. (Carus 2007 argues that in this broadly pragmatic dimension lies the very point of Carnap’s explicationism.) On this issue, too, it would have been helpful if there had been more collaboration with Neurath and Frank, who were sympathetic to Carnap’s explication of analyticity but did not refer to it much in their own, more practice-oriented investigations (see section 3.6 below).

3.3 Reductionism and Foundationalism: Two Criticisms Partly Rebutted

Opposition to foundationalism is often motivated by opposition to the reductionism which it presupposes. Two forms of reductionism must be distinguished, phenomenalist and physicalist reductionism. Phenomenalism holds statements to be cognitively significant if they can be reduced to statements about one’s experience, be it outer (senses) or inner (introspection). Physicalism holds statements to be cognitively significant if they can be reduced (or, in a liberalised version, evidentially related) to statements about physical states of affairs. The Vienna Circle has been charged with both types of reductionism. On the one hand, its philosophy is remembered mostly in terms of the phenomenalism of the Aufbau, neglecting that already there the possibility of adopting a physicalist basis for a conceptual genealogy was indicated. On the other hand, the forms of physicalism that were favored already in the early 1930s by some leading members (Neurath 1931a, 1931b, Carnap 1932b, 1932c) seemed to threaten the elimination of the intentional idiom. Thus one must not only ask about the reductionism in the Aufbau but also consider just how reductivist in intent the physicalism was meant to be. Moreover, we must ask for the point of all the seeming reductionism: was it to place scientific knowledge on a secure foundation?

Considerations can begin with an early critique that has given rise in some quarters to a sharp distinction between Viennese logical positivism and German logical empiricism, with the former accused of reductionism and the latter praised for its anti-reductionism, a distinction which discounts the changing nature and variety of Vienna Circle doctrines. Reichenbach’s defense of empiricism (1938) turned on the replacement of the criterion of strict verifiability with one demanding only that the degree of probability of meaningful statements be determinable. This involved opposition also to demands for the eliminative reduction of non-observational to observational statements: both the methodological phenomenalism of the Aufbau and reductive physicalism were viewed as untenable and a correspondentist realism was advanced in their stead. Now it is true that of the members of the Vienna Circle only Feigl ever showed sympathies for scientific realism, but it is false that all opposition to it in the Circle depended on the naive semantics of early verificationism. (That even the Aufbau did not require strict verification is argued in Creath 1982 and, as we saw in section 3.1 above, by 1935 physicalist reductionism was abandoned too.) Again, of course, some Vienna Circle positions were liable to Reichenbach’s criticism.

Another misunderstanding to guard against is that the Vienna Circle’s ongoing concern with “foundational issues” and the “foundations of science” amount to foundationalism. (In the Vienna Circle’s days, foundationalism had it that the basic items of knowledge upon which all others depended were non-inferentially justified, concerned phenomenal states of affairs and were infallible; nowadays, foundationalists drop phenomenalism and infallibility.) Already the manifesto sought to make clear the Circle’s opposition when it claimed that

the work of ‘philosophic’ or ‘foundational’ investigations remains important in accord with the scientific world conception. For the logical clarification of scientific concepts, statements and methods liberates one from inhibiting prejudices. Logical and epistemological analysis does not wish to set barriers to scientific enquiry; on the contrary, analysis provides science with as complete a range of formal possibilities as is possible, from which to select what best fits each empirical finding (example: non-Euclidean geometries and the theory of relativity). (Carnap, Hahn, & Neurath 1929 [1973: 316])

This passage can be read as an early articulation of the project of a critical-constructivist meta-theory of science that abjures a special authority of its own beyond that stemming from the application of the methods of the empirical and formal sciences to science itself, but instead remains open to what the actual practice of these sciences demands. That Carnap later called his non-eliminative definitions of disposition terms “reduction sentences” indicates that it was enough for him to provide a basis for the applicability of these terms by merely sufficient but not necessary conditions. Likewise, Carnap’s later proposal to conceive of theoretical terms as defined by implicit definition in a non-interpreted language, only selected terms of which were linked via non-eliminative reductive chain to the observational language (see section 3.4 below), suggests that what concerned him primarily was the capture of indicator relations to sustain in principle testability of statements containing the terms in question. This is best understood as an attempt to preserve the empirical applicability of languages constructed for high-level theory, but not as reductivism with regard to some foundational given.

So can Vienna Circle philosophy be absolved of foundationalism? As noted, it is the Aufbau (and echoes of it in the manifesto) that invites one version of this charge, but one must distinguish between the strategy of reductionism and the ambition of foundationalism. Concerning the Aufbau it has been argued convincingly that its strategy of reconstructing empirical knowledge from the perspective of methodological solipsism (phenomenalism without its ontological commitments and some of its epistemological ambitions) was owed not to foundationalist aims but to the ease by which this perspective seemed to allow the demonstration of the interlocking and structural nature of our system of empirical concepts, a system that exhibited unity and afforded objectivity, which was Carnap’s main concern. (See Friedman’s path-breaking 1987 and 1992, and Richardson 1990, 1998, Pincock 2002, 2005. For the wide variety of influences on the Aufbau more generally, see Damböck 2016.) That the Aufbau fails when it is read as a foundationalist project, as it was by Quine (1951a) who pointed out that no eliminative definition of the relation ‘is at’ was provided (required for locating objects of consciousness in physical space) and that further failures of reduction were detected by Richardson (1998: Ch.3), may give additional grounds for questioning the Aufbau’s supposed foundationalism.

Yet it is hard to deny categorically that Carnap ever harbored foundationalist ambitions. Not only did Carnap himself, albeit in retrospect, once locate his Aufbau very close to foundationalism (1963a: 57), more indicative is a passage outlining his epistemological ideas in (1930: §8) that led Uebel (2007: Ch.6) to claim that around 1929/30 Carnap was motivated by foundationalist concerns and reinterpreted the Aufbau along these lines. (It was around the same time that Wittgenstein entertained a psychologistic reinterpretation of his own Tractatus that was reported back to the Circle by Waismann and also then that he, as noted above, bewitched the Circle with strict verificationism.) However, this brief aberration of Carnap’s must not be taken to tell against the persuasiveness of the new reading of the Aufbau as concerned with structural objectivity or indeed against the overriding importance of the epistemologies developed from 1930 onwards on the physicalist wing of the Circle. For to correct Carnap’s aberration was the task that Neurath then shouldered in the Circle’s protocol-sentence debate about the content, form and status of the evidence statements of science.

Interestingly, it was yet another failure of reduction that appears to have prompted Carnap to abandon methodological solipsism for use in his reconstructions of the language of science (though not the logical investigation of phenomenal languages for their own sake, as noted in his 1961a). Throughout 1931 and much of 1932 Carnap defended his approach even though Neurath (1931b, 1932a) argued that such a type of rational reconstruction traded on objectionable counterfactual presuppositions (methodological solipsism did not provide a correct description of the reasoning involved in cognitive commerce with the world around us). Only in “On Protocol Sentences” (which first applied the Principle of Tolerance without much fanfare before it was officially introduced in Logical Syntax) Carnap conceded that it was more “convenient” to reconstruct the language of science on a physicalistic than a phenomenalist basis, but allowed for both (1932e). A few years later in “Testability and Meaning”, however, Carnap concluded that “a language about conscious events as non-spatial events … is a purely subjective one, suitable for soliloquy only” and from then on abandoned the methodologically solipsist approach for practical purposes (1936/37: 10; compare 1963b: 869). Evidently, with dispositional predicates uneliminable in favor of observational ones and a “re-translation” of theoretical discourse into pre-theoretical terms no longer possible (1936/37: 464), the additional effort it would take to “reduce” theoretical assertions beyond the physicalist “thing-language” still further to the phenomenal level was not only inconvenient but pointless. The new logic of science must not be as “entangled with psychological questions” (1934c [1937]: §72) as his earlier epistemology still had been, Carnap now resolved.

As Carnap also testified, “Neurath had always rejected the alleged rock bottom of knowledge” (1963a: 57). A good example of his position is provided by his complex conception of the form of protocol statements (1932b). Neurath proposed to explicate the concept of observational evidence in terms that expressly reflected debts to empirical assumptions which called for theoretical elaboration in turn. For unlike the logician of science Carnap, who left it to psychology and brain science to determine more precisely what the class observational predicates were that could feature in protocol statements (1936/37: 454), the empirically oriented meta-theoretician of science Neurath was concerned to encompass and comprehend the practical complexities of reliance on scientific testimony: the different clauses (embeddings) of his proposed protocol statements stand for conditions on the acceptance of such testimony (see Uebel 2009, Bentley 2022). In addition, the details of Neurath’s theory of protocol statements also make clear that his understanding of physicalism did not entail the eliminative reduction of the intentional idiom but, like Carnap (1932c), merely sought its integration into empiricist discourse.

Given these different emphases of their respective physicalisms, mention must also be made of the significant differences between Carnap’s and Neurath’s conceptions of unified science: where the formalist Carnap once preferred a hierarchical ordering of finitely axiomatized theoretical languages that allowed at least partial cross-language definitions and derivations—these requirements were liberalized in (1936b), (1936/37) (1938)—the pragmatist Neurath demanded from the start only the interconnectability of predictions made in the different individual sciences (1935a), (1936a), (1944). (Meteorology, botany and sociology must be combinable to predict the consequences of a forest fire, say, even though each may have its own autonomous theoretical vocabulary.) Here too it must be remembered that, unlike Carnap, Neurath only rarely addressed issues in the formal logic of science but mainly concerned himself with the partly contextually fixed pragmatics of science. (One exception is his 1935b, a coda to his previous contributions to the socialist calculation debate with Ludwig von Mises and others.) At times the priorities set by Neurath for the pragmatics of science seemed to conflict with those of Carnap’s logic of science. (These tensions were palpable in the grand publication project undertaken by Carnap and Neurath in conjunction with Morris, the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science; see Reisch 2003.) That said, however, note that Carnap’s initially more hierarchical approach to the unity of science also does not support the attribution of foundationalist ambitions. (The ontological micro-reductions introduced by Oppenheim & Putnam 1958 were never part of his conception.)

But for a brief lapse around 1929/30 and perhaps in some pre-Vienna years, then, Carnap fully represents the position of Vienna Circle anti-foundationalism. In this he joined Neurath whose long-standing anti-foundationalism is evident from his famous simile, first used in 1913, that likens scientists to sailors who have to repair their boat without ever being able to pull into dry dock (1932). Their positions contrasted at least prima facie with that of Schlick (1934) who explicitly defended the idea of foundations in the Circle’s protocol-sentence debate. Even Schlick conceded, however, that all scientific statements were fallible ones, so his position on foundationalism was by no means the traditional one. The point of his “foundations” remained less than wholly clear and different interpretation of it have been put forward (e.g., Oberdan 1998, Uebel 1996, 2020b). (On the protocol sentence debate as a whole, which included not only the discussions between Carnap and Neurath but also debates between the physicalists and Schlick and other occasional participants, see the differently centered accounts of Uebel 1992, 2007, Oberdan 1993, Cirera 1990 [1994].) While all in the Circle thus recognized as futile the attempt to restore certainty to scientific knowledge claims, not all members embraced positions that rejected foundationalism tout court. Clearly, however, attributing foundationalist ambitions to the Circle as a whole constitutes a total misunderstanding of its internal dynamics and historical development, if it does not bespeak wilfull ignorance. At most, a vaguely foundationalist faction around Schlick can be distinguished from the so-called left wing whose members pioneered anti-foundationalism with regard to both the empirical and formal sciences.

3.4 Scientific Theories, Theoretical Terms and the Problem of Realism

Yet even if it be conceded that the members of the Vienna Circle did not harbour undue reductionist-foundationalist ambitions, the question remains open whether they were able to deal with the complexities of scientific theory building.

Here the prominent role of Schlick must be mentioned, whose General Theory of Knowledge was the first publication by (future) members of the Vienna Circle to follow Hilbert’s work on the axiomatic method and introduce the so-called two-languages model of scientific theories (1918, enhanced in second edition 1925: §11). According to Schlick, scientific theories comprised an observational part formulated with observational predicates as customarily interpreted, in which observations and experiential laws were stated, and a theoretical part which consisted of theoretical laws (axioms) the terms of which were merely implicitly defined, namely, in terms of the roles they played in the laws in which they figured. Both parts were connected in virtue of a not further specified correlation between some of their terms. (A similar precursor was the idea contained in a remark by Frank [1910] pointing out the applicability of Hilbert’s method of implicit definition to the reconstruction empirical scientific theories as conceived by the French conventionalists Rey and Duhem.) In the second half of the 1920s this model, involving separate conceptual systems, was temporarily set aside in favor of a more streamlined conception of scientific theories along the reductive lines as suggested by the Aufbau, but its broad outline was returned to by Carnap when it was noted that not even the so-called reduction sentences provided a bridge to all theoretical terms (1939: §24); further elaborated it became standard in logical empiricism.

According to Carnap (see esp. his 1956b: 47, also Feigl 1970), scientific theories are formalised as axiomatized sets of sentences in first- or higher-order logic which contain, besides logical and mathematical terms, descriptive terms referring to entities, properties and processes in the theory’s intended domain. Some selected theoretical terms are connected to observational terms that refer to observable entities, properties and processes via so-called correspondence rules which contain both types of terms. (Reduction sentences and their chains count as correspondence rules.) Only the observational terms are given a full semantic interpretation. The theoretical terms are defined only implicitly through their inferential role by the axioms of the theory; the correspondence rules link the theory as a whole to observable reality, but not every theoretical term individually. A theory is viewed as an uninterpreted calculus that receives only a “partial interpretation” by the correspondence rules which guarantee its applicability through observable consequences but do not generally assign references to its terms.

Note that this conception of scientific theories was put forward as a rational reconstruction, not a description of scientific practice; nevertheless, as “the received view” (Putnam 1962) it received much criticism both as formally inadequate and methodologically misguided. (See Suppe 1977 for a systematic overview of the standard formal charges against logical empiricism’s misleadingly labelled “syntactic view” of theories, Mormann 2007a for a partial defense, and Lutz 2012, 2014 for the refutation of common misunderstandings and arguments against the supposed superiority of the equally mislabelled “semantic view” of theories.) Nowadays philosophers prefer a more practice-oriented view that focusses less on the linguistic structure of theories but on their “models” which themselves can be understood in a great variety of ways (see, e.g., Morgan & Morrison 1999 or Frigg 2022).

Even granted the partial interpretation model in outline (more criticism in section 3.7), questions arise both concerning its observational base as well as its theoretical superstructure. We already discussed one aspect of the former, the issue of protocols, in the previous section, so let’s turn to the latter topic. Talk of correspondence rules only masks the problem that is raised by theoretical terms. One of the pressing issues concerns their so-called surplus meaning over and above their observational consequences. This issue is closely related to the problem of scientific realism: are there truth-evaluable matters of fact for scientific theories beyond their empirical, observational adequacy? Even though the moniker “neo-positivism” would seem to prescribe an easy answer as to what the Vienna Circle’s position was, it must be noted that just as there is no consensus discernible today there was none in the Circle beyond certain basics that left the matter undecided.

All in the Vienna Circle followed Carnap’s judgement in Pseudoproblems of Philosophy (1928b) and Schlick’s contention in his response to Planck’s renewal of anti-Machian polemics (1932) that questions like that of the reality of the external world were not well-formed ones but only constituted pseudo-questions. While this left the observables of empirical reality clearly in place, theoretical entities remained problematical: were they really only computational fictions introduced for the ease with which they allowed complex predictive reasoning, as Frank (1932) held? This hardly seems to do justice to the role of theoretical terms over and above their computational utility: theories employing them seem to tell us about non-observable features of the world. This indeed was Feigl’s complaint (1950) in what must count as the first of very few forays into “semantical realism” (scientific realism by another word) by a former member of the Vienna Circle—and one that was quickly opposed by Frank’s instrumentalist rejoinder (1950). Carnap sought to remain aloof on this as on other ontological questions. So while in the heyday of the Vienna Circle itself the issue had not yet come into clear focus, by mid-century one could distinguish amongst its surviving members both realists (Feigl) and anti-realists (Frank) as well as ontological deflationists (Carnap).

Carnap’s general recipe for avoiding undue commitments (while pursuing his investigations of various language forms, including the intensional ones Quine frowned upon) was given in terms of the distinction between so-called internal and external questions (1950a). Internal questions and their answers presuppose the adoption of a logico-linguistic framework. Given one such, we can state the facts in accordance with what that framework allows us to say. Given any of the languages of arithmetic, say, we can state as particular arithmetical facts whatever we can prove in them; to say that there are numbers is to express the fact that numbers are a recognized category of objects in that framework (irrespective of whether they are logically derived from a still more basic category). Whether certain special types of numbers exist depends on the expressive power of the framework at hand and on whether the relevant facts can be proven. Analogous considerations apply to the existence of physical things (the external world) given the logico-linguistic frameworks of everyday discourse and empirical science. (The near-tautologous nature of these categorical claims in Carnap’s hands echoes his earlier diagnosis of metaphysical claims as pseudo-statements; see also 1934c [1937]: Part V.A.) Unlike such internal questions, however, external questions ask whether numbers or electrons “really exist” irrespective of any framework. External questions were ruled out as illegitimate and meaningless for in the absence of a framework there is no way of making determinate sense of them. The only way in which sense could be given to them was to read them as pragmatic questions concerned with the utility of talk about numbers or electrons, of adopting certain frameworks. Meaningful existence claims respond to internal questions and must be regarded as mediated by the available conceptual tools of inquiry. Logicians of science are in no position to double-guess scientists by appeals to superior intuition. (Needless to say, Quine 1951b opposed the internal/external distinction as much as his 1951a opposed the analytic/synthetic distinction.)

Matters came to a head with the discovery of a proof (see Craig 1956) that the theoretical terms of a scientific theory are dispensable in the sense of it being possible to devise a functionally equivalent theory that does not make use of them. Did this not rob theoretical terms of their distinctive role and so support instrumentalism? The negative answer was twofold. As regards defending their utility, Carnap (1963b: §24) agreed with Hempel (1958) that in practice theoretical terms were indispensable in facilitating inductive relations between observational data. As regards the defense of their cognitive legitimacy, Carnap held that this demanded determining what he called their “experiential import”, namely, determining what specifically their empirical significance consisted in. It was for this purpose that Carnap came to employ Ramsey’s method of regimenting theoretical terms. Nowadays this so-called ramseyfication is often discussed as a means for expressing a position of “structural realism”, a position midway between fully-blown scientific realism and anti-realism and so sometimes thought to be of interest to Carnap. Carnap’s own concern with ramseyfication throws into relief not only the question of the viability of one of the Vienna Circle’s most forward-looking stances in the debate about theoretical terms—the intention to avoid both realism and anti-realism—but also several other issues that bear on the question of which, if any, forms of Vienna Circle philosophy remain viable.

3.5 Carnap’s Later Meaning Criterion and the Problem of Ramseyfication

Note that the issue of realism vis-à-vis theoretical terms is closely related to two other issues central to the development of Vienna Circle philosophy: Carnap’s further attempts to develop a criterion of empiricist significance for the terms of the theoretical languages of science and his attempts to defend the distinction between synthetic and analytic statements with regard to such theoretical languages.

In 1956 Carnap introduced a new criterion of meaningfulness specifically for theoretical terms (1956b). This criterion was explicitly theory-relative. Roughly, Carnap first defined the concept of the “relative significance” of a theoretical term. A term is relatively significant if and only if there exists a statement in the theoretical language that contains it as the only non-logical term and from which, in conjunction with another theoretical statement and the sets of theoretical postulates and correspondence rules, an observational statement is derivable that is not derivable from that other theoretical statement and the sets of theoretical postulates and correspondence rules alone. Then Carnap defined the “significance” of a theoretical term by its belonging to a sequence of such terms such that each is relatively significant to the class of those terms that precede it in the sequence. Now those theoretical statements were legitimate and cognitively significant that were well-formed and whose descriptive constants were significant the sense just specified. It is clear that by the stepwise introduction of theoretical terms as specified, Carnap sought to avoid the deleterious situations that rendered Ayer’s criterion false (and his own in 1928b). Nevertheless, this proposal too was subjected to criticism (e.g., Rozeboom 1960; D. Kaplan 1975a). A common impression amongst philosophers appears to be that this criterion failed as well, but this judgement is by no means universally shared (for the majority view see Glymour 1980, for a contrary assessment see Sarkar 2001). Thus it has been argued that subject to some further refinements, Carnap’s proposal can be made to work (see for discussion Creath 1976, Justus 2014, 2022, Lutz 2017)—as long as the distinction between observational and theoretical terms can be sustained. (In light of the objections to the latter distinction one wants to add: or by a dichotomy of terms functionally equivalent to it.)

Carnap’s own position on his 1956 criterion appears somewhat ambiguous. While he is reported to have accepted one set of criticisms (D. Kaplan 1975b), he also asserted even after they had been put to him that he thought his criterion remained adequate (1963b: §24b). Yet Carnap there also advised investigation of whether still another, then entirely new approach to theoretical terms that he was developing would allow for an improved criterion of significance for them. Still, when Carnap offered “the Ramsey method” as a method of characterizing the “empirical meaning of theoretical terms” it was not their empirical meaningfulness as such but the specific empirical import of theoretical terms that he investigated (1966: Ch. 26). What prompted him to undertake his investigations of ramseyfications was not dissatisfaction with his 1956 proposal as a criterion of significance for theoretical terms, but the fact that it still proved impossible with this model to draw the distinction between synthetic and analytic statements in the theoretical language. The reason for this was that the postulates for the theoretical language also specify factual relations between phenomena that fall under the concepts that are implicitly defined by them. (As noted, a similar problem already had plagued Carnap’s analyses of disposition terms ever since he allowed for non-eliminative reduction chains.)

Carnap’s attempt to address this problem by ramseyfication was published in several places from 1958 onwards. (See Carnap 1958, 1963b: §24C-D and the popular exposition 1966: Chs. 26 and 28; compare Ramsey 1929 and see Psillos 1999: Ch.3. This proposal and a variant of it (1961b) were both presented in his 1959 Santa Barbara lecture (published in Psillos 2000a); as it happened, Kaplan presented his criticism (1975a) of Carnap’s 1956 criterion at the same conference.) With ramseyfication Carnap adverted again to entire theories as the unit of assessment. Ramseyfication consists in the replacement of the theoretical terms of a finitely axiomatized theory by bound higher-order variables. This involves combining all the theoretical postulates which define theoretical terms (call this conjunction T) and correspondence rules of a theory which link some of these theoretical terms with observational ones (call this C) in one long sentence (call this TC) and then replacing all the theoretical predicates that occur in it by bound higher-order variables (call this RTC). This is the so-called Ramsey-sentence of the entire theory; in it no theoretical terms appear, but it possesses the same explanatory and predictive power as the original theory: it has the same observational consequences. However, Carnap stressed that the Ramsey sentence cannot be said to be expressed in a “simple” but only an “extended” observational language, for due to its higher-order quantificational apparatus it includes “an advanced complicated logic embracing virtually the whole of mathematics” (1966, [1996, 253]).

To distinguish between analytic and synthetic statements in the theoretical language Carnap made the following proposal. Let the Ramsey sentence of the conjunction of all theoretical postulates and the conjunction of all correspondence rules of that theory be considered as expressing the entire factual, synthetic content of a scientific theory and its terms. By contrast, the statement RTCTC expressed the purely analytic component of the theory, its “A-postulate” (or so-called Carnap sentence). This

A-postulate states that if entities exist (referred to by the existential quantifiers of the Ramsey sentence) that are of a kind bound together by all the relations expressed in the theoretical postulates of the theory and that are related to observational entities by all the relations specified by the correspondence postulates of the theory, then the theory itself is true.

Or differently put, the A-postulate “says only that if the world is this way, then the theoretical terms must be understood as satisfying the theory” (1966 [1996: 271]). With RTCTC expressing a meaning postulate Carnap claimed to have separated the analytic and synthetic components of a scientific theory.

Carnap’s adoption of the Ramsey method met mainly with criticism (Psillos 1999: ch.3, 2000b; Demopoulos 2003, 2017), even though ramseyfications continue to be discussed as a method of characterizing theoretical terms in a realist vein (albeit with conditions not yet introduced by Carnap, as in Lewis 1970, Papineau 1996). With Carnap’s ramseyfications, however, we do not get the answer that what exists is the structure that the ramseyfication at hand identifies. Given the absence of a clause requiring unique realizability, ramseyfications counseled modesty: the structure that is identified remains indeterminate to just that degree to which theoretical terms remain incompletely interpreted (Carnap 1961b). To this we must add that for Carnap ramseyfications of theoretical terms could support only internal existence claims: he explicitly reaffirmed his confidence in the distinction between internal and external question to defuse the realism/anti-realism issue (1966 [1996: 256]). This strongly suggests that with these proposals Carnap did not intend to deviate from his deflationist approach to ontology.

What must be considered, however, is that Carnap’s proposal to reconstruct the contribution of theoretical terms by ramseyfication falls foul of arguments deriving from M.H.A. Newman’s objection to Russell’s structuralism in Analysis of Matter (see Demopoulos & Friedman 1985). This objection says that once they are empirically adequate, ramseyfied theories are trivially true, given the nature of their reconstruction of original theories. Russell held that “nothing but the structure of the external world is known”. But if nothing is known about the generating relation that produces the structure, then the claim that there exists such a structure is vacuous, Newman claimed. “Any collection of things can be organised so as to have the structure W, provided there are the right number of them.” (Newman 1928: 144) To see how this so-called cardinality constraint applies to ramseyfications of theories, note that in Carnap’s hands, the non-observational part of reconstructed theories, their theoretical entities, were represented by “purely logico-mathematical entities, e.g. natural numbers, classes of such, classes of classes, etc.” For him the Ramsey sentence asserted that “observable events in the world are such that there are numbers, classes of such, etc., which are correlated with events in a prescribed way and which have among themselves certain relations”, this being “clearly a factual statement about the world” (Carnap 1963b: 963). Carnap here had mathematical physics in mind where space-time points are represented by quadruples of real numbers and physical properties like electrical charge-density or mass-density are represented as functions of such quadruples of real numbers.

The problem that arises from this for Carnap is not the failure to single out the intended interpretation of the theory: as noted, Carnap clearly thought it an advantage of the method that it remained suitably indeterminate. The problem is rather that, subject to its empirical adequacy, the truth conditions of the Ramsey-sentences are fulfilled trivially on logico-mathematical grounds alone. As he stated, Ramsey-sentences demand that there be a structure of entities that is correlated with observable events in the way described. Yet given the amount of mathematics that went into the ramseyfied theory—“virtually the whole of mathematics”—some such structure as demanded by the Ramsey-sentence is bound to be found among those entities presupposed by its representational apparatus. (Here the cardinality constraint is no constraint at all.) That any theory is trivially true for purely formal reasons (as long as it is empirically adequate) therefore is held against Carnap’s proposal to use Ramsey sentences as reconstructions of the synthetic content of the theoretical part of empirical scientific theories. Given that with ramseyfications “the truth of physical theory reduces to the truth of its observational consequences” (Demopoulos & Friedman 1985: 635), this is a problem for Carnap’s project on its own terms: any surplus empirical meaning of theoretical terms that Carnap sought to capture simply evaporates (Demopoulos 2003).

This result casts its shadow over Carnap’s last treatment of theoretical terms and threatens further consequences. If the reconstruction of empirical theories by ramseyfication in Carnap’s fashion is unacceptable and no justice has been done to the import of theoretical terms, then one must ask whether the analytic components of a theoretical language have been correctly identified. If they have not, then the meta-theoretical utility of the synthetic/analytic distinction is once again be called into question. One is lead to wonder whether Carnap would not be well advised to return to his 1956 position, which allowed for a criterion of empirical significance for theoretical terms but not for the full analytic/synthetic distinction to be sustained with regard to the theoretical language. (According to Carnap’s fall-back position before he hit upon ramseyfication, it was thought possible to distinguish narrow logical truth from factual truth in the theoretical language: 1966: Ch. 28.) Yet it is difficult to silence the suspicion that an analytic/synthetic distinction that applies only to observational languages is not what the debate between Carnap and Quine was all about. Attempts have thus been undertaken to provide interpretations of Carnap’s ramseyfications to contain or mitigate the effects of the Newman objection (Friedman 2008, 2011; Uebel 2011b; Creath 2012a). What has become clear, in any case, is that much is at stake for the standard logical empiricist model of scientific theories (see also end of section 3.7 below).

3.6 The Status of the Criterion of Significance and the Point of the Project of Explication

We are now in a position to return to a final criticism of the search for a criterion of empiricist significance. Much has been made of the very status of the criterion itself (however it may be put in the end): was it empirically testable? It is common to claim that it is not and therefore to consign it to insignificance in turn (e.g., Putnam 1981a, 1981b). The question arises whether this is to overlook the fact that the criterion of significance was put forward not as an empirical claim but as a meta-theoretical proposal for how to delimit empiricist languages from non-empiricist ones (see Carnap 1936/37: §27). Again, pursuing this line of inquiry is not to deny that the meaning criterion may have been understood by some members of the Circle in such a way that it became liable to charges of self-refutation. (In that case the criterion would share its contradictory status with Wittgenstein’s Tractarian “elucidations” to which it may have been likened. The legitimacy of these elucidations was at issue already in the debates that divided the Circle in the early 1930s; see, e.g., Neurath 1931a) What will be considered here is primarily the view of Carnap, who in the spirit of the Principle of Tolerance put his philosophical theses in the form of “proposals” for alternative language forms, but how the pragmatist alternative fares will also be considered. Finally, we will consider where this does leave neopositivist anti-metaphysics.

For Carnap, the empiricist criterion of significance was an analytic principle, but in a very special sense. As a convention, the criterion had the standing of an analytic statement, but it was not a formally specifiable framework principle of the language Ln to which it pertained. Properly formulated, it was a semantic principle concerning Ln that was statable only in its meta-language Ln+1. To argue that the criterion itself is meaningless because it has no standing in Ln is to commit a category mistake, for meta-linguistic assertions need not have counterparts in their object languages (Goldfarb 1997, Creath 2004, Richardson 2004). Nor would it be correct to claim that the criterion hides circular reasoning, allegedly because its rejection of the meaningless depends on an unquestioned notion of experiential fact as self-explanatory (when such fact is still to be constituted). Importantly, Carnap’s language constructor does not start with fixed notions of what is empirical (rather than formal) or what is given (rather than assumed or inferred), but from the beginning allows a plurality of perspectives on these distinctions (Ricketts 1994). Carnap’s empiricist criterion of significance is precisely this: an explication, a proposal for how empiricists may wish to speak. It is not an explanation of how meaning arises from what is not meaningful in itself. Unlike theorists who wish to explain how meaning itself is constituted, explicationists can remain untroubled by the regress of formal semantics with Tarskian strictures. For them, the lack of formal closure (the incompleteness of arithmetic and the inapplicability of the truth predicate to its own language) only betokens the fact that our very own home languages cannot ever be fully explicated.

It may be thought that such considerations have become pointless, given the troubles that attempts to provide a formal criterion of significance ran into, but revisions of Carnap’s 1956 criterion for constructed languages remain under discussion (as we saw). Moreover, there also remains the informal, pragmatic approach that can be applied even more widely. Thus it is not without importance to see that pragmatic principles delineating empirical significance (like Mach’s or Quine’s Peircean insight) are not ruled out from the start either. The reason for this is different however. For pragmatists, the anti-metaphysical demarcation criterion is not strictly speaking a meaning criterion. The pragmatic criterion of significance is expressly epistemic, not semantic: it speaks of relevance with regard to an established cognitive practice, not in-principle truth-evaluability. This criterion is most easily expressed as a conditional norm, alongside other methodological maxims. (If you want your reasoning to be responsible to evidence, then avoid statements that experience can neither confirm or disconfirm, however indirectly.) So the suggestion that the criterion of empirical significance can be regarded as a proposal for how to treat the language of science cannot be brushed aside but for the persistent neglect of the philosophical projects of Carnap or the non-formalist left Vienna Circle.

Still, some readers may wonder whether in the course of responding to the various counter-criticisms, the Vienna Circle’s position has not shifted considerably. This indeed is true: the attempt to show metaphysics strictly meaningless once and for all did not succeed. For even if revisions of Carnap’s 1956 criterion and the pragmatic approach work, they do not achieve that: Carnap’s criterion only works for constructed languages and the pragmatic one only works case by case. But it can be argued that while this debilitates the Vienna Circle’s most notorious claim (if understood without qualifications), it does not debilitate their entire program. That was, we recall, to defend Enlightenment reason and to counter the abuse of possibly empty but certainly ill-understood deep-sounding language in science and in public life. Their program was, to put it somewhat anachronistically, to promote epistemic empowerment. This program would have been helped by an across-the-board criterion to show metaphysics meaningless, but it can also proceed in its absence.

But now the suspicion may be that if all that is meant to be excluded is speculative reason without due regard to empirical and logico-linguistic evidence, the program’s success appears too easy. Few contemporary philosophers would confess to such reckless practices. Still, even the rejection of speculative reason is by no means uncontroversial, as shown by the unresolved status of the appeal to intuitions that characterizes much of contemporary analytical metaphysics and epistemology. Moreover, much depends on what’s considered to be “due regard”: is merely bad science “metaphysics”? Or only appeals to the supernatural? And what about de re necessities? The promotion of anti-metaphysics may be applauded in principle as an exercise in intellectual hygiene, the objection goes, but in practice it excludes either too much or too little: it either cripples our understanding of theoretical science or normalizes away the Vienna Circle’s most notorious claim.

In response it is helpful to consider the conception of metaphysics that can be seen to be motivating much of the Circle’s ethical non-cognitivism. What did Carnap (1935) and Neurath (1931c) dismiss when they dismissed normative ethics as metaphysical and cognitively meaningless? One may concede that due to the brusque way in which they put their broadly Humean point, they opened themselves up to significant criticism, but it is very important to see also what they did not do. Most notably, they did not dismiss as meaningless all concern with how to live. Conditional prescriptions remained straight-forwardly truth-evaluable in instrumental terms and so cognitively meaningful. In addition, their own active engagement for Enlightenment values in public life showed that they took these matters very seriously themselves. (In fact, their engagement as public intellectuals compares strikingly with that of most contemporary philosophers of science.) But neither did they fall victim to the naturalistic fallacy nor were they simply inconsistent. In the determination of basic values they rather saw acts of personal self-definition, but, characteristically, Carnap showed a more individualistic and Neurath a more collectively oriented approach to the matter. What needs to be borne in mind, then, is the meaning that they attached to the epithet “metaphysical” in this and other areas: the arrogation of unique and fully determined objective insight into matters beyond scientific reason. It was in the ambition of providing such unconditional prescriptions that they saw philosophical ethics being the heir of theology. (Compare Carnap 1935 and 1963b: §32 and Neurath 1932a and 1944: §19.) Needless to say, it remains contentious to claim those types of philosophical ethics to be cognitively meaningless that seek to derive determinate sets of codes from some indisputable principle or other. But the ongoing discussion of non-cognitivism and its persistent defense in analytical ethics as “expressivism” suggest that, understood as outlined, the Circle’s non-cognitivism was by no means absurd or contradictory.

It may be noted here that a newly discovered fragment of Carnap’s writing (2017) has given fresh impetus to explorations of the model of ethical reasoning in terms of pure and applied optatives that Carnap outlined (1963b: §32) in response to A. Kaplan’s criticism (1963) of his earlier position. (Remember that conditional value statements had never been ruled cognitively meaningless.) What emerges is that Carnap was prepared to integrate ethical desiderata among non-ethical ones within the network of means and ends that decision theory as a normative theory of rational action seeks to systematize and regiment. Moral reasoning was assimilated to practical instrumental reasoning and no longer suffered from a wholesale deficit of significance—albeit at the cost of not being able to exclude certain values as basic and consider the respective pure optatives inadmissible on the ground their being beyond the pale morally (see Carus 2017). Carnap may reasonably respond here that as a theorist of science he is not required to account for normative ethics beyond providing a framework for understanding its undeniable role in a generic theory of human behavior. What was rightly objected against his earlier position was that it made such understanding impossible.

Whatever the details, their non-cognitivism supports the idea that the left wing’s anti-metaphysics was primarily deflationist. They opposed all claims to have a categorically deeper insight into reality than either empirical or formal science, such that philosophy would stand in judgement of these sciences as to their reality content or that mere science would stand in need of philosophical interpretations. (Concerned with practical problems, they likewise opposed philosophical claims to stand above the contestations of mere mortals.) Importantly, such deflationism need not remain general and vague, but can be given precise content. For instance, it has been argued (Carus 1999) that Carnap was correct to understand Tarski’s theory of truth not as a traditional correspondence theory such that truth consisted in some kind of agreement of statements or judgements and facts or the world where the latter make true the former. In Carnap’s unchanged opposition to the classical correspondence theory of truth in turn lies not only the continuity between his own syntactic and semantic phases, but also the key to his and the entire left Vienna Circle’s understanding of their anti-metaphysical campaign. (On various occasions in the early 30s, Hahn, Frank and Neurath opposed correspondence truth very explicitly, while, in later years, Neurath resisted Tarskian semantics precisely because he wrongly suspected it of resurrecting correspondentism and Frank continued to castigate correspondentism whenever required. On this tangled issue, see Mormann 1999, Uebel 2004, Mancosu 2008, Carus 2019.)

This suggests that a hard core of Viennese anti-metaphysics survives the criticism and subsequent qualifications of early claims made for their criteria of empirical significance, and retains sufficient philosophical teeth to remain of contemporary interest. The metaphysics which the left wing attacked, besides everyday supernaturalism and the supra-scientific essentialism of old, was the correspondence conception of truth and associated realist conceptions of knowledge. These notions were deemed attackable directly on epistemological grounds, without any diversion through the theory of meaning: how could such correspondences or likenesses ever be established? As Neurath liked to put it (1930), we cannot step outside of our thinking to see whether a correspondence obtains between what we think and how the world is. (Against defenses of the correspondence theory by arguments from analogy it would be argued that the analogy is overextended.) Against the counter that this is merely an epistemic argument that does not touch the ontological issue Neurath is likely to have argued that doing without an epistemic account is a recipe for uncontrollable metaphysics.

Importantly, the left wing’s deflationary anti-metaphysics was accompanied by a distinctively constructivist attitude. Here one must hasten to add, of course, that what was constructed were not the objects of first-order discourse (tables, chairs, electrons and black holes) but concepts, be they concepts associated with technical terms for observables, theoretical terms or terms needed for reflection about the cognitive enterprise of science (ideas like evidence and its degrees and presuppositions). As meta-theorists of science they developed explications: different types of explications were envisaged, ranging from analytic definitions giving necessary and sufficient conditions in formal languages all the way to pragmatic, exemplar-based criterial delimitations of the central applications of contested concepts or practices. Two branches of the Circle’s constructivist tendency can thus be distinguished: Carnap’s rational reconstructions and formalist explications and Neurath’s and Frank’s empirically informed and practice-oriented reconceptualizations. The difference between these two approaches can be understood as a division of labor between the tasks of exploring logico-linguistic possibilities of conceptual reconstruction and considering the efficacy of particular scientific practices. In principle, the constructivist tendency in Vienna Circle philosophy was able to embrace both (compare Carnap 1934/37: §72 and Neurath 1936b). However, in its own day, this two-track approach remained incompletely realized as philosophical relations between Carnap and Neurath soured over disputes stemming from mutual misunderstandings. Frank’s final paper (1963) was a terse reminder that the logic of science was not the sole successor or replacement of traditional philosophy and Carnap’s response (1963b: §3) again acknowledged the compatibility in principle of his logic of science and what Frank called the “pragmatics of science” (1957).

Considering the Vienna Circle as a whole in the light of this reading of its anti-metaphysical philosophy, we find the most striking division within it yet. Unlike Carnap and the left wing, Schlick had little problem with a correspondence theory of truth once it was cleansed of psychologistic and intuitive accretions and centered on the idea of unique coordination of statement and fact. In this lay the strongest sense of continuity between his pre-Vienna Circle General Theory of Knowledge (1918/25) and his post-Tractarian epistemology (1935a, 1935b). (Schlick also showed little enthusiasm for the constructivist tendencies which already the manifesto of 1929 had celebrated.) Allowing for some simplification, it must be noted that Schlick’s attack on metaphysics (which gradually weakened anyway) presupposed a non-constructivist reading of the criterion of significance. Whether his conception can escape the charge self-refutation must be left open here.

3.7 The Vienna Circle and History

Much confusion exists concerning the Vienna Circle and history, that is, concerning the Vienna Circle’s attitude towards the history of philosophy and science and its own place in that history. As more has been learnt about the history of the Vienna Circle itself—the development and variety of its doctrines as well as its own prehistory as a philosophical forum—this matter can be addressed more adequately.

As the unnamed villain of the opening sentences of Kuhn’s influential Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962), logical empiricism is often accused of lacking historical consciousness and any sense of the embedding of philosophy and science in the wider culture of the day. Again it can hardly be denied that much logical empiricist philosophy, especially after World War II, was ahistorical in outlook and asocial in its orientation. Reichenbach’s distinction (1938) between the contexts of discovery and justification—which echoed distinctions made since Kant (Hoyningen-Huene 1987) and was already observed under a different name by Carnap in the Aufbau—was often employed to shield philosophy not only from contact with the sciences as practiced but also culture at large. But this was not the case for the Vienna Circle generally. On the one hand, unlike Reichenbach, who drew a sharp break between traditional philosophy and the new philosophy of logical empiricism in his popular The Rise of Scientific Philosophy (1951), Schlick was very much concerned to stress the remaining continuities with traditional philosophy and its cultural mission in his last paper (1937). On the other hand, on the left wing of the Circle scientific meta-theory was opened to the empirical sciences. To be sure, Carnap for his own part was happy to withdraw to the “icy slopes” of the logic of science and showed no research interest of his own in the history of science or philosophy, let alone its social history. By way of the division of labor he left it to Neurath and Frank to pursue the historical and practice-related sociological questions that the pure logic of science had to leave unaddressed. (See, e.g., Neurath’s studies of the history of optics [1915, 1916], Frank’s homage to Mach [1917], his pedagogical papers in 1949b and his concern with the practice of theory acceptance and change in 1956; cf. Uebel 2000 and Nemeth 2007.) Moreover, it must be noted that Neurath himself all along had planned there to be a volume on the history of science in the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, a volume that in the end became Kuhn’s Structure. Its publication in this series is often regarded as supremely ironical, given how Kuhn’s book is commonly read. But this is not only to overlook that the surviving editors of that series, Carnap and Morris, were happy to accept the manuscript, but also that Carnap found himself in positive agreement with Kuhn (Reisch 1991, Irzik & Grunberg 1995; cf. Friedman 2001). Finally, one look at the 1929 manifesto shows that its authors were very aware of and promoted the links between their philosophy of science and the socio-political and cultural issues of the day.

Turning to the historical influences on the Vienna Circle itself, the scholarship of recent decades has unearthed a much greater variety than was previously noted. Scientifically, the strongest influences have long been recognized to have been the physicists Helmholtz, Mach and Boltzmann (to which Maxwell must now be added: see Cat 2021), the mathematicians Hilbert and Klein and the logicians Frege and Russell; amongst contemporaries, Einstein was revered above all others. The Circle’s philosophical influences extend far beyond that of the British empiricists (especially Hume), to include the French conventionalists Henri Poincaré, Pierre Duhem and Abel Rey, American pragmatists like James and, in German-language philosophy, the Neo-Kantianism of both the Heidelberg and the Marburg variety, even the early phenomenology of Husserl as well as the Austrian tradition of Bolzano’s logic and the Brentano school. (See Frank 1949a for the influence of the French conventionalists; for the importance of Neo-Kantianism for Carnap, see Friedman 1987, 1992, Sauer 1989, Richardson 1998, Mormann 2007b; for Neo-Kantianism in Schlick, see Coffa 1991: Ch. 9 and Gower 2000; for the significance of Husserl for Carnap, see Sarkar 2003, Ryckman 2007, Carus 2016, Damböck 2018; for the influence of and sympathies for pragmatism see Frank 1949a and Uebel 2015b; the Bolzano-Brentano connection is explored in Haller 1986.) It is against this very wide background of influences that the seminal force must be assessed that their contemporary Wittgenstein exerted. The literature on the relation between Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle tends to suffer from an over-simplified conception of the latter, and an over-estimation of their commitment to the Tractarian program. (See Stern 2007 for an attempt by a Wittgenstein scholar to redress the balance and also contributions in Stadler 2023.) Needless to say, different wings of the Circle show these influences to different degrees. German Neo-Kantianism was important for Schlick and particularly so for Carnap, whereas Austrian naturalist-pragmatist influences were particularly strong on Hahn, Frank and Neurath. Frege was of great importance for Carnap, less so for Hahn who looked to Russell. Most importantly, by no means all members of the Vienna Circle sought to emulate Wittgenstein—thus the division between the faction around Schlick and the left wing (see Uebel 2017).

While these findings leave numerous questions open, they nevertheless refute the standard picture of Vienna Circle philosophy which confuses A.J. Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic with the real thing. Ayer offered a version of British empiricism (Berkeley’s epistemic phenomenalism updated with Russellian logic) and paid no attention, for instance, to the Circle’s overarching concern with establishing the objectivity claim of science. Ayer’s remark in the preface to his later anthology Logical Positivism that his own Language, Truth and Logic “did something to popularize what may be called the classical position of the Vienna Circle” (1959b, 8) is highly misleading therefore. What he called “the classical position” was at best a partial characterisation of the starting position of some—by no means all—of its members, a position which by 1932 the left wing as a whole rejected and even Schlick had no reason to endorse any longer (see also contributions in Tuboly 2021).

All that said by way of embedding the Vienna Circle’s philosophy in its time, one must also ask whether its members understood their own position correctly. Here one issue in particular has become increasingly prominent and raises questions that are of importance for philosophy of science still today. That is whether, after all, logical empiricism did have the resources to understand correctly the then paradigm modern science, the general theory of relativity. According to the standard logical empiricist story (Schlick 1915, 1917, 1921, 1922), their theory conclusively refuted the Kantian conception of the synthetic a priori: Euclidean geometry was not only one geometry amongst many, it also was not the one that characterized empirical reality. With one of its most prominent exemplars refuted, the synthetic a priori was deemed overthrown altogether. As noted, Schlick convinced the young Reichenbach to drop his residually Kantian talk of constitutive principles and speak of conventions instead. Likewise Schlick (1921, 1922) rejected Cassirer’s Neo-Kantian efforts (see his 1921, developing themes from his 1910) to make do with a merely relative a priori in helping along scientific self-reflection. Even though much later, and on the independent grounds of quantum physics, Frank attested to the increased proximity of his and Cassirer’s understanding of scientific theories (1938), Schlick’s earlier dismissal of his efforts remains notable.

Most controversial is how the issue of general relativity as a touchstone for competing philosophies of science was framed: having dismissed Kant’s own synthetic a priori for its mistaken apodicity, no time was spared for discussion of its then contemporary development in Neo-Kantianism as a merely relative but still constitutive a priori. Now in the philosophy of physics, this omission—committed both by Schlick and Reichenbach—has come back to haunt logical empiricists with considerable vengeance. Thus it has been shown that the Schlick-Reichenbach reading of general relativity as embodying the standard logical empiricist model of scientific theories, with high theory linked to its observational strata by purely conventional coordinative definitions, is deeply mistaken in representing the local metric of space-time not to be empirically but conventionally determined as in special relativity (Ryckman 1992) and it has been argued that it is instead only the tradition of transcendental idealism that possesses the resources to understand the achievements of mathematical physics (Ryckman 2005; cf. Friedman 2001). It is tempting to speak of the return of the repressed Neo-Kantian opposition. But it is tempting too to note that Schlick’s and Reichenbach’s mistake was already corrected quietly and without fanfare by Carnap (see the example in his 1934c [1937]: §50). So that mistake does not seem to have been inevitable and inherent in logical empiricist theorizing about science as such. Still further interpretive perspectives on the matter must be noted that in turn reflect varying assessments of Einstein’s position and who of the Circle is taken as point of reference. For instance, different criticisms of the Circle’s standard reading of Einstein’s relation to Mach (and Einstein’s self-understanding) are presented by DiSalle (2006: Ch.4), while Howard (who also long criticized the Schlick-Reichenbach reading: 1994) elaborates and defends Frank’s distinctive, namely holistic Duhemian reading of Einstein’s general theory of relativity and his endorsement of Einstein’s refusal to privilege man-made a prioris as natural in (2021).

A different charge of failing the history of science arises from Demopoulos’s challenge to the partial interpretation view of scientific theories universally adopted in logical empiricism (2017, 2022, Ch.1). Importantly, this challenge does not proceed, as some previous ones have, from the impossibility of drawing a sharp distinction between the observational and the theoretical, a point Carnap had long admitted, or other failures previously alleged. Rather, the challenge is that the partial interpretation view falsely supposes that the process of testing scientific hypotheses must only advert to theoretically uncontaminated facts and so results in misunderstanding the empirical import of theoretical claims (as in the Newman problem). Instead, Demopoulos’s argument appeals to the methodology of theory-mediated measurement rediscovered from Newton. This methodology extends the evidential base for theoretical claims about unobservables beyond the prediction of observation statements. It does so by taking account of how hitherto undetermined parameters which apply to these theoretical entities are measured, namely by exploiting diverse but concordant theoretically predicted functional relationships with yet other parameters for which experimental techniques of determining their values exist (see Smith 2002). This methodology breaks with regarding the theoretical language as an essentially uninterpreted calculus and is shown at work in Jean Perrin’s argument for the molecular hypothesis and J.J. Thomson’s for the corpuscular nature of cathode rays. Notably Demopoulos’s critique of the partial interpretation view is intended to support the existential claims of theories without supporting the so-called semantic view of theories or scientific realism in general.

With the Vienna Circle thus challenged on account of their historical self-understanding, we must also mention one important contribution from its ranks to the study of the history of science and its philosophy itself, the adoption of the non-apodictic but nevertheless constitutive a priori. Friedman (2001) drew attention to the fact that Carnap’s notion of the relative a priori coheres well with certain aspects of Kuhn’s notion of paradigms or disciplinary matrixes that change in the course of scientific revolutions. The significance of this is not lessened by the fact that Kuhn was not aware of the parallel. Carnap was open to the idea, indeed the fact, that reason has a history, even though as a logician he did not explore it much. Nor was he alone with this recognition. Neurath’s remark “That reason changes its a prioris is a matter for the history of the sciences, it is not a matter for the logic of science” (1935c [1981: 657], trans. TU) shows that even Vienna Circle naturalists were prepared to accept the relative a priori, free as it was of the metaphysical baggage of the old a priori and its associated Platonism, pertaining instead to the changing presuppositions of scientific conceptions of the world that were held at various points in history by investigators. That self-styled philosophical revolutionaries like Carnap and Neurath held such a view suggests once more that they and their colleagues in the Vienna Circle (Frank cannot be far behind) be credited with a reflexive awareness that still is not as common even among philosophers as it should be. (For explorations of the implications of this partial convergence of Carnap and Kuhn for the history of the Vienna Circle and philosophy in general, see Richardson 2002, Creath 2010, 2024.)

4. Concluding Remarks

The results of the discussion in section 3 can be briefly summarised. To start with, the dominant popular picture of the Vienna Circle as a monolithic group of simple-minded verificationists who pursued a blandly reductivist philosophy with foundationalist ambitions is widely off the mark. Instead, the Vienna Circle must be seen as a forum in which widely divergent ideas about how empiricism can cope with modern empirical and formal science were discussed. While by no means all of the philosophical initiatives started by members of the Vienna Circle have borne fruit, it is neither the case that all of them have remained fruitless. Nor is it the case that everything once distinctive of Vienna Circle philosophy has to be discarded.

Consider verificationism. Once the focus on the language of science is clarified it hardly matters that the idea to show metaphysics once-and-for-all and across-the-board to be not false but meaningless—arguably the most distinctive thesis associated with the Vienna Circle—had to be abandoned, for two versions of criterial verificationism elements remain to be pursued. On the one hand, there is the search for a criterion of empirical significance in terms of constructed, formal languages further along the lines opened by Carnap with his theory-relative proposal of 1956 and its later amendments. On the other hand—albeit at the cost of merging with the pragmatist tradition and losing the apparent Viennese distinctiveness—there is the option to reject claims made in natural language that are of a type for which no exemplars of testing exist. Properly formulated as proposals, neither the formalist nor the pragmatist version of the criterion are threatened by self-refutation.

Consider analyticity. Here again, the traditional idea—sometimes defended by some members—did show itself indefensible, but this leaves Carnap’s language-relative interpretation of analyticity and the understanding of the a priori as framework-relative to be explored. If Carnap’s ramseyfications can be defended, an analytic/synthetic distinction could be upheld also for the theoretical languages of science, but the distinction between framework principles and content continues to be drawable on a case by case basis in any case. For pragmatists the inability to define “analytic” and “logical” for all languages at once is no deterrent as long as they can be for the languages under investigation.

Consider reductionism and foundationalism. While it cannot be denied that various reductionist projects were undertaken by members of the Vienna Circle early on and that not all members were epistemological anti-foundationalists either from the start or at the end, it is clearly false to paint all of them with reductivist and/or foundationalist brushes. This is particularly true of the members of the so-called left wing of the Circle who ended up with anti-foundationalist and anti-reductionist positions (some involving instrumentalism).

Consider also, however, the challenges mentioned above to the fundamental tenets of logical empiricism that remain issues of intense discussion: challenges to its conception of the nature of empirical theory and of what is distinctive about the formal sciences. That to this day no agreement has been reached about how its proposals are to be replaced shows the ongoing relevance and centrality of its work for philosophy of science.

On the centenary of the inception of the Vienna Circle as a discussion group around Schlick it can be said that much of the variety of the philosophies of its members has been recovered, but work is ongoing. Whether the suggested qualifications and/or modifications count as defeats of the original project depends at least in part on what precisely is rejected when metaphysics is rejected and that in turn depends on what the positive vision for philosophy consists in. Here again one must differentiate. While some members ended with considerably more sympathy for traditional philosophy than they displayed in the Circle’s heyday—and may thus be charged with partial surrender—others stuck to their guns. For them, what remained of philosophy stayed squarely in the deflationist vein established by the linguistic turn. They offered explications of contested concepts or practices that, they hoped, would prove useful. Importantly, the explications given can be of two sorts: the formal explications of the logic of science by means of exemplary fragments of constructed languages, and the more informal explications of the empirical theory of science given by spelling out how certain theoretical desiderata can be attained more or less under practical constraints. This has been designated as the bipartite metatheory conception of scientific philosophy and ascribed to the left wing of the Circle as an ideal unifying its diverse methodologies (Uebel 2007: Ch.12, 2015a; Bentley 2023). Readers will note therefore that despite his enormous contribution to the development of Vienna Circle philosophy, it is not Schlick’s version of it that appears to this reviewer to be of continuing relevance to contemporary philosophy—unlike, in their very different but not incompatible ways, Carnap’s and Neurath’s and Frank’s. This may be taken as a partial endorsement of Hempel’s 1991 judgement (quoted in section 1 above), against which, however, Carnap has here been re-claimed for the Neurathian wing.

Recent work on Vienna Circle philosophies has inspired a notable variety of approaches to the legacy they constitute (besides prompting continuing excavations of other members’ non-standard variants). There is Michael Friedman’s extremely wide-ranging project (2001, 2010, 2012) to use the shortcomings of Vienna Circle philosophies as a springboard for developing a renewed Kantian philosophy that also overcomes the failings of neo-Kantianism and provides a philosophy-cum-history fit for our post-Kuhnian times. Then there is Richardson’s proposal (2008) to turn the ambition to develop a scientific philosophy into a research programme for the history of science, so as to reveal more clearly the real world dynamics and limitations of philosophy as a scientific metatheory, and to revitalize the idea of scientific philosophy itself (2024). And there is Carus’s suggestion (2007) that Carnap’s minimalist explicationism be placed in the service of a renewed Enlightenment agenda (continuing the task of the “scientific world conception”). This connects with the current metaphilosophical interest in conceptual engineering, the relevance of Carnap’s work to which is becoming increasingly recognised (Creath 1991, Justus 2012, Richardson 2013, Wagner 2012, Brun 2016, Dutilh Novaes & Reck 2017, Dutilh Novaes 2020, Lutz 2020). All along, of course, Vienna Circle philosophies also continue to serve as foils for alternative and self-consciously post-positivist programs, fruitfully so when informed by the results of recent scholarship.

It would appear then that despite continued resistance to recent revisionist scholarship—a resistance that consists not so much in contesting but in ignoring its results—the fortune of Vienna Circle philosophy has turned again. Restored from the numerous distortions of its teachings that accrued over generations of acolytes and opponents, the Vienna Circle is being recognized again as a force of considerable philosophical sophistication. Not only is it the case that its members profoundly influenced the actual development of analytical philosophy of science with conceptual initiatives that, typically, were seen through to their bitter end. It is also the case that some of its members offered proposals and suggested approaches that were not taken up widely at the time (if at all), but that are relevant again today. Much like its precursors Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein, the conventionalists Poincaré and Duhem, the pragmatists Peirce and Dewey—and like its contemporaries from Reichenbach’s Berlin Group and the Warsaw-Lvov school of logic to the Neo-Kantian Cassirer—the Vienna Circle affords a valuable vantage point on contemporary philosophy of empirical and formal science.

Bibliography

Note: Bibliographies of the members of the Vienna Circle and selected associates are given, along with short biographies, in Stadler 1997 [2015b: 397–592].

  • Achinstein, Peter and Stephen Francis Barker (eds.), 1969, The Legacy of Logical Positivism: Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press.
  • Awodey, Steve, 2007, “Carnap’s Quest for Analyticity: the Studies in Semantics”, in Friedman and Creath 2007: 226–247. doi:10.1017/CCOL9780521840156.011
  • –––, 2012, “Explicating ‘Analytic’”, in Wagner 2012: 131–143. doi:10.1057/9780230379749_10
  • –––, 2017, “Carnap and the Invariance of Logical Truth”, Synthese, 194(1): 67–78. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0781-6
  • Awodey, Steve and André W. Carus, 2003, “Carnap versus Gödel on Syntax and Tolerance”, in Parrini, Salmon, and Salmon 2003: 57–65.
  • –––, 2004, “How Carnap Could Have replied to Gödel”, in Awodey and Klein 2004: 203–224.
  • –––, 2007, “The Turning Point and the Revolution. Philosophy of Mathematics in Logical Empiricism from Tractatus to Logical Syntax”, in Richardson and Uebel 2007: 165–192. doi:10.1017/CCOL0521791782.008
  • Awodey, Steve and Carsten Klein (eds.), 2004, Carnap Brought Home: The View from Jena (Full Circle 2), Chicago: Open Court.
  • Ayer, Alfred J., 1936, Language, Truth and Logic, London: Gollancz. Second edition 1946.
  • ––– (ed.), 1959a, Logical Positivism, New York: Free Press.
  • –––, 1959b, “Editor’s Introduction”, in Ayer 1959a: 3–28.
  • Baker, Gordon P. (ed.), 2003, The Voices of Wittgenstein, The Vienna Circle: Ludwig Wittgenstein and Friedrich Waismann, London/New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203412022
  • Bell, David and Wilhelm Vossenkuhl (eds.), 1992, Wissenschaft und Subjektivität: der Wiener Kreis und die Philosophie des 20. Jahrhunderts (Science and subjectivity: the Vienna circle and twentieth century philosophy, English and German, Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
  • Bentley, Joseph, 2022, “Protocol Statements, Physicalism, and Metadata: Otto Neurath on Scientific Evidence”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 96: 125–134. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2022.09.007
  • –––, 2023, Logical Empiricism and Naturalism: Neurath and Carnap’s Metatheory of Science, Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-031-29328-3
  • Bergmann, Gustav, 1987, “Erinnerungen an den Wiener Kreis, Brief an Otto Neurath”, in Friedrich Stadler (ed.), Vertriebene Vernunft, Vienna; translated as “Memories of the Vienna Circle. Letter to Otto Neurath (1938)”, William Heald and Gunter Zoeller (trans.) in Stadler 1993: 193–208.
  • Blatti, Stephan and Sandra Lapointe (eds.), 2016, Ontology after Carnap, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199661985.001.0001
  • Bonk, Thomas (ed.), 2003, Language, Truth and Knowledge: Contributions to the Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, Dordrecht: Kluwer. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-0151-8
  • Brun, Georg, 2016, “Explication as a Method of Conceptual Re-Engineering”, Erkenntnis, 81(6): 1211–1241. doi:10.1007/s10670-015-9791-5
  • Carnap, Rudolf, 1928a, Der logische Aufbau der Welt, Berlin: Weitkreis; translated as The Logical Structure of the World in Carnap 1967.
  • –––, 1928b, Scheinprobleme in der Philosophie, Berlin: Bernary; translated as Pseudoproblems in Philosophy, in Carnap 1967: 301–343.
  • –––, 1930, “Die alte und die neue Logik”, Erkenntnis, 1: 12–26; translated as “The Old and the New Logic”, in Ayer 1959a: 60–81. doi:10.1007/BF00208606 (German)
  • –––, 1932a, “Überwindung der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Sprache”, Erkenntnis, 2: 219–241; translated as “The Elimination of Metaphysics through Logical Analysis of Language”, Arthur Papp (trans.) in Ayer 1959a: 60–81. doi:10.1007/BF02028153 (German)
  • –––, 1932b, “Die physikalische Sprache als Universalsprache der Wissenschaft”, Erkenntnis, 2: 432–465; translated with author’s introduction The Unity of Science, London: Kegan, Paul, Trench Teubner & Co., 1934. doi:10.1007/BF02028172 (German)
  • –––, 1932c, “Psychologie in physikalifcher Sprache”, Erkenntnis, 3: 107–142; translated as “Psychology in Physicalist Language” in Ayer 1959a: 165–198. doi:10.1007/BF01886414 (German)
  • –––, 1932d, “Erwiderung auf die vorstehenden Aufsätze von E. Zilsel und K. Duncker”, Erkenntnis, 3: 177–188. doi:10.1007/BF01886417 (German)
  • –––, 1932e, “Über Protokollsätze”, Erkenntnis, 3: 215–228; translated as “On Protocol Sentences”, Richard Creath and Richard Nollan (trans.), Noûs, 21(4): 457–470, 1987. doi:10.1007/BF01886421 (German) doi:10.2307/2215667 (English)
  • –––, 1934a, “On the Character of Philosophic Problems”, W. M. Malisoff (trans.), Philosophy of Science, 1(1): 5–19. doi:10.1086/286302
  • –––, 1934b [1987], Die Aufgabe der Wissenschaftslogik, Vienna: Gerold; translated as “The Task of the Logic of Science”, in McGuinness 1987: 46–66.
  • –––, 1934c [1937], Logische Syntax der Sprache, Wien: Springer. Revised edition translated as The Logical Syntax of Language, Amethe Smeaton (trans.), London: Kegan, Paul, Trench Teubner & Cie, 1937; reprinted Chicago: Open Court, 2002.
  • –––, 1935, Philosophy and Logical Syntax, London: Kegan Paul.
  • –––, 1936a, “Wahrheit und Bewährung”, Actes du Congres Internationale de Philosophie Scientifique, Sorbonne, Paris 1935, Facs. IV, “Induction et Probabilité”, Paris: Hermann & Cie., pp. 18–23; translated with additions as “Truth and Confirmation” in Feigl and Sellars 1949: 119–127.
  • –––, 1936b, “Von der Erkenntnistheorie zur Wissenschaftslogik”, Actes du Congres Internationale de Philosophie Scientifique, Sorbonne, Paris 1935, Facs. I, “Philosophie Scientifique et Empirisme Logique”, Paris: Hermann & Cie., pp. 36–41.
  • –––, 1936c, “Über die Einheitssprache der Wissenschaft. Logische Bemerkungen zum Projekt einer Enzyklopadie”, Actes du Congres Internationale de Philosophie Scientifique, Sorbonne, Paris 1935, Facs. II, “Unité de la Science”, Paris: Hermann & Cie., pp. 60–70.
  • –––, 1936/37, “Testability and Meaning”, Philosophy of Science, 3(4): 419–471 & 4(1): 1–40; reprinted in Feigl and Brodbeck 1953: 47–92. doi:10.1086/286432 doi:10.1086/286443
  • –––, 1938, “Logical Foundations of the Unity of Science”, in Encyclopedia and Unified Science (International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, 1.1), Otto Neurath, Niels Bohr, John Dewey, Bertrand Russell, Rudolf Carnap, and Charles Morris (eds.), Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 42–62.
  • –––, 1939, Foundations of Logic and Mathematics (International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, 1.3), Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, 1942, Introduction to Semantics, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1947, Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic, first edition, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, 1950a, “Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology”, Revue International de Philosophie, 4(11): 20–40; reprinted in Carnap 1956a: 205–221.
  • –––, 1950b, Logical Foundations of Probability, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, 1952, “Meaning Postulates”, Philosophical Studies, 3(5): 65–73; reprinted in Carnap 1956a: 222–229. doi:10.1007/BF02350366
  • –––, 1955, “Meaning and Synonymy in Natural Languages”, Philosophical Studies, 6(3): 33–47; reprinted in Carnap 1956a: 233–247. doi:10.1007/BF02330951
  • –––, 1956a, Meaning and Necessity: a Study in Semantics and Modal Logic, second edition, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, 1956b, “The Methodological Character of Theoretical Concepts”, in Herbert Feigl and Michael Scriven (eds.), The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Science and Psychology, Minneapolis, MN: University of Minneapolis Press, pp. 38–76
  • –––, 1958, “Beobachtungssprache und theoretische Sprache”, Dialectica, 12(3–4): 236–248; translated as “Observational and Theoretical Language” in Hintikka 1975: 75–85. doi:10.1111/j.1746-8361.1958.tb01461.x
  • –––, 1961a, “Vorwort zur zweiten Auflage”, Der logische Aufbau der Welt. Scheinprobleme in der Philosophie, second edition, Hamburg: Meiner; translated as “Preface to 2nd edition” in Carnap 1967: v–xi.
  • –––, 1961b, “On the Use of Hilbert’s E-Operator in Scientific Theories”, in Yehoshua Bar-Hillel et al. (eds.), Essays on the Foundations of Mathematics, Jerusalem: Magnes Press, pp. 156–164
  • –––, 1963a, “Intellectual Autobiography”, in Schilpp 1963: 3–84.
  • –––, 1963b, “Comments and Replies”, in Schilpp 1963: 859–1016.
  • –––, 1966 [1996], Philosophical Foundations of Science, New York: Basic Books; reprinted as An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, 1972 and New York: Dover, 1996.
  • –––, 1967, The Logical Structure of the World & Pseudoproblems in Philosophy, Rolf A. George (trans.), Berkeley: University of California Press; translations of Carnap 1928a and 1928b.
  • –––, 1990, “Quine on Analyticity”, in Creath 1990a: 427–432.
  • –––, 2000, Untersuchungen zur allgemeinen Axiomatik, T. Bonk and J. Mosterin (eds.), Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
  • –––, 2017, “Value Concepts (1958)”, Synthese, 194(1): 185–194. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0793-2
  • Carnap, Rudolf, Hans Hahn, and Otto Neurath, 1929, Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung – Der Wiener Kreis, Wien: Wolf. Partial translation in Neurath 1973: 299–318. Full translation in Stadler and Uebel 2012: 75–116.
  • Cartwright, Nancy, Jordi Cat, Lola Fleck, and Thomas E. Uebel, 1996, Otto Neurath: Philosophy between Science and Politics (Ideas in Context 38), New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511598241
  • Carus, A. W., 1999, “Carnap, Syntax, and Truth”, in Truth and Its Nature (If Any), Jaroslav Peregrin (ed.), Dordrecht/Boston: Kluwer, 15–35. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-9233-8_2
  • –––, 2007, Carnap and Twentieth-Century Thought. Explication as Enlightenment, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511487132
  • –––, 2010, “The Pragmatics of Scientific Knowledge: Howard Stein’s Reshaping of Logical Empiricism”, Monist, 93(4): 618–639. doi:10.5840/monist201093435
  • –––, 2016, “Carnap and Phenomenology: What Happened in 1924?”, in Damböck 2016: 137–162.
  • –––, 2017, “Carnapian Rationality”, Synthese, 194(1): 163–184. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0574-3
  • ––– (ed.), 2018, Carnap’s Metaphilosophy, special issue of The Monist, 101(1).
  • –––, 2019, “Neurath and Carnap on Semantics”, in Cat and Tuboly 2019: 339–361. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-02128-3_12
  • Cassirer, Ernst, 1910, Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegriff: Untersuchungen über die Grundfragen der Erkenntniskritik, Berlin: Bruno Cassirer; translated as Substance and Function in Cassirer 1923: 3–346.
  • –––, 1921, Zur Einstein’schen relativitätstheorie: Erkenntnistheoretische betrachtungen, Berlin: Bruno Cassirer; translated as Einstein’s Theory of Relativity in Cassirer 1923: 347–460.
  • –––, 1923, Substance and Function, and Einstein’s Theory of Relativity, William Curtis Swabey and Marie Taylor Collins Swabey (trans), Chicago ; London: The Open Court Publishing Company. [Cassirer 1923 available online]
  • Cat, Jordi, 2021, “The Electromoagnetic Way to the Scientific World-Conception: Maxwell’s Equations at the Service of Logical Empiricism”, in Lutz & Tuboly 20231: 21–63.
  • Cat, Jordi and Adam Tamas Tuboly (eds.), 2019, Neurath Reconsidered: New Sources and Perspectives (Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science 336), Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-02128-3
  • Cirera, Ramon, 1990 [1994], “Empirisme i sintaxi lògica. (Carnap i el Cercle de Viena)”, PhD thesis, Barcelona: Universitat de Barcelona; translated as Carnap and the Vienna Circle: Empiricism and Logical Syntax (Studien Zur Österreichischen Philosophie 23), Dick Edelstein (trans.), Amsterdam/Atlanta, GA: Rodopi. [Cirera 1990 available online (Catalan)]
  • Coffa, J. Alberto, 1976, “Carnap’s Sprachanschauung Circa 1932”, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1976(2): 205–241. doi:10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1976.2.192383
  • –––, 1991, The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap: To the Vienna Station, Linda Wessels (ed.), Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139172240
  • Craig, William, 1956, “Replacement of Auxiliary Expressions”, The Philosophical Review, 65(1): 38–55.
  • Creath, Richard, 1976, “On Kaplan on Carnap on Significance”, Philosophical Studies, 30(6): 393–400. doi:10.1007/BF00372539
  • –––, 1982, “Was Carnap a Complete Verificationist in the Aufbau?”, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1982(1): 384–393. doi:10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1982.1.192681
  • ––– (ed.), 1990a, Dear Carnap, Dear Van: The Quine-Carnap Correspondence and Related Work, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
  • –––, 1990b, “The Unimportance of Semantics”, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1990(2): 404–416. doi:10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1990.2.193084
  • –––, 1991, “Every Dogma Has Its Day”, Erkenntnis, 35(1–3): 347–389. doi:10.1007/BF00388294
  • –––, 1996, “Languages Without Logic”, in Giere and Richardson 1996: 251–268.
  • –––, 1999, “Carnap’s Move to Semantics: Gains and Losses”, in Woleński and Köhler 1999: 65–76. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-0689-6_6
  • –––, 2003, “The Linguistic Doctrine and Conventionality: The Main Argument in ‘Carnap and Logical Truth’”, in Hardcastle and Richardson 2003: 234–256.
  • –––, 2004, “Quine on the Intelligibility and Relevance of Analyticity”, in The Cambridge Companion to Quine, Roger F. Gibson, Jr (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 47–64. doi:10.1017/CCOL0521630568.003
  • –––, 2010, “The Construction of Reason: Kant, Carnap, Kuhn, and Beyond”, in Domski and Dickson 2010: 493–509.
  • –––, 2012a, “Analyticity in the Theoretical Language: Is a Different Account Really Necessary?”, in Creath 2012b: 57–66.
  • ––– (ed.), 2012b, Rudolf Carnap and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 16), Dordrecht/New York: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-3929-1
  • –––, 2017, “The Logical and the Analytic”, Synthese, 194(1): 79–96. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0685-5
  • –––, 2024, “‘… I Probably Would Never Have Written Structure ’”, in Kuhn’s ‘The Structure of Scientific Revolutions’ at 60, K. Brad Wray (ed.), Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press, 21–36. doi:10.1017/9781009122696.004
  • Curiel, Eric and Flavia Padovani (eds.), 2021–22, All Things Reichenbach, Collection strewn intermittently through Synthese, 199–200. [All Things Reichenbach collection available online]
  • Dahms, Hans-Joachim, 1995, “The Emigration of the Vienna Circle”, in Vertreibung der Vernunft: The Cultural Exodus from Austria, Peter Weibel and Friedrich Stadler (eds.), second revised and enlarged edition, Wien/New York: Springer, 57–79.
  • –––, 2004, “Neue Sachlichkeit in the Architecture and Philosophy of the 1920s”, in Awodey and Klein 2004: 357–375.
  • Damböck, Christian (ed.), 2016, Influences on the Aufbau (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 18), Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-21876-2
  • –––, 2018, “Carnap’s Auflau: A Case of Plagiarism?”, Magyar Filozófiai Szemle/Hungarian Philosophical Review, 62(4): 66–80.
  • Damböck, Christian and Gereon Wolters (eds.), 2021, Der junge Carnap in historischem Kontext: 1918–1935 / Young Carnap in an Historical Context: 1918–1935 (Veröffentlichungen des Instituts Wiener Kreis 30), Cham: Springer International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-58251-7
  • Damböck, Christian, Günther Sandner, and Meike G. Werner (eds.), 2022, Logischer Empirismus, Lebensreform und die deutsche Jugendbewegung: Logical Empiricism, Life Reform, and the German Youth Movement (Veröffentlichungen des Instituts Wiener Kreis), Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-84887-3
  • Damböck, Christian and Adam Tamas Tuboly (eds.), 2022, The Socio-Ethical Dimension of Knowledge: The Mission of Logical Empiricism (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 26), Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-80363-6
  • Demopoulos, William, 2003, “On the Rational Reconstruction of Our Theoretical Knowledge”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54(3): 371–403. doi:10.1093/bjps/54.3.371
  • –––, 2017, “Logical Empiricist Reconstructions of Theoretical Knowledge”, in Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science: Proceedings of the 15th International Congress (Helsinki, 2015), Hannes Leitgeb, Ilkka Niiniluoto, Päivi Seppälä, and Elliot Sober (eds.), London: College publications, 182–198.
  • –––, 2022, On Theories: Logical Empiricism and the Methodology of Modern Physics, Michael Friedman (ed.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Demopoulos, William and Michael Friedman, 1985, “Critical Notice: Bertrand Russell’s The Analysis of Matter : Its Historical Context and Contemporary Interest”, Philosophy of Science, 52(4): 621–639. doi:10.1086/289281
  • DiSalle, Robert, 2006, Understanding Space-Time: The Philosophical Development of Physics from Newton to Einstein, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Domski, Mary and Michael Dickson (eds.), 2010, Discourse on a New Method: Reinvigorating the Marriage of History and Philosophy of Science, Chicago, IL: Open Court.
  • Douglas, Heather (ed.), 2009, Symposium on Politics and Philosophy of Science, special issue of Science & Education, 18(2).
  • Dutilh Novaes, Catarina, 2020, “Carnapian Explication and Ameliorative Analysis: A Systematic Comparison”, Synthese, 197(3): 1011–1034. doi:10.1007/s11229-018-1732-9
  • Dutilh Novaes, Catarina and Erich Reck, 2017, “Carnapian Explication, Formalisms as Cognitive Tools, and the Paradox of Adequate Formalization”, Synthese, 194(1): 195–215. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0816-z
  • Ebbs, Gary, 2017, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781316823392
  • –––, 2023, “Reading Quine’s Claim That Carnap’s Term ‘Semantical Rule’ Is Meaningless”, in Morris 2023: 135–153. doi:10.1017/9781108664202.011
  • Edmonds, David, 2020, The Murder of Professor Schlick: The Rise and Fall of the Vienna Circle, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Feigl, Herbert, 1943, “Logical Empiricism”, in Twentieth Century Philosophy: Living Schools of Thought, Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), New York: Philosophical Library, 371–416. Abbreviated version reprinted in Feigl and Sellars 1949: 3–26.
  • –––, 1950, “Existential Hypotheses: Realistic versus Phenomenalistic Interpretations”, Philosophy of Science, 17(1): 35–62. doi:10.1086/287065
  • –––, 1953, “Unity of Science and Unitary Science”, in Feigl and Brodbeck 1953: 382–384.
  • –––, 1955, “The Philosophy of Science of Logical Empiricism”, in Proceedings of the Second International Congress of the International Union for the Philosophy of Science, Zurich 1954, Neuchatel: Editions du Griffon, pp. 95–115.
  • –––, 1969a, “The Wiener Kreis in America”, in The Intellectual Migration: Europe and America, 1930–1960, Donald Fleming and Bernard Bailyn (eds.), Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, pp. 630–673; reprinted in Feigl 1981: 57–94. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-9426-9_4
  • –––, 1969b, “The Origin and Spirit of Logical Positivism”, in Achinstein and Barker 1969: 3–24; reprinted in Feigl 1981: 21–37.
  • –––, 1970, “The ‘Orthodox’ View of Theories: Remarks in Defense as well as Critique”, in Radner and Winokur 1970: 3–16.
  • –––, 1981, Inquiries and Provocations: Selected Writings, 1929-1974 (Vienna Circle Collection 14), R. S. Cohen (ed.), Dordrecht/Hingham, MA: D. Reidel/Kluwer.
  • Feigl, Herbert and May Brodbeck, 1953, Readings in the Philosophy of Science, New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
  • Feigl, Herbert and Wilfrid Sellars (eds.), 1949, Readings in Philosophical Analysis, New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
  • Feigl, Herbert, Michael Scriven, and Grover Maxwell (eds.), 1958, Concepts, Theories and the Mind-Body Problem (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 2), Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
  • Fetzer, James H. (ed.), 2000, Science, Explanation, and Rationality: Aspects of the Philosophy of Carl G. Hempel, Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780195121377.001.0001
  • Frank, Philipp, 1910, “[Review] A. Rey, Die Theorie der Physik bei den modernen Physikern”, Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, 21: 43–45 (of separate review section).
  • –––, 1917, “Die Bedeutung der physikalischen Erkenntnistheorie Machs für das Geistesleben der Gegenwart”, Die Naturwissenschaften, 5(5): 65–72; translated as “The importance for our times of Ernst Mach’s Philosophy of Science” in Frank 1941b and Frank 1949b: 61–79. doi:10.1007/BF02448154 (German)
  • –––, 1932, Das Kausalgesetz und seine Grenzen, Wien: Springer; translated as The Law of Causality and Its Limits, Robert S. Cohen (ed.), Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen (trans.), Dordrecht/Boston: Kluwer, 1998. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-5516-8
  • –––, 1938, “Bemerkungen zu Ernst Cassirer: Determinismus und Indeterminismus in der modernen Physik”, Theoria, 4(1): 70–80; translated as “Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics”, in Frank 1949b: 172–185.
  • –––, 1941a, “Introduction: Historical Background”, in Frank 1941b: 3–16.
  • –––, 1941b, Between Physics and Philosophy, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1949a, “Historical Introduction”, in Frank 1949b: 1–51.
  • –––, 1949b, Modern Science and its Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1950, “Comments on Realistic Versus Phenomenalistic Interpretations”, Philosophy of Science, 17(2): 166–169. doi:10.1086/287077
  • –––, 1956, “The Variety of Reasons for the Acceptance of Scientific Theories”, in The Validation of Scientific Theories, Philipp Frank (ed.), Boston: Beacon Press, 3–17.
  • –––, 1957, Philosophy of Science: The Link Between Science and Philosophy, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall; reprinted. Minola, NY: Dover, 2004.
  • –––, 1963, “The Pragmatic Components in Carnap’s ‘Elimination of Metaphysics’”, in Schilpp 1963: 159–164.
  • –––, 2021, The Humanistic Background of Science (SUNY Series in American Philosophy and Cultural Thought), George A. Reisch and Adam Tamas Tuboly (eds.), Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
  • Friedman, Michael, 1987, “Carnap’s Aufbau Reconsidered”, Noûs, 21(4): 521–545; reprinted in Friedman 1999b: 89–113. doi:10.2307/2215671
  • –––, 1988, “Logical Truth and Analyticity in Carnap’s ‘Logical Syntax of Language’”, in History and Philosophy of Modern Mathematics (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 11), William Aspray and Philip Kitcher (eds.), Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 82–94; reprinted in Friedman 1999b: 165–177.
  • –––, 1992, “Epistemology in the Aufbau”, Synthese, 93(1–2): 15–57. Collected in in Friedman 1999b: 114–151. doi:10.1007/BF00869420
  • –––, 1994, “Geometry, Convention, and the Relativized A Priori: Reichenbach, Schlick, and Carnap”, in Salmon and Wolters 1994: 21–43; reprinted. in Friedman 1999b: 59–71.
  • –––, 1999a, “Tolerance and Analyticity in Carnap’s Philosophy of Mathematics”, in Friedman 1999b: 198–233.
  • –––, 1999b, Reconsidering Logical Positivism, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139173193
  • –––, 2000, A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger, Chicago, IL: Open Court.
  • –––, 2001, Dynamics of Reason, Stanford: CSLI Publications.
  • –––, 2008, “Wissenschaftslogik: The Role of Logic in the Philosophy of Science”, Synthese, 164(3): 385–400. doi:10.1007/s11229-008-9356-0
  • –––, 2009, “Tolerance, Intuition and Empiricism”, in Wagner 2009: 236–249. doi:10.1057/9780230235397_11
  • –––, 2010, “Synthetic History Reconsidered”, in Domski and Dickson 2010: 385–400.
  • –––, 2011, “Carnap on Theoretical Terms: Structuralism without Metaphysics”, Synthese, 180(2): 249–263. doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9604-y
  • –––, 2012, “Reconsidering the Dynamics of Reason: Response to Ferrari, Mormann, Nordmann, and Uebel”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 43(1): 47–53. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2011.10.006
  • Friedman, Michael and Richard Creath (eds.), 2007, The Cambridge Companion to Carnap (Cambridge Companions to Philosophy), Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CCOL9780521840156
  • Frigg, Roman, 2022, Models and Theories: A Philosophical Inquiry, London: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781003285106
  • Frost-Arnold, Greg, 2013, Carnap, Tarski, and Quine at Harvard: Conversations on Logic, Mathematics, and Science, (Full Circle : Publications of the Archive of Scientific Philosophy, Hillman Library, University of Pittsburgh 5), Chicago, IL: Open Court.
  • Galavotti, Maria Carla (ed.), 2006, Cambridge and Vienna: Frank P. Ramsey and the Vienna Circle (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 12), Dordrecht/London: Springer. doi:10.1007/1-4020-4101-2
  • Galison, Peter, 1990, “Aufbau/Bauhaus: Logical Positivism and Architectural Modernism”, Critical Inquiry, 16(4): 709–752. doi:10.1086/448557
  • Giere, Ronald N. and Alan W. Richardson (eds.), 1996, Origins of Logical Empiricism (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 16), Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
  • Glymour, Clark, 1980, Theory and Evidence, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Goldfarb, Warren, 1997, “Semantics in Carnap: A Rejoinder to Alberto Coffa”, Philosophical Topics, 25(2): 51–66. doi:10.5840/philtopics19972529
  • Goldfarb, Warren and Thomas Ricketts, 1992, “Carnap and the Philosophy of Mathematics”, in Bell and Vossenkuhl 1992: 61–78.
  • Gower, Barry (ed.), 1987, Logical Positivism in Perspective: Essays on Language, Truth, and Logic, London: Croom Helm.
  • –––, 2000, “Cassirer, Schlick and ‘Structural’ Realism: The Philosophy of the Exact Sciences in the Background to Early Logical Empiricism”, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 8(1): 71–106. doi:10.1080/096087800360238
  • Hahn, Hans, 1933, Logik, Mathematik und Naturerkennen, Wien: Gerold; translated as “Logic, Mathematics, and Knowledge of Nature”, in McGuinness 1987: 24–45.
  • –––, 1980, Empiricism, Logic, and Mathematics: Philosophical Papers (Vienna Circle Collection 13), Brian McGuinness (ed.), Dordrecht/Boston: D. Reidel.
  • Haller, Rudolf (ed.), 1982, Schlick und Neurath—ein Symposion, Grazer Philosophische Studien, Volume 16–17.
  • –––, 1985, “Der erste Wiener Kreis”, Erkenntnis, 22(1–3): 341–358; translated as “The First Vienna Circle”, Thomas E. Uebel (trans.) in Uebel 1991: 95–108. doi:10.1007/BF00269973
  • –––, 1986, “Zur Historiographie der österreichischen Philosophie”, in Nyíri 1986: 41–53; translated as “On the Historiography of Austrian Philosophy” in Uebel 1991: 41–50. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-3182-7_4 (English)
  • –––, 1993, Neopositivismus. Eine historische Enführung in die Philosophie des Wiener Kreises, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
  • –––, 2003, “On Herbert Feigl”, in Hardcastle and Richardson 2003: 115–128.
  • Hanfling, Oswald, 1981, Logical Positivism, New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Hardcastle, Gary L. and Alan W. Richardson (eds.), 2003, Logical Empiricism in North America (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 18), Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
  • Hempel, Carl Gustav, 1935, “On the Logical Positivists’ Theory of Truth”, Analysis, 2(4): 49–59; reprinted in Selected Philosophical Essays, by Carl G. Hempel, Richard Jeffrey (ed.), Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press, 9–20. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511815157.005 doi:10.1093/analys/2.4.49
  • –––, 1942, “The Function of General Laws in History”, The Journal of Philosophy, 39(2): 35–48; reprinted in Hempel 1965b: 231–244. doi:10.2307/2017635
  • –––, 1950 [1959], “Problems and Changes in the Empiricist Criterion of Meaning”, Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4(11): 41–63; reprinted in Ayer 1959a: 108–129.
  • –––, 1951, “The Concept of Cognitive Significance: A Reconsideration”, Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 80(1): 61–77. doi:10.2307/20023635
  • –––, 1958, “The Theoretician’s Dilemma: A Study in the Logic of Theory Construction”, in Feigl, Scriven, and Maxwell 1958: 37–98; reprinted in Hempel 1965b: 173–228.
  • –––, 1963, “Implications of Carnap’s Work for the Philosophy of Science”, in Schilpp 1963: 685–710.
  • –––, 1965a, “Empiricist Criteria of Cognitive Significance: Problems and Changes”, [adaptation of Hempel 1950 and Hempel 1951], in Hempel 1965b: 101–122
  • –––, 1965b, Aspects of Scientific Explanation: And Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, New York: Free Press.
  • Hintikka, Jaakko (ed.), 1975, Rudolf Carnap, Logical Empiricist: Materials and Perspectives (Synthese Library, 73), Dordrecht/Boston,: D. Reidel. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-1807-4
  • Howard, Don, 1994, “Einstein, Kant, and the Origins of Logical Empiricism”, in Salmon and Wolters 1994: 45–106.
  • –––, 2003, “Two Left Turns Make a Right: On the Curious Political Career of North American Philosophy of Science at Midcentury”, in Hardcastle and Richardson 2003: 25–93.
  • –––, 2021, “The Philosopher Physicists: Albert Einstein and Philipp Frank”, in Lutz and Tuboly 2021: 121–156.
  • Hoyningen-Huene, Paul, 1987, “Context of Discovery and Context of Justification”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 18(4): 501–515. doi:10.1016/0039-3681(87)90005-7
  • Irzik, Gürol and Teo Grünberg, 1995, “Carnap and Kuhn: Arch Enemies or Close Allies?”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46(3): 285–307. doi:10.1093/bjps/46.3.285
  • Jørgensen, Jørgen, 1951, The Development of Logical Empiricism (International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. Foundations of the Unity of Science, 2.9), Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Justus, James, 2012, “Carnap on Concept Determination: Methodology for Philosophy of Science”, European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2(2): 161–179. doi:10.1007/s13194-011-0027-5
  • –––, 2014, “Carnap’s Forgotten Criterion of Empirical Significance”, Mind, 123(490): 415–436. doi:10.1093/mind/fzu042
  • –––, 2022, “Verificationism”, in Uebel and Limbeck-Lilienau 2022: 157–167 (ch. 16).
  • Kaplan, Abraham, 1963, “Logical Empiricism and Value Judgments”, in Schilpp 1963: 827–856.
  • Kaplan, David, 1975a, “Significance and Analyticity”, in Hintikka 1975: 87–94.
  • –––, 1975b, “Hommage to Rudolf Carnap”, in Hintikka 1975: xlvii–xlix.
  • Kemeny, John G., 1956, “A New Approach to Semantics – Part I”, Journal of Symbolic Logic, 21(1): 1–27. doi:10.2307/2268481
  • Kraft, Viktor, 1950 [1953], Der Wiener Kreis, der Ursprung des Neopositivismus: ein Kapitel der jüngsten Philosophiegeschichte, Wien: Springer-Verlag. Second expanded edition, 1968; translated as The Vienna Circle, the Origin of Neo-Positivism: A Chapter in the History of Recent Philosophy, Arthur Pap (trans.), New York: Philosophical Library, 1953.
  • Kuhn, Thomas S., 1962, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, 2.2), Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Second edition, 1970.
  • Lewis, David, 1970, “How to Define Theoretical Terms”, The Journal of Philosophy, 67(13): 427–446; reprinted in his Philosophical Papers, Volume 1, New York: Oxford University Press, 78–95. doi:10.2307/2023861 doi:10.1093/0195032047.003.0006
  • Lutz, Sebastian, 2012, “On a Straw Man in the Philosophy of Science: A Defense of the Received View”, HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, 2(1): 77–120. doi:10.1086/664460
  • –––, 2014, “What’s Right with a Syntactic Approach to Theories and Models?”, Erkenntnis, 79(S8): 1475–1492. doi:10.1007/s10670-013-9578-5
  • –––, 2017, “Carnap on Empirical Significance”, Synthese, 194(1): 217–252. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0561-8
  • –––, 2020, “Armchair Philosophy Naturalized”, Synthese, 197(3): 1099–1125. doi:10.1007/s11229-017-1653-z
  • Lutz, Sebastian and Adam Tamas Tuboly (eds.), 2021, Logical Empiricism and the Physical Sciences. From Philosophy of Nature to Philosophy of Physics, Abingdon: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780429429835
  • Mach, Ernst, 1883 [1960], Die Mechanik in ihrer Entwicklung, Leipzig: Brockhaus. Second edition translated as The Science of Mechanics: A Critical and Historical Account of Its Development, Thomas J. McCormack (trans.), Chicago: Open Court, 1893. Sixth English edition updated to the ninth German edition, LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 1960.
  • MacLane, Saunders, 1938, “Carnap on Logical Syntax”, Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 44(3): 171–176.
  • Makovec, Dejan and Stewart Shapiro (eds.), 2019, Friedrich Waismann: The Open Texture of Analytic Philosophy, Basingstoke: Macmillan-Palgrave. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-25008-9
  • Mancosu, Paolo, 2005, “Harvard 1940–1941: Tarski, Carnap and Quine on a Finitistic Language of Mathematics for Science”, History and Philosophy of Logic, 26(4): 327–357. doi:10.1080/01445340500141586
  • –––, 2008, “Tarski, Neurath, and Kokoszyńska on the Semantic Conception of Truth”, in New Essays on Tarski and Philosophy, Douglas Patterson (ed.), Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press, 192–224. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199296309.003.0008
  • Manninen, Juha, 2011, “Waismann’s Testimony of Wittgenstein’s Fresh Starts in 1931–35”, in McGuinness 2011: 243–265. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-1751-0_10
  • Manninen, Juha and Friedrich Stadler (eds.), 2010, The Vienna Circle in the Nordic Countries: Networks and Transformations of Logical Empiricism (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 14), Dordrecht/New York: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-90-481-3683-4
  • Maxwell, Grover, 1970, “Structural Realism and the Meaning of Theoretical Terms”, in Radner and Winoker 1970: 181–192
  • McGuinness, Brian F. (ed.), 1967 [1979], Wittgenstein und der Wiener Kreis, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp/ Oxford: B. Blackwell; translated as Wittgenstein & the Vienna Circle: Conversations recorded by Friedrich Waismann, Joachim Schulte and Brian McGuinness (trans), Oxford: Blackwell, 1979.
  • –––, 1985, Moritz Schlick, special issue of Synthese, 64(3).
  • ––– (ed.), 1987, Unified Science: The Vienna Circle Monograph Series (Vienna Circle Collection), Dordrecht: Reidel. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-3865-6
  • ––– (ed.), 2011, Friedrich Waismann - Causality and Logical Positivism (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 15), Dordrecht/New York: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-1751-0
  • Menger, Karl, 1934, Moral, Wille und Weltgestaltung: Grundlegung zur Logik der Sitten, Vienna: Springer; translated as Morality, Decision, and Social Organization: Toward a Logic of Ethics (Vienna Circle Collection 6), Dordrecht/Boston: D. Reidel, 1974. doi:10.1007/978-3-7091-3053-7 (German) doi:10.1007/978-94-010-2107-4 (English)
  • –––, 1994, Reminiscences of the Vienna Circle and the Mathematical Colloquium (Vienna Circle Collection, 20), Louise Golland, Brian McGuinness, and Abe Sklar (eds.), Dordrecht/Boston: Kluwer. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-1102-7
  • Milkov, Nikolay and Volker Peckhaus (eds.), 2013, The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism (Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, 273), Dordrecht/New York: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-5485-0
  • Morgan, Mary S. and Margaret Morrison (eds.), 1999, Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science (Ideas in Context 52), Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Mormann, Thomas, 1999, “Neurath’s Opposition to Tarskian Semantics”, in Woleński and Köhler 1999: 165–178. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-0689-6_14
  • –––, 2000, Rudolf Carnap (Beck’sche Reihe Denker 554), München: Beck (in German).
  • –––, 2007a, “The Structure of Scientific Theories in Logical Empiricism”, in Richardson and Uebel 2007: 136–162. doi:10.1017/CCOL0521791782.007
  • –––, 2007b, “Carnap’s Logical Empiricism, Values, and American Pragmatism”, Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 38(1): 127–146. doi:10.1007/s10838-007-9033-x
  • Morris, Sean (ed.), 2023, The Philosophical Project of Carnap and Quine, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781108664202
  • Nagel, Ernest, 1936, “Impressions and Appraisals of Analytic Philosophy in Europe”, The Journal of Philosophy, part I 33(1): 5–24, part II 33(2): 29–53; reprinted in Ernest Nagel, Logic without Metaphysics: And Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1956: 191–246. doi:10.2307/2016895 (I) doi:10.2307/2016015(II)
  • Nemeth, Elisabeth, 2007, “Logical Empiricism and the History and Sociology of Science”, in Richardson and Uebel, 2007: 278–304. doi:10.1017/CCOL0521791782.012
  • Nemeth, Elisabeth and Friedrich Stadler (eds.), 1996, Encyclopedia and Utopia: The Life and Work of Otto Neurath (1882–1945) (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 4), Dordrecht/Boston: Kluwer.
  • Nemeth, Elisabeth, Stefan W. Schmitz, and Thomas E. Uebel (eds.), 2007, Otto Neurath’s Economics in Context (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 13), Dordrecht/London. doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-6905-5
  • Neuber, Matthias, 2011, “Feigl’s ‘Scientific Realism’”, Philosophy of Science, 78(1): 165–183. doi:10.1086/658114
  • Neurath, Otto, 1913, “Die Verirrten des Cartesius und das Auxiliarmotiv (Zur Psychologie des Entschlusses)”, Jahrbuch der Philosophischen Gesellschaft an der Universität zu Wien 1913, pp. 45–59; translated as “The Lost Wanderers and the Auxiliary Motive (On the Psychology of Decision)” in Neurath 1983: 1–12. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_1 (English)
  • –––, 1915, “Prinzipielles zur Geschichte der Optik”, Archiv für die Geschichte der Naturwissenschaften und Technik, 5: 371–389; translated as “On the Foundations of the History of Optics” in Neurath 1973: 101–112.
  • –––, 1916, “Zur Klassifikation von Hypothesensystemen”, Jahrbuch der Philosophischen Gesellschaft an der Universität Wien 1914 und 1915, pp. 39–63; translated as “On the Classification of Systems of Hypotheses” in Neurath 1983: 13–31. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_2 (English)
  • –––, 1930, “Wege der wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung”, Erkenntnis, 1: 106–125; translated as “Ways of the Scientific World Conception” in Neurath 1983: 32–47. doi:10.1007/BF00208613 (German) doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_3 (English)
  • –––, 1931a, Empirische Soziologie: Der wissenschaftliche Gehalt der Geschichte und Nationalökonomie, Berlin: Springer; reprinted in Neurath 1981: 423–527. Partially translated as “Empirical Sociology”, in Neurath 1973: 391–421. doi:10.1007/978-3-7091-2334-8 (German)
  • –––, 1931b, “Physikalismus”, Scientia, 50: 297–303; translated as “Physicalism” in Neurath 1983: 52–57. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_5 (English)
  • –––, 1932a, “Soziologie im Physikalismus”, Erkenntnis, 2: 393–431; translated as “Sociology in the Framework of Physicalism” in Neurath 1983: 58–90. doi:10.1007/BF02028171 (German) doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_6 (English)
  • –––, 1932b, “Protokollsätze”, Erkenntnis, 3: 204–214; translated as “Protocol Statements” in Neurath 1983: 91–99. doi:10.1007/BF01886420 (German) doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_7 (English)
  • –––, 1934, “Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt’”, Erkenntnis, 4: 346–362; translated as “Radical Physicalism and ‘the Real World’” in Neurath 1983: 100–114. doi:10.1007/BF01793498 (German) doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_8 (English)
  • –––, 1935a [1983], “Einheit der Wissenschaft als Aufgabe”:, Erkenntnis, 5: 16–22; translated as “The Unity of Science as a Task” in Neurath 1983: 115–120. doi:10.1007/BF00172277 (German) doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_9 (English)
  • –––, 1935b [1987], Was heisst rationale Wirtschaftsbetrachtung?, Vienna: Gerold; translated as “What is Meant by a Rational Economic Theory?”, in McGuinness 1987: 67–109.
  • –––, 1935c [1981], Le developpement du Cercle de Vienne et l’avenir de l’Empirisme logique, Paris: Hermann & Cie; translated as “Die Entwicklung des Wiener Kreises und die Zukunft des Logischen Empirismus”, B. Treschmitzer and H. G. Zilian (trans), in Neurath 1981: 673–703.
  • –––, 1936a, “L’encyclopedie comme ‘modele’”, Revue de Synthese, 12: 187–201, Translated as “Encyclopedia as ‘Model’” in Neurath 1983: 145–158. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_13 (English)
  • –––, 1936b, “Diskussionsinlägg: Physikalismus und Erkenntnisforschung”, Theoria, 2(1–): 97–105 and 2(3): 359–364; translated as “Physicalism and the Investigation of Knowledge” in Neurath 1983: 159–167. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_14 (English)
  • –––, 1937, “Zu den Vorträgen von Black, Kokoszynska, Williams”, Erkenntnis, 7(1): 371–374; translated as “ Comments on the Papers by Black, Kokoszyńska, Williams” in Neurath 1983: 206–8. doi:10.1007/BF00666566 (German) doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_19 (English)
  • –––, 1944, Foundations of the Social Sciences (International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, 2.1), Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago press.
  • –––, 1973, Empiricism and Sociology (Vienna Circle Collections 1), Marie Neurath and R. S. Cohen (eds.), Dordrecht: Reidel. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-2525-6
  • –––, 1981, Gesammelte philosophische und methodologische Schriften, Rudolf Haller and Heiner Rutte (eds.), Wien: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.
  • –––, 1983, Philosophical Papers, 1913–1946 (Vienna Circle Collection 16), R. S. Cohen and Marie Neurath (eds.), Dordrecht/Boston: D. Riedel. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7
  • Newman, M. H. A., 1928, “Mr. Russell’s ‘Causal Theory of Perception’”, Mind, 37(146): 137–148. doi:10.1093/mind/XXXVII.146.137
  • Nyíri, János Kristóf (ed.), 1986, From Bolzano to Wittgenstein: The Tradition of Austrian Philosophy/Von Bolzano zu Wittgenstein: zur Tradition der österreichischen Philosophie (Schiftenreihe der Wittgenstein-Gesellschaft 12/2), Wien: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.
  • Oberdan, Thomas, 1993, Protocols, Truth and Convention (Studien zur Österreichischen Philosophie, 19), Amsterdam/Atlanta, GA: Rodopi.
  • –––, 1998, “The Vienna Circle’s ‘Anti-Foundationalism’”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49(2): 297–308. doi:10.1093/bjps/49.2.297
  • –––, 2009, “Geometry, Convention, and the Relativized Apriori: The Schlick—Reichenbach Correspondence”, in Stationen. Dem Philosophen und Physiker Moritz Schlick zum 125. Geburtstag (Schlick-Studien 1), Friedrich Stadler, Hans Jürgen Wendel, and Edwin Glassner (eds.), Vienna: Springer, 186–211. doi:10.1007/978-3-211-71581-9_7
  • Oppenheim, Paul, and Hilary Putnam, 1958, “Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis”, in Feigl, Maxwell, and Scriven 1958: 3–36.
  • Papineau, David, 1996, “Theory-Dependent Terms”, Philosophy of Science, 63(1): 1–20. doi:10.1086/289890
  • Parrini, Paolo, 1995 [1998], Conoscenza e realtà, Roma-Bari: Gius. Laterza & Figli Spa; translated as Knowledge and Reality: An Essay in Positive Philosophy (The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science 59), Paolo Baracchi (trans.), Dordrecht/Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1998.
  • Parrini, Paolo, Wesley C. Salmon, and Merrilee Salmon (eds.), 2003, Logical Empiricism. Historical and Contemporary Perspectives, Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.
  • Passmore, John, 1967, “Logical Positivism”, Paul Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, New York: Macmillan, 5: 52–57.
  • Peirce, Charles Sanders, 1878, “How to Makes Our Ideas Clear”, Popular Science Monthly, 12: 286–303; reprinted in The Essential Peirce Vol. 1, Peirce Edition Project (ed.), Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1998, pp. 124–141.
  • Pihlström, Sami, Friedrich Stadler, and Niels Weidtmann (eds.), 2017, Logical Empiricism and Pragmatism (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 19), Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-50730-9
  • Pincock, Christopher, 2002, “Russell’s Influence On Carnap’s Aufbau”, Synthese, 131(1): 1–37. doi:10.1023/A:1015066427566
  • –––, 2005, “A Reserved Reading of Carnap’s Aufbau”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 86(4): 518–543. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0114.2005.00240.x
  • –––, 2016, “Logical Empiricism”, in The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology, Herman Cappelen, Tamar Szabó Gendler, and John Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 93–111. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199668779.013.19
  • Proust, Joëlle, 1986, Questions de forme: logique et proposition analytique de Kant à Carnap, Paris: Fayard; translated as Questions of Form: Logic and the Analytic Proposition from Kant to Carnap, Anastasios Albert Brenner (trans.), Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1989.
  • Psillos, Stathis, 1999, Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth (Philosophical Issues in Science), London/New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203979648
  • –––, 2000a, “Rudolf Carnap’s ‘Theoretical Concepts in Science’”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 31(1): 151–172. doi:10.1016/S0039-3681(99)00031-X
  • –––, 2000b, “Carnap, the Ramsey-Sentence and Realistic Empiricism”, Erkenntnis, 52(2): 253–279. doi:10.1023/A:1005589117656
  • Putnam, Hilary, 1962, “What Theories Are Not”, in Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science: Proceeding of the 1960 International Congress, Ernest Nagel, Patrick Suppes, and Alfred Tarski (eds.), Stanford: Stanford University Press, 240–251; reprinted in Putnam, Philosophical Papers Vol. 1, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978, 215–227. doi:10.1016/S0049-237X(09)70591-9
  • –––, 1978, “There Is at Least One a Priori Truth”, Erkenntnis, 13(1): 153–170; reprinted in Putnam 1983: 98–114. doi:10.1007/BF00160892
  • –––, 1981a, Reason, Truth, and History, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511625398
  • –––, 1981b, “Convention: A Theme in Philosophy”, New Literary History, 13(1): 1–14; reprinted in Putnam 1983: 170–183. doi:10.2307/468639
  • –––, 1983, Realism and Reason: Philosophical Papers, Volume 3, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511625275
  • Quine, W. V. O., 1936, “Truth by Convention”, in Philosophical Essays for A.N. Whitehead, Otis H. Lee (ed.), New York: Longmans, Green and co., 90–124; reprinted in Quine 1966: 77–106.
  • –––, 1940, Mathematical Logic, New York: W. W. Norton & company. Revised edition, 1951, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; reprinted, 1981, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1951a, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”, The Philosophical Review, 60(1): 20–43; reprinted in Quine From a Logical Point of View: 9 Logico-Philosophical Essays, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953. Revised edition 1980: 20–46. doi:10.2307/2181906
  • –––, 1951b, “On Carnap’s Views on Ontology”, Philosophical Studies, 2(5): 65–72; reprinted in his The Ways of Paradox, and Other Essays, 1st ed. 1966, revised and enlarged edition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1976: 203–211. doi:10.1007/BF02199422
  • –––, 1960, Word and Object, Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.
  • –––, 1963, “Carnap and Logical Truth”, in Schilpp 1963: 385–406.
  • –––, 1966, The Ways of Paradox, and Other Essays, New York: Random House.
  • –––, 1969, “Epistemology Naturalized”, in Quine, Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 69–90.
  • –––, 1991, “Two Dogmas in Retrospect”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 21(3): 265–274. doi:10.1080/00455091.1991.10717246
  • Radner, Michael and Stephen Winokur (eds.), 1970, Analyses of Theories and Methods of Physics and Psychology (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 4), Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
  • Ramharter, Esther (ed.), 2022, The Vienna Circle and Religion (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 25), Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-76151-6
  • Ramsey, Frank P., 1929, “Theories”, first published in his 1931, The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays (International Library of Psychology, Philosophy, and Scientific Method), R. B. Braithwaite (ed.), New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company, 212–236; reprinted in his Foundations: Essays in Philosophy, Logic, Mathematics and Economics, D. H. Mellor (ed.), London: Routledge, 1978, 101–125
  • Reichenbach, Hans, 1920, Relativitätstheorie und Erkenntnis apriori, Berlin: J. Springer; translated as The Theory of Relativity and A Priori Knowledge, Maria Reichenbach (trans.), Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1965.
  • –––, 1938, Experience and Prediction. An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press; reprinted Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2006.
  • –––, 1951, The Rise of Scientific Philosophy, Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.
  • Reisch, George A., 1991, “Did Kuhn Kill Logical Empiricism?”, Philosophy of Science, 58(2): 264–277. doi:10.1086/289615
  • –––, 2003, “Disunity within the International Encyclopedia of the Unity of Science”, in Hardcastle and Richardson 2003: 197–215.
  • –––, 2005, How the Cold War Transformed Philosophy of Science: To the Icy Slopes of Logic, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511610318
  • Reisch, George and Adam Tamas Tuboly, 2021, “Philipp Frank: A Crusader for Scientific Philosophy”, in Frank 2021: 1–67.
  • Rescher, Nicholas (ed.), 1985, The Heritage of logical Positivism, Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
  • Richardson, Alan W., 1990, “How Not to Russell Carnap’s Aufbau”, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1990(1): 2–14. doi:10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1990.1.192688
  • –––, 1994, “Carnap’s Principle of Tolerance, I: The Limits of Tolerance: Carnap’s Logico-Philosophical Project in Logical Syntax of Language”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 68: 67–82.
  • –––, 1997, “Two Dogmas about Logical Empiricism: Carnap and Quine on Logic, Epistemology, and Empiricism”, Philosophical Topics, 25(2): 145–168. doi:10.5840/philtopics19972523
  • –––, 1998, Carnap’s Construction of the World: The “Aufbau” and the Emergence of Logical Empiricism, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511570810
  • –––, 2002, “Narrating the History of Reason Itself: Friedman, Kuhn, and a Constitutive A Priori for the Twenty-First Century”, Perspectives on Science, 10(3): 253–274. doi:10.1162/106361402321899050
  • –––, 2003, “The Scientific World Conception: Logical Positivism”, in The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870–1945, Thomas Baldwin (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 391–400. doi:10.1017/CHOL9780521591041.032
  • –––, 2004, “Tolerating Semantics: Carnap’s Philosophical Point of View”, in Awodey and Klein 2004: 63–78.
  • –––, 2005, “‘The Tenacious, Malleable, Indefatigable, and Yet, Eternally Modifiable Will’: Hans Reichenbach’s Knowing Subject”, Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 79: 73–87. doi:10.1111/j.0309-7013.2005.00126.x
  • –––, 2006, “Introduction”, to Experience and Prediction, by Hans Reichenbach, 2006 edition, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. vii–xxxviii.
  • –––, 2008, “Scientific Philosophy as a Topic for History of Science”, Isis, 99(1): 88–96. doi:10.1086/587534
  • –––, 2013, “Taking the Measure of Carnap’s Philosophical Engineering: Metalogic as Metrology”, in The Historical Turn in Analytic Philosophy, Erich H. Reck (ed.), London: Palgrave Macmillan, 60–77.
  • –––, 2024, Logical Empiricism as Scientific Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781009471497
  • Richardson, Alan and Adam Tamas Tuboly (eds.), 2024, Interpreting Carnap: Critical Essays, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781009099080
  • Richardson, Alan W. and Thomas E. Uebel (eds.), 2007, The Cambridge Companion to Logical Empiricism (Cambridge Companions to Philosophy), Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CCOL0521791782
  • Ricketts, Thomas G., 1982, “Rationality, Translation, and Epistemology Naturalized”, The Journal of Philosophy, 79(3): 117–136. doi:10.2307/2026069
  • –––, 1994, “Carnap’s Principle of Tolerance, Empiricism and Conventionalism”, in Reading Putnam, Peter Clark and Bob Hale (eds.), Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 176–200.
  • –––, 1996, “Carnap: From Logical Syntax to Semantics”, in Giere and Richardson 1996: 231–250.
  • –––, 2003, “Languages and Calculi”, in Hardcastle and Richardson 2003: 257–280.
  • –––, 2010, “Quine’s Objection and Carnap’s Aufbau”, in Domski and Dickson 2010: 311–332.
  • Romizi, Donata, 2012, “The Vienna Circle’s ‘Scientific World-Conception’: Philosophy of Science in the Political Arena”, HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, 2(2): 205–242. doi:10.1086/666659
  • Romizi, Donata, Monika Wulz, and Elisabeth Nemeth (eds.), 2022, Edgar Zilsel: Philosopher, Historian, Sociologist (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 27), Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-93687-7
  • Rozeboom, William W., 1960, “A Note on Carnap’s Meaning Criterion”, Philosophical Studies, 11(3): 33–38. doi:10.1007/BF01324399
  • Rutte, Heiner, 1986, “Ethik und Werturteilsprobleme im Wiener Kreis”, in Nyíri 1986: 162–172; Translated as “Ethics and the Problem of Value in the Vienna Circle” in Uebel 1991: 143–158. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-3182-7_11 (English)
  • Ryckman, Thomas A., 1992, “‘P(oint)-C(oincidence) Thinking’: The Ironical Attachment of Logical Empiricism to General Relativity (and Some Lingering Consequences)”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 23(3): 471–497. doi:10.1016/0039-3681(92)90005-Q
  • –––, 2005, The Reign of Relativity: Philosophy in Physics, 1915–1925 (Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Science), Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0195177177.001.0001
  • –––, 2007, “Carnap and Husserl”, in Friedman and Creath 2007: 81–105. doi:10.1017/CCOL9780521840156.005
  • Salmon, Wesley, 1985, “Empiricism: The Key Question”, in Rescher 1985: 1–21.
  • –––, 2003, “Commit it then to the Flames…”, in Parrini, Salmon, and Salmon 2003: 375–387.
  • Salmon, Wesley C. and Gereon Wolters (eds.), 1994, Logic, Language, and the Structure of Scientific Theories: Proceedings of the Carnap-Reichenbach Centennial, University of Konstanz, 21–24 May 1991 (Pittsburgh-Konstanz Series in the History and Philosophy of Science), Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press/Universitätsverlag Konstanz.
  • Sarkar, Sahotra (ed.), 1992, Rudolf Carnap Centenary, special issue of Synthese, 93(1–2).
  • ––– (ed.), 1996, The Legacy of the Vienna Circle: Modern Reappraisals (Science and Philosophy in the Twentieth Century 6), New York: Garland Publishing.
  • –––, 2001, “Rudolf Carnap (1891–1970)”, in A Companion to Analytic Philosophy, A. P. Martinich and David Sosa (eds.), Oxford/Malden, MA: Blackwell, 94–109. doi:10.1002/9780470998656.ch7
  • –––, 2003, “Husserl’s Role in Carnap’s Der Raum”, in Bonk 2003: 179–190. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-0151-8_11
  • Sauer, Werner, 1989, “On the Kantian Background of Neopositivism”, Topoi, 8(2): 111–119. doi:10.1007/BF00141366
  • Schiemer, Georg (ed.), 2017, Carnap on Logic and Rationality, special issue of Synthese, 194(1).
  • Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.), 1963, The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (Library of Living Philosophers, Volume 11), LaSalle, IL: Open Court.
  • Schlick, Moritz, 1915, “Die philosophische Bedeutung des Relativitätsprinzips”, Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 159: 129–175; translated as “The Philosophical Significance of the Principle of Relativity” in Schlick 1979a: 153–189.
  • –––, 1917, Raum und Zeit in der gegenwärtigen Physik, Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer; third enlarged edition, Berlin: Springer, 1920; translated as Space and Time in Contemporary Physics: An Introduction to the Theory of Relativity and Gravitation, Henry L. Brose (trans.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1920; reprinted [with translation of revisions in the fourth edition] in Schlick 1979a: 207–269. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-41063-9 (1917, German)
  • –––, 1918/25, Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre, Berlin: Springer, 1918; second revised edition 1925. Second edition translated as General Theory of Knowledge (Library of Exact Philosophy 11), Albert E. Blumberg (trans.), New York: Springer-Verlag.
  • –––, 1921, “Kritizistische oder empiristiche Deutung der neuen Physik?”, Kant-Studien, 26(1–2): 96–111; translated as “Critical or Empiricist Interpretation of Modern Physics” in Schlick 1979a: 322–334. doi:10.1515/kant.1921.26.1-2.96 (German)
  • –––, 1922, “Die Relativitätstheorie in der Philosophie”, Verhandlungen der Gesellschaft deutscher Naturforscher und ärzte, 87: 58–69; translated as “The Theory of Relativity in Philosophy” in Schlick 1979a:. 343–353.
  • –––, 1926, “Erleben, Erkennen, Metaphysik”, Kant-Studien, 31(1–3): 146–158; translated as “Experience Cognition, Metaphysics”, by P. Heath (trans.), in Schlick 1979b:. 99–111. doi:10.1515/kant.1926.31.1-3.146 (German)
  • –––, 1930, “Die Wende der Philosophie”, Erkenntnis, 1: 4–11; translated as “The Turning Point in Philosophy” in Schlick 1979b: 154–160 [previously translated in Ayer 1959a: 53–59]. doi:10.1007/BF00208605 (German)
  • –––, 1931, “Die Kausalität in der gegenwärtigen Physik”, Die Naturwissenschaften, 19(7): 145–162; translated as “Causality in Contemporary Physics” in Schlick 1979b: 176–209. doi:10.1007/BF01516406
  • –––, 1932, “Positivismus und Realismus”, Erkenntnis, 3: 1–31; translated as “Positivism and Realism” in Schlick 1979b: 259–284 [previously transl. in Ayer 1959a: 82–107]. doi:10.1007/BF01886406 (German)
  • –––, 1934, “Über das Fundament der Erkenntnis”, Erkenntnis, 4: 79–99; translated as “The Foundation of Knowledge” in Schlick 1979b: 370–387 [previously translated in Ayer 1959a: 209–227]. doi:10.1007/BF01793485 (German)
  • –––, 1935a, “Facts and Propositions”, Analysis, 2(5): 65–70; reprinted in Schlick 1979b: 400–404. doi:10.1093/analys/2.5.65
  • –––, 1935b, “Sur les ‘Constatations’”, in his Sur le Fondament du Conaissance, Paris: Herman & Cie., Translated as “On ‘Affirmations’” in Schlick 1979b: 407–413.
  • –––, 1936a, “Meaning and Verification”, The Philosophical Review, 45(4): 339–369; reprinted in Schlick 1979b: 456–481. doi:10.2307/2180487
  • –––, 1936b, “Sind die Naturgesetze Konventionen?”, Actes du Congres International de Philosophie Scientifique, Paris 1935, Facs. IV, Induction et Probabilite, Paris: Herman & Cie., pp. 8–17; translated as “Are Natural Laws Conventions?” in Schlick 1979b: 437–445.
  • –––, 1937, “L’Ecole de Vienne et la Philosophie Traditionelle”, Travaux du IXeme Congres Internationale de Philosophie, Facs. IV, “L’unite de la Science: la Methode et les Methodes”, Paris: Heinman & Cie, pp. 99–107; translated as “The Vienna School and Traditional Philosophy” in Schlick 1979b: 491–498.
  • –––, 1979, Philosophical Papers (Vienna Circle Collection 11a), Henk L. Mulder and Barbara F. B. van de Velde-Schlick (eds.), Dordrecht: Reidel.
    • 1979a, Volume 1 (1909–1922)
    • 1979b, Volume 2 (1925–1936)
  • Schuster, Radek (ed.), 2020, The Vienna Circle in Czechoslovakia (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 23), Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-36383-3
  • Siegetsleitner, Anne, 2014, Ethik und Moral im Wiener Kreis: zur Geschichte eines engagierten Humanismus, Wien: Böhlau Verlag.
  • Sigmund, Karl, 1995, “A Philosopher’s Mathematician: Hans Hahn and the Vienna Circle”, The Mathematical Intelligencer, 17(4): 16–29. doi:10.1007/BF03024784
  • –––, 2015 [2017], Sie nannten sich Der Wiener Kreis: Exaktes Denken am Rand des Untergangs, Wiesbaden: Springer; translated as Exact Thinking in Demented Times. The Vienna Circle and the Epic Quest for the Foundations of Science, New York: Basic Books, 2017. doi:10.1007/978-3-658-08535-3 (German)
  • Smith, George E., 2002, “The Methodology of the Principia”, in The Cambridge Companion to Newton, I. Bernard Cohen and George E. Smith (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 138–173. doi:10.1017/CCOL0521651778.005
  • Soames, Scott, 2003, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, 2 vols., Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Spohn, Wolfgang (ed.), 1991, Special Volume in Honor of Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach, Erkenntnis, 35.
  • Stadler, Friedrich (ed.), 1993, Scientific Philosophy: Origins and Developments (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 1), Dordrecht: Kluwer. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-2964-2
  • –––, 1997 [2015b], Studien zum Wiener Kreis. Ursprung, Entwicklung und Wirkung des Logischen Empirismus im Kontext, Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp; second abbreviated and revised edition, Dordrecht: Springer, 2015a; translated as The Vienna Circle. Studies in the Origins, Development and Influence of logical Empiricism, Vienna/New York: Springer, 2001; second abbreviated and revised edition, Cham: Springer, 2015b.
  • –––, 1998, “The Vienna Circle”, C. Piller (trans.), in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Volume 9), Edward Craig (ed.), London: Routledge, pp. 606–616. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-DD076-1
  • ––– (ed.), 2003, The Vienna Circle and Logical Empiricism. Re-evaluation and Future Perspectives (Vienna Circle Institute yearbook 10), Dordrecht/Boston: Kluwer.
  • –––, 2008, “Paul Feyerabend and the Forgotten Third Vienna Circle”, in The Migration of Ideas, Roberto Scazzieri and Raffaella Simili (eds.), Sagamore Beach, MA: Science History Publications/USA, 203–244.
  • ––– (ed.), 2023, Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle: 100 Years after the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 28), Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-031-07789-0
  • Stadler, Friedrich, and Thomas Uebel (eds.), 2012, Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung. Der Wiener Kreis. Reprint of original Edition with Translations, Vienna: Springer.
  • Stein, Howard, 1992, “Was Carnap Entirely Wrong, After All?”, in Sarkar 1992: 275–296.
  • Stern, David, 2007, “Wittgenstein, the Vienna Circle, and Physicalism: A Reassessment”, in Richardson and Uebel 2007: 305–331. doi:10.1017/CCOL0521791782.013
  • Suppe, Frederick, 1977, “The Search for a Philosophical Understanding of Theories”, in The Structure of Scientific Theories, second edition, Frederick Suppe (ed.), Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, pp. 3–241.
  • Symons, John, Olga Pombo, and Juan Manuel Torres (eds.), 2011, Otto Neurath and the Unity of Science (Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science 18), Dordrecht: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-0143-4
  • Tarski, Alfred, 1933–35, “Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten Sprachen”, Studia Philosophica, 1 (1935): 261–405 [rev. and transl. of Polish original in Trav. Varsovie 34 (1933)]; translated as “The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages” in Tarski 1956: 152–278.
  • –––, 1936, “Über den Begriff der logischen Folgerung”, Actes du Congres Internationale de Philosophie Scientifique, Sorbonne, Paris 1935, Facs. VII, “Logique”, Paris: Hermann & Cie., pp. 1–12; translated as “The Concept of Logical Consequence” in Tarski 1956: 409–420.
  • –––, 1956, Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, J. H. Woodger (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press; second edition, J. Corcoran (ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983.
  • Tuboly, Adam Tamas (ed.), 2017, The Life and Work of Philipp Frank, special issue of Studies in East European Thought, 69(3).
  • ––– (ed.), 2021, The Historical and Philosophical Significance of Ayer’s “Language, Truth and Logic” (History of Analytic Philosophy), Cham: Palgrave Macmillan. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-50884-5
  • Uebel, Thomas E. (ed.), 1991, Rediscovering the Forgotten Vienna Circle: Austrian Studies on Otto Neurath and the Vienna Circle (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 133), Dordrecht/Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-3182-7
  • –––, 1992, Overcoming Logical Positivism from Within. The Emergence of Neurath’s Naturalism in the Vienna Circle’s Protocol Sentence Debate, Amsterdam-Atlanta, GA: Rodopi.
  • –––, 1996, “Anti-Foundationalism and the Vienna Circle’s Revolution in Philosophy”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 47(3): 415–440. doi:10.1093/bjps/47.3.415
  • –––, 2000, “Logical Empiricism and Sociology of Knowledge”, Philosophy of Science, 67: S138–150.
  • –––, 2003, “On the Austrian Roots of Logical Empiricism: The Case of the First Vienna Circle”, in Parrini, Salmon, and Salmon 2003: 67–93.
  • –––, 2004, “Carnap. the Left Vienna Circle, and Neopositivist Antimetaphysics”, in Awodey & Klein 2004: 247–278
  • –––, 2005a, “Political Philosophy of Science in Logical Empiricism: The Left Vienna Circle”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 36(4): 754–773. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2005.08.014
  • –––, 2005b, “Learning Logical Tolerance: Hans Hahn on the Foundations of Mathematics”, History and Philosophy of Logic, 26(3): 175–209. doi:10.1080/01445340500112108
  • –––, 2007, Empiricism at the Crossroads. The Vienna Circle’s Protocol-Sentence Debate, Chicago: Open Court.
  • –––, 2008, “Writing a Revolution: On the Production and Early Reception of the Vienna Circle’s Manifesto”, Perspectives on Science, 16(1): 70–102. doi:10.1162/posc.2008.16.1.70
  • –––, 2009, “Neurath’s Protocol Statements Revisited: Sketch of a Theory of Scientific Testimony”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 40(1): 4–13. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2008.12.001
  • –––, 2010, “What’s Right about Carnap, Neurath and the Left Vienna Circle Thesis: A Refutation”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41(2): 214–221. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2010.03.001
  • –––, 2011a, “Beyond the Formalist Criterion of Cognitive Significance: Philipp Frank’s Later Antimetaphysics”, HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, 1(1): 47–72. doi:10.1086/658918
  • –––, 2011b, “Carnap’s Ramseyfications Defended”, European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 1(1): 71–87. doi:10.1007/s13194-010-0003-5
  • –––, 2015a, “Three Challenges to the Complementarity of the Logic and the Pragmatics of Science”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 53: 23–32. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2015.05.002
  • –––, 2015b, “American Pragmatism and the Vienna Circle: The Early Years”, Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, 3(3): 35 pages. doi:10.15173/jhap.v3i3.39
  • –––, 2017, “Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle”, in A Companion to Wittgenstein, Hans‐Johann Glock and John Hyman (eds.), Chichester: Wiley, 699–717. doi:10.1002/9781118884607.ch46
  • –––, 2020a, “Intersubjective Accountability: Politics and Philosophy in the Left Vienna Circle”, Perspectives on Science, 28(1): 35–62. doi:10.1162/posc_a_00332
  • –––, 2020b, “Schlick and Wittgenstein: The Theory of Affirmations Revisited”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 58(1): 141–166. doi:10.1353/hph.2020.0007
  • –––, 2022, “The First Vienna Circle: What Kind of Formation Was It—And Why Does It Matter?”, in Romizi, Wulz, and Nemeth 2022: 361–379. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-93687-7_19
  • Uebel, Thomas and Christoph Limbeck-Lilienau (eds.), 2022, The Routledge Handbook of Logical Empiricism, London: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781315650647
  • Verhaegh, Sander, 2023, “Carnap and Quine: First Encounters (1932–1936)”, in Morris 2023: 11–31. doi:10.1017/9781108664202.003
  • Wagner, Pierre (ed.), 2009, Carnap’s Logical Syntax of Language, London: Palgrave Macmillan. doi:10.1057/9780230235397
  • ––– (ed.), 2012, Carnap’s Ideal of Explication and Naturalism, London: Palgrave Macmillan. doi:10.1057/9780230379749
  • Waismann, Friedrich, 1965, The Principles of Linguistic Philosophy, R. Harŕe (trans.), London: Macmillan.
  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1921, “Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung”, Annalen der Naturphilosophie u. K. Philosophie, 14, pp. 185–262; translated as Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, C. Ogden (trans.), London, 1922; revised edition 1933, reprinted London: Routledge, Kegen, Paul, 1983.
  • Woleński, Jan and Eckehart Köhler (eds.), 1999, Alfred Tarski and the Vienna Circle: Austro-Polish Connections in Logical Empiricism (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 6), Dordrecht/Boston: Kluwer. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-0689-6
  • Wolters, Gereon, 2003, “Carl Gustav Hempel: Pragmatic Empiricist”, in Parrini, Salmon, and Salmon 2003: 109–122.
  • Zilsel, Edgar, 1932, “Bemerkungen zur Wissenschaftslogik”, Erkenntnis, 3(1): 143–161. doi:10.1007/BF01886415
  • Zolo, Danilo, 1986, Scienza e Politica in Otto Neurath, Milano: Feltrinelli. Revised edition translated as Reflexive Epistemology. The Philosophical Legacy of Otto Neurath, Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1989. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-2415-4

Other Internet Resources

Acknowledgments

I received helpful comments on drafts for the original 2006 version of this entry and the updates since from more colleagues than can be listed here, but I wish to thank all of them sincerely.

Copyright © 2024 by
Thomas Uebel <Thomas.Uebel@manchester.ac.uk>

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.
The Encyclopedia Now Needs Your Support
Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free