This is a file in the archives of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. |
Inconsistent Mathematics began historically with foundational considerations. Set-theoretic paradoxes such as Russell's led to attempts to produce a consistent set theory as a foundation for mathematics. But, as is well known, set theories such as ZF, NBG and the like were in various ways ad hoc. Hence, a number of people including da Costa (1974), Brady (1971), Priest, Routley, and Norman (1989), considered it preferable to retain the full power of the natural abstraction principle (every predicate determines a set), and tolerate a degree of inconsistency in set theory. This requires, of course, that one dispense with the logical principle ex contradictione quodlibet (ECQ) (from a contradiction every proposition may be deduced), as well as any principle which leads to it, such as disjunctive syllogism (DS) (from A-or-B and not-A deduce B). But considerable debate, in Burgess (1981) and Mortensen (1983), made it clear that dispensing with ECQ and DS was not so counter-intuitive, especially when a plausible story emerged about the special conditions under which they continue to hold.
In addition, mathematics has a metalanguage; that is, names for mathematical statements and other parts of syntax, self-reference, proof and truth. Godel's contribution to the philosophy of mathematics was to show that the first three of these can be rigorously expressed in arithmetical theories, albeit in theories which are either inconsistent or incomplete. The possibility of a well-structured example of the former alternative was not taken seriously, again because of belief in ECQ. However, in addition natural languages seem to have their own truth predicate. Combined with self-reference this produces the Liar paradox, "This sentence is false", an inconsistency. Priest (1987) and Priest, Routley, and Norman (1989) argued that the Liar had to be regarded as a statement both true and false, a true contradiction. This represents another argument for studying inconsistent theories, namely the claim that some contradictions are true. Kripke (1975) proposed instead to model a truth predicate differently, in a consistent incomplete theory. We see below that incompleteness and inconsistency are closely related.
But mathematics is not its foundations. Hence there is a further independent motive, to see what mathematical structure remains when the constraint of consistency is relaxed. But it would be wrong to regard this as in any way a loss of structure. If it is different at all, then it represents an addition to known structure.
Robert K. Meyer (1976) seems to have been the first to think of an inconsistent arithmetical theory. At this point, he was more interested in the fate of a consistent theory, his relevant arithmetic R#. There proved to be a whole class of inconsistent arithmetical theories; see Meyer and Mortensen (1984), for example. Meyer argued that these theories provide the basis for a revived Hilbert Program. Hilbert's program was widely held to have been seriously damaged by Godel's Second Incompleteness Theorem, according to which the consistency of arithmetic was unprovable within arithmetic itself. But a consequence of Meyer's construction was that within his arithmetic R# it was demonstrable by simple finitary means that whatever contradictions there might happen to be, they could not adversely affect any numerical calculations. Hence Hilbert's goal of conclusively demonstrating that mathematics is trouble-free proves largely achievable. The arithmetical models used later proved to allow inconsistent representation of the truth predicate. They also permit representation of structures beyond natural number arithmetic, such as rings and fields, including their order properties.
One could hardly ignore the examples of analysis and its special
case, the calculus. There prove to be many places where there are
distinctive inconsistent insights; see Mortensen (1995) for
example. (1) Robinson's non-standard analysis was based on
infinitesimals, quantities smaller than any real number, as well as
their reciprocals, the infinite numbers. This has an inconsistent
version, which has some advantages for calculation in being able to
discard higher-order infinitesimals. Interestingly, the theory of
differentiation turned out to have these advantages, while the theory
of integration did not. (2) Another place is topology, where one
readily observes the practice of cutting and pasting spaces being
described as "identification" of one boundary with another. One can
show that this can be described in an inconsistent theory in which the
two boundaries are both identical and not identical, and it can be
further argued that this is the most natural description of the
practice. (3) Yet another application is the class of inconsistent
continuous functions. Not all functions which are classically
discontinuous are amenable of inconsistent treatment; but some are,
for example f(x)=0 for all x<0 and f(x)=1 for all
x0. The inconsistent extension replaces the first
< by
, and has distinctive structural
properties. These inconsistent functions may well have some
application in dynamic systems in which there are discontinuous jumps,
such as quantum measurement systems. Differentiating such functions
leads to the delta functions, applied by Dirac to the study of quantum
measurement also. (4) Next, there is the well-known case of
inconsistent systems of linear equations, such as the system (i)
x+y=1, plus (ii) x+y=2. Such systems can potentially arise within the
context of automated control. Little work has been done classically
to solve such systems, but it can be shown that there are well-behaved
solutions within inconsistent vector spaces. (5) Finally, one can note
a further application in topology and dynamics. Given a supposition
which seems to be conceivable, namely that whatever happens or is
true, happens or is true on an open set of (spacetime) points, one has
that the logic of dynamically possible paths is open set logic, that
is to say intuitionist logic, which supports incomplete theories par
excellence. This is because the natural account of the negation of a
proposition in such a space says that it holds on the largest open set
contained in the Boolean complement of the set of points on which the
original proposition held, which is in general smaller than the
Boolean complement. However, specifying a topological space by its
closed sets is every bit as reasonable as specifying it by its open
sets. Yet the logic of closed sets is known to be paraconsistent,
ie. supports inconsistent theories; see Goodman (1981) for example.
Thus given the (alternative) supposition which also seems to be
conceivable, namely that whatever is true is true on a closed set of
points, one has that inconsistent theories may well hold. This is
because the natural account of the negation of a proposition, namely
that it holds on the smallest closed set containing the Boolean
negation of the proposition, means that on the overlapping boundary
both the proposition and its negation hold. Thus dynamical theories
determine their own logic of possible propositions, and corresponding
theories which may be inconsistent, and are certainly as natural as
their incomplete counterparts.
Category theory throws light on many mathematical structures. However, when there are consistency problems for category theory as a foundation for mathematics, which certainly has been proposed. Hence there is the same possible application of inconsistent solutions. There is also an important collection of categorial structures, the toposes, which support open set logic in exact parallel to the way sets support Boolean logic. This has been taken by many to be a vindication of the foundational point of view of mathematical intuitionism. However, it can be proved that that toposes support closed set logic as readily as they support open set logic. That should not be viewed as an objection to intuitionism, however, so much as an argument that inconsistent theories are equally reasonable as items of mathematical study.
Duality between incompleteness/intuitionism and inconsistency/paraconsistency has at least two aspects. First there is the above topological (open/closed) duality. Second there is Routley * duality. Discovered by the Routleys (1972) as a semantical tool for relevant logics, the * operation dualises between inconsistent and incomplete theories of the large natural class of de Morgan logics. Both kinds of duality interact as well, where the * gives distinctive duality and invariance theorems for open set and closed set arithmetical theories. On the basis of these results, it is fair to argue that both kinds of mathematics, intuitionist and paraconsistent, are equally reasonable.
These constructions do not in any way challenge or repudiate existing mathematics, but extend our conception of what is mathematically possible.
First published: July 2, 1996
Content last modified: January 9, 1997