Nonexistent Objects
Are there nonexistent objects, i.e., objects that do not exist? Some examples often cited are: Zeus, Pegasus, Sherlock Holmes, Vulcan (the hypothetical planet postulated by the 19th century astronomer Le Verrier), the perpetual motion machine, the golden mountain, the fountain of youth, the round square, etc. Some important philosophers have thought that the very concept of a nonexistent object is contradictory (Hume) or logically ill-formed (Kant, Frege), while others (Leibniz, Meinong, the Russell of Principles of Mathematics) have embraced it wholeheartedly.
One of the reasons why there are doubts about the concept of a nonexistent object is this: to be able to say truly of an object that it doesn’t exist, it seems that one has to presuppose that it exists, for doesn’t a thing have to exist if we are to make a true claim about it? In the face of this puzzling situation, one has to be very careful when accepting or formulating the idea that there are nonexistent objects. It turns out that Kant’s view that “exists” is not a “real” predicate and Frege’s view, that “exists” is not a predicate of individuals (i.e., a predicate that yields a well-formed sentence if one puts a singular term in front of it), has to be abandoned if one is to accept the claim that there are nonexistent objects.
This entry is an examination of the many questions which arise in connection with the view that there are nonexistent objects. The following are particularly salient: What reasons are there (if any) for thinking that there are nonexistent objects? If there are nonexistent objects, then what kind of objects are they? How can they be characterized? Is it possible to provide a consistent theory of nonexistent objects? What is the explanatory force of a consistent theory of nonexistent objects (if such a thing is possible)?
- 1. The Concept of a Nonexistent Object
- 2. Historical Roots: Alexius Meinong and the Problem of Intentionality
- 3. Further Motivations for Belief in Nonexistent Objects
- 4. Problems with Belief in Nonexistent Objects
- 5. Contemporary Theories of Nonexistent Objects: From Nonexistence to Abstractness
- 6. Themes for Further Investigation
- Bibliography
- Academic Tools
- Other Internet Resources
- Related Entries
1. The Concept of a Nonexistent Object
The very concept of a “nonexistent object” has an air of paradox about it, at least for those philosophers whose thinking is rooted in the Humean tradition. For Hume suggested that to think of an object is always and necessarily to think of an existent object, or to put it differently, that to think of an object and to think of the same object as existing are just one and the same thing. Immanuel Kant took up Hume’s idea and claimed that existence is not a “real predicate”, a claim that is often interpreted as an anticipation of Gottlob Frege’s famous doctrine that existence is not a predicate of individuals. (See Hume 2000, Book 1, Part 2, Sect. 6; Kant 2003, B 627; Frege 1966, pp. 37f.) Kant’s motivation for rejecting the view that existence is a “real predicate” was the so-called “ontological proof” of God’s existence, which says, roughly, that God’s perfection entails God’s existence, since a being that would have all of God’s perfections except existence (i.e., omniscience, omnipotence, benevolence) would be less perfect than a being with the same perfections plus existence. For centuries, philosophers have felt that there is something wrong with this proof, but Kant was the first one who was able to point out a possible error: he argued that the mistake of the “ontological argument” lies in the treatment of existence as a “real predicate”.
If Hume is right, then the concept of an object includes the concept of existence, and the concept of a nonexistent object would be as self-contradictory as the concept of a round square. If existence is not a predicate of individuals, then one might suppose that neither is nonexistence. Therefore, if Frege is right, to say of an object that it is nonexistent is a kind of nonsense that arises from a violation of logical grammar. (For Frege and those who follow him, a claim like “God exists/does not exist” is to be understood as a claim about the concept God, or about the property of being God. On this view, the logical form of “God exists” is not Exists (God)—where Exists is a predicate of individuals, but rather: The concept God applies to something, or Something possesses the property of being God.)
Thus, in order to take the idea of nonexistent objects seriously, one has to give up views held by important philosophers about the nature of existence and adopt the view that existence is some kind of predicate of individuals. This view entails, among other things, that to say, for instance, that some white elephants exist is to say that some white elephants have the property of existence (or, to put it the other way around, that not all white elephants are nonexistent)—a consequence that might strike some as strange.
Furthermore, in order to assert “there are nonexistent objects” without implying “nonexistent objects exist”, one has to suppose that sentences of the form “There are Fs” mean something different from sentences of the form “Fs exist”.[1] Some philosophers reject a distinction between “there is” and “exists” (see, for instance, Lewis 1990, Priest 2005, Quine 1953), some philosophers (e.g., Meinong 1960, Parsons 1980, Zalta 1988) think that there are good reasons for making this distinction. Some of the latter think that the distinction between “there is” and “exists” is rooted in ordinary language, but others deny this firmly (see, for instance, Geach 1971). Obviously, although there might be a tendency among competent English speakers to use “there is” and “exists” in different contexts, ordinary language use is too wavering and non-uniform in this respect to be a stable ground for a philosophical theory. Of course, this does not rule out that there are theoretical reasons for a distinction between “there is” and “exists”, some of which are discussed below.
1.1 The Logics of Nonexistent Objects
In those logics that stand in the Frege-Quine tradition, both “there is” and “exists” are expressed by means of the “existential quantifier” (“∃”), which is, consequently, interpreted as having “ontological import”. Thus, in these formal systems, there is no means to distinguish between “there is” and “exists”. However, it has been shown that the distinction between the two can be coherently regimented in various ways. In the systems of Terence Parsons, Edward N. Zalta and Dale Jacquette, for instance, “there is an x such that … x…” is expressed by “∃x(…x…)”, whereas “there exists an x such that … x…” is expressed by “∃x(E!x & …x…)”, where “E!” is the existence predicate (Parsons 1980, Zalta 1983, Zalta 1988, Jacquette 1996). “Some things do not exist” could thus be rendered in logical notation as follows: “∃x(¬E!x)”; “Pegasus does not exist” as “¬E!p”; and so forth.
Graham Priest (2005) has proposed a theory of nonexistent objects that treats “there is” and “exists” as synonyms. He interprets quantification as utterly ontologically neutral. The quantifier should express neither “there is” nor “there exists”. Rather, quantifier expressions should be read “For some x, …x…”, where “For some x, …x…” does not imply that “there is (or exists) an x such that …x…”.
Thus, Priest belongs to those philosophers who distinguish between “quantifier commitment” and “ontological commitment” (see Azzouni 2004), claiming that to “quantifier over” objects of a certain kind does not entail an ontological commitment to objects of this kind.[2]
The various logics of nonexistent objects cannot be described and discussed here in detail. However, it is now clear that there is no formal obstacle to a theory of nonexistent objects. The only questions are philosophical: can the concepts that such theories aim to formalize be explained, and do we have good reason to accept a theory formulated in these terms? In the following two sections, the main motivations for believing in nonexistent objects are delineated.
2. Historical Roots: Alexius Meinong and the Problem of Intentionality
Philosophical writings on nonexistent objects in the 20th and 21st century usually take as their starting point the so-called “theory of objects” of the Austrian philosopher Alexius Meinong (1853–1920). Therefore, it is appropriate to give an outline of the basic principles of and motives behind this theory. (For a detailed presentation see the entry on Meinong.)
Meinong was concerned about the problem of intentional states which are not directed at anything existent. The starting point of this problem is the so-called “principle of intentionality”, which says that mental phenomena are characterized by an “intentional directedness” towards an object. For instance, to love is always to love something, to imagine is always to imagine something, and so forth. In other words, every intentional act is “about” something. The problem is that sometimes people imagine, desire or fear things that do not exist. Some people fear the devil, although the devil doesn’t exist. Many people hope for peace in the Middle East. But there is no peace in the Middle East. Ponce the Leon searched for the fountain of youth, even though it doesn’t exist. It is easy to imagine a golden mountain, even if no such thing exists.
Cases like these seem to be clear counterexamples to the principle of intentionality. However, many philosophers found this principle too appealing to be given up completely. While some came to the conclusion that intentionality is not a real relation and therefore does not require the existence of an object (see, for instance, Brentano 1874, Prior 1971, Searle 1983, Crane 2013), Meinong offered another solution: there is indeed an object for every mental state whatsoever—if not an existent object then at least a nonexistent one.[3]
The problem of intentionality may still count as one of the most important motivations for thinking there are nonexistent objects.[4] But there are other motivations as well.
3. Further Motivations for Belief in Nonexistent Objects
3.1 The Problem of Negative Singular Existence Statements
Very briefly, the problem can be stated as follows: it seems that in order to deny the existence of a given individual, one must assume the existence of that very individual. Thus, it seems that it is impossible to deny the existence of an individual without getting involved in a contradiction.
However, this conclusion seems hard to accept. In fact, there are many negative existence statements that we take not only to be sensible but also to be true (or at least not to be necessarily false). Consider, for instance:
Pegasus does not exist.
Yugoslavia does not exist anymore.
The perpetual motion machine does not exist and never will exist.
From the common sense point of view, negative singular existence statements are ubiquitous, comprehensible and sometimes true. So why is it that many philosophers are so puzzled about them? In particular, why think one has to assume the existence of an individual in order to deny its existence?
One traditional reason that has been given is based on the following assumptions:
- Only meaningful sentences can be true.
- In a meaningful sentence, every constituent of the sentence must be meaningful.
- If a singular term is meaningful, then it denotes something.
- If a singular term “b” denotes something, then “b does not exist” is false.
Let’s see how these assumptions lead to a problem in light of the negative singular existence sentence “Pegasus does not exist”. If “Pegasus does not exist” is true, then it must be meaningful (by (1) above). If it is meaningful, all of its constituents must be meaningful, including the singular term “Pegasus” (by (2) above). If “Pegasus” is meaningful, then “Pegasus” denotes something (by (3) above). If “Pegasus” denotes something, then “Pegasus does not exist” is false (by (4) above). Thus, the assumption that “Pegasus does not exist” is true leads to the conclusion that this same sentence is false. So if the above premises are correct, it is impossible that “Pegasus does not exist” is true: either “Pegasus” denotes something, in which case “Pegasus does not exist” is false; or “Pegasus” does not denote anything, in which case “Pegasus does not exist” is not even meaningful, let alone true.
There are several ways to resolve this problem, i.e., to account for meaningful and true negative singular existence sentences. One solution that became very prominent in the 20th century consists in the strategy of “analyzing away” the proper names and definite descriptions appearing in negative singular existential claims. This strategy consists of two steps:
- Ordinary proper names are interpreted as disguised definite descriptions. For instance, “Pegasus” is to be analyzed as short for “the flying horse from Greek mythology”. This is often called the description theory of proper names. Thus to say “Pegasus exists” is simply to say “the flying horse of Greek mythology exists”.
- Definite descriptions are to be analyzed along the lines of Bertrand Russell’s theory of definite descriptions. On Russell’s theory, to say “the flying horse of Greek mythology exists” is to say “there is exactly one x which is a flying horse of Greek mythology”.
Thus, combining these two steps, it follows that:
- To say “Pegasus doesn’t exist” is to say “it is not the case that there is exactly one x which is a flying horse of Greek mythology”.[5]
If “Vulcan” is short for “the planet between Mercury and the sun”, then:
- To say “Vulcan doesn’t exist” is to say “it is not the case that there is exactly one x which is such that x is a planet between Mercury and the sun”.
The point of these paraphrases is to show that the original sentences can be analyzed in terms of sentences in which the singular terms (“Pegasus”, “Vulcan”, “the flying horse of Greek mythology” and “the planet between Mercury and the sun”) have all disappeared. The paraphrases involve the general terms “flying horse from Greek mythology” and “planet between Mercury and the sun”, along with the existential quantifier (“there is”) and a uniqueness condition (“exactly one”). (Let’s ignore the fact that the singular terms “Mercury” and “Le Verrier” appear within the general terms; of course, this means that the procedure isn’t complete, but, in principle, it can be completed.) The problem of negative singular existentials is thereby resolved because sentences containing names which appear to be about nonexistent objects are paraphrased in terms of sentences involving general terms, quantifiers and uniqueness conditions. These latter sentences are meaningful independently of whether the general terms apply to anything.
However, both the description theory of proper names and Russell’s theory of definite descriptions have been subject to serious criticisms. One might object that they fail to do full justice to our actual use of proper names and definite descriptions. Often we use proper names—successfully—without having any definite description in mind. Sometimes we don’t need a definite description in order to refer to a particular object, because we individuate the respective object by means of perception or perceptual memories. Sometimes we simply do not know of a definite description that individuates the object we wish to refer to. Most of us know about Cicero just that he was a famous Roman orator; but the Romans had more than one famous orator. Nevertheless, we can use the name “Cicero” successfully to refer to a particular famous Roman orator. Moreover, even when we do have something like the mental correlate of a definite description in mind when we use a proper name, we do not usually treat the description as a definition of the proper name (as the Russellian picture suggests). Suppose what I have in mind when I use the name “Socrates” corresponds to the description “the ancient Greek philosopher who died from drinking hemlock”. Suppose furthermore that the famous story about Socrates’ death is actually a myth and that Socrates in fact died peacefully of old age. Do I then simply fail to refer to Socrates whenever I use the name “Socrates”? It does not seem so. When I eventually come to know that Socrates did not die from drinking hemlock, I will take this as a piece of information about Socrates, the person I referred to all the time by using the name “Socrates”. (See Kripke 1980.)
As to the theory of definite descriptions, two kinds of problem arise. First, some philosophers simply deny that the paraphrases properly capture the meaning of sentences with definite descriptions, simply on the grounds that the meaning of a proper name like “Pegasus” is just less specific than the meaning of the definite description “the flying horse of Greek mythology”. Second, some philosophers have objected that the theory of definite descriptions sometimes yields the wrong results. Consider, for instance: “The ancient Greeks worshipped Zeus.” Prima facie, this sentence expresses a real relation between the ancient Greeks and Zeus; and it is surely a historical fact that the ancient Greeks worshipped Zeus. Yet on Russell’s analysis, proper names like “Zeus” have to be replaced by definite descriptions, even in contexts other than existence claims. So “Zeus” would get replaced by a definite description like “the Greek god who lived on Mt. Olympus and who …”. Thus, the above true sentence would get analyzed in terms of the following false one: “There exists one and only one Greek god who lived on Mt. Olympus and who … and who was such that the ancient Greeks worshipped him.” There are numerous other true sentences like this, such as “Sherlock Holmes is more famous than any real detective”, etc., all of which appear to involve real relations between existent objects and nonexistent ones, but whose Russellian paraphrases are false. Third, the use of the anaphoric pronoun “it” in “Teams of scientists have searched for the Loch Ness monster, but since it doesn’t exist, no one will ever find it” seems problematic. The pronoun in both of its occurrences in this sentence seems to pick up its meaning/denotation from the definite description “the Loch Ness monster”—which is not easy to explain given Russell’s theory of definite descriptions.
There might be ways to defend the theory of definite descriptions, but they will not be pursued here. In the context of this article, the relevant point is that Russell’s theory does not provide a generally accepted solution to the problem of negative existence sentences. The appeal to nonexistent objects, on the other hand, provides a very simple solution to this problem. It consists in rejecting the premise
- If a singular term “b” denotes something, then “b does not exist” is false.
If there are nonexistent objects, then “b” may denote an object that does not exist.
The idea here is that whereas the quantifiers “there is” and “something” range over everything whatsoever, the objects that exist constitute only a portion of that domain. Therefore, it would be fallacious to derive from “‘b’ denotes something” that “b” denotes something that exists. According to this picture, “Pegasus does not exist” simply expresses that Pegasus is a nonexistent object. Premises 1–3 from above can be accepted without restriction. “Pegasus” denotes a nonexistent flying horse and thus is meaningful. Thus, the whole sentence “Pegasus does not exist” is meaningful as well. Since it is true that Pegasus does not belong to the class of existent objects, “Pegasus does not exist” is true. Of course, this solution can be generalized to all negative singular existence statements. The appeal to nonexistent objects thus supplies an elegant solution to the problem of negative singular existentials.
Naturally, there are alternative solutions to the problem of negative singular existence statements. Among other things, it is possible to reject premise 4 without committing oneself to an ontology of nonexistent objects. One might simply accept a positive Free Logic, i.e., the conjunction of the following two principles: 1. Singular terms do not need to denote anything in order to be meaningful. 2. Sentences containing non-denoting singular terms can be true. (This strategy is to be found, for instance, in Crane 2013.) One of the difficulties of this solution, however, is to give an account of what makes such sentences true, i.e., of what their truthhmakers are (given the principle that, for every true sentence, there is something in the world that makes it true, i.e., something that is the sentence’s truthmaker). For the special case of negative singular existence sentences, one might claim that that their truthmaker is just the entire world (see, e.g., Crane 2013, Section 3.5; for more about Crane’s position see Section 5.1 below). However, this answer to the truthmaker question is not available for the problem of fictional discourse, which provides another important motivation for a commitment to nonexistent objects.
3.2 The Problem of Fictional Discourse
By “fictional discourse” we mean here and in what follows discourse about fictitious objects. Sometimes, the term “fictitious object” is used as synonymous with “nonexistent object”. Here, the term is used in a different sense, namely for objects (characters, things, events etc.) which occur in fictions, i.e., in myths or fairy tales, in fictional novels, movies, operas etc. Pegasus is a fictitious object in this sense (as are Sherlock Holmes and Hamlet) but Vulcan (the hypothetical planet sought by Le Verrier) is not.
Consider, for instance, the sentence
(1) Pegasus is a flying horse.
Like many other sentences of fictional discourse, it appears to fulfill the following three conditions:
- It has the grammatical structure of a predication, i.e., the structure that is rendered in logical notation by “Fb” (where “F” stands for a predicate expression—here: “is a flying horse”—and “b” stands for a singular term—here: “Pegasus”).
- The singular term in subject position is a name for a fictitious object.
- It is commonly, and with good reason, taken to be true.
The problem of fictional discourse is closely connected to two logical principles. The first one is well known as “the principle of existential generalization”:
Existential Generalization (EG):
Fb → ∃x(Fx), i.e.,
If b is F, then there is something that is F.[6]
The second principle is less prominent, rather seldom explicitly stated, but often tacitly assumed. We call it “the predication principle”:
Predication Principle (PP):
Fb → ∃x(x = b).[7]
(PP) may be read in two ways:
(PPa) If b is F, then there is something that is identical with b.(PPb) If b is F, then b exists.
Both principles are prima facie extremely plausible: If it is true of some individual that the predicate “F” applies to it, then the predicate “F” applies to something. If some predicate “F” applies to an individual, then the individual has to exist (for if it were otherwise, how could the predicate apply to it?).
Yet, when applied to fictional discourse, these two principles lead to consequences that seem to contradict hard empirical facts on the one hand and trivial truths about the ontological status of fictitious objects on the other. According to (EG), the sentence
(1) Pegasus is a flying horse.
implies
(2) There are flying horses.
Yet, as we all know, there are no flying horses.
According to (PP),
(1) Pegasus is a flying horse.
implies
(3) Pegasus exists.
But Pegasus is a fictitious object; and it seems that to call an object fictitious is just to say that it does not exist.
The problem is that obviously true sentences of fictional discourse seem to lead into outright contradictions. Of course, there are several ways to avoid the contradictions. One of them consists in rejecting the principles (EG) and (PP). By this move, one blocks the inference from “Pegasus is a flying horse” to “There are flying horses” and “Pegasus exists”. Indeed, some logicians, notably proponents of Free Logics, take this path. (See Crane 2013, Hintikka 1959, Lambert 1983 and 1991, Leonard 1956.)[8] Again (as with the case of negative singular existence statements) this raises the question of what the truthmakers of such sentences are. There are attempts to answer this question in a “reductionist” fashion, i.e., to claim that sentences about fictitious objects are made true not by fictitious objects but by something else, e.g., by literary works, myths, stories or facts about these, respectively.[9]
Another way to avoid the contradictions would be simply to reject the sentence “Pegasus is a flying horse” (and, in general, all alleged predications about fictitious objects) as false or untrue. This radical solution, however, fails to do justice to the widespread intuition that there is a difference in truth-value between “Pegasus is a flying horse” and, say, “Pegasus is a flying dog”.
A third attempt to resolve the problem is what may be called “the story-operator strategy”. According to the story-operator strategy, we have to interpret sentences of fictional discourse as incomplete. A complete rendition of, for instance,
(1) Pegasus is a flying horse.
would be as follows:
(1′) According to the story S (where “S” here and in what follows stands for the story of Greek mythology): Pegasus is a flying horse.
The expression “according to the story S” is the so-called “story operator”,[10] which is a sentence operator (that is, it is the sentence as a whole that is in its scope, not just a part of the sentence, for instance the predicate). While the sentence within the scope of the story operator (here: “Pegasus is a flying horse”) may be false when taken in isolation, the complete sentence may be true. (This strategy is developed in detail in Künne 1990.)
Sentence (1′) does not imply that there are flying horses; neither does it imply that Pegasus exists. Thus, the contradictions are avoided.[11] This looks like an elegant solution, at least as long as we confine ourselves to a particular kind of example. Unfortunately, however, it does not work equally well for all kinds of sentences of fictional discourse. Consider, for instance:
(4) Pegasus is a character from Greek mythology.
This sentence seems to be straightforwardly true; but if we put a story operator in front of it, we get a straightforward falsehood:
(4′) According to the story S: Pegasus is a character from Greek mythology.
It is not true that according to the relevant story, Pegasus is a character. Rather, according to this story, Pegasus is a living being of flesh and blood.
One may call sentences like “Pegasus is a flying horse” or “Hamlet hates his stepfather” “internal sentences of fictional discourse”, in distinction from external sentences of fictional discourse, like “Pegasus is a character from Greek mythology” or “Hamlet has fascinated many psychoanalysts”. The story operator strategy can be applied to internal sentences only and thus fails as a general solution to the problem of fictional discourse.[12]
The claim that there are nonexistent objects provides a solution that can be applied uniformly both to internal and external sentences of fictional discourse. It allows us to admit that fictitious objects do not exist but at the same time to acknowledge that there are fictitious objects. According to this position, fictitious objects are just a species of nonexistent objects.
In order to see how this assumption is supposed to avoid the contradictions spelled out above, consider:
- Pegasus is a flying horse.[13]
- There are flying horses. (1, EG)
- There are no flying horses.
According to the Meinongian solution, premise 3 has to be rejected as false. The Meinongian grants that flying horses do not exist, but this does not imply that there are no flying horses. According to the Meinongian, there are flying horses, and they belong to the class of nonexistent objects, and Pegasus is one of them. Premise 3 may be replaced by
3′. Flying horses do not exist.
But this does not contradict
2. There are flying horses.
Thus, the problem is solved.[14]
Consider next:
- Pegasus is a flying horse.
- Pegasus exists. (1, PP)
- Pegasus is a fictitious object.
- Fictitious objects do not exist.
- Pegasus doesn’t exist. (3, 4)
In this case, the Meinongian solution consists in rejecting premise 2. The Meinongian cannot accept 2, since Pegasus is supposed to be a nonexistent object.
What, then, about the predication principle? Does the Meinongian have to reject it?—Not necessarily. Remember that (PP) can be read in (at least) two ways:
(PPa) If b is F, then there is something that is identical with b.(PPb) If b is F, then b exists.
Within the Meinongian framework, these two readings are not equivalent. According to the Meinongian, certainly there is something that is identical with Pegasus, although Pegasus does not exist. Thus, the Meinongian must reject the reading (PPb), but she can (and does) accept the reading (PPa).[15]
Since the Meinongian accepts only the weaker version (PPa) of the predication principle, the inference from premise 1 (“Pegasus is a flying horse”) to “Pegasus exists” is blocked. All that can be derived from premise 1 is the weaker claim
2′. There is something that is identical with Pegasus.
But this is not in conflict with “Pegasus does not exist”. Thus, the problem is resolved.
Alternatively, one may abstain from the Meinongian distinction between being and existence and hold that fictitious objects are existent abstract objects. According to this position, “Pegasus does not exist” has to be rejected as false, and thus, again, the contradiction is avoided. This position (it might be called “abstractionism with respect to fictitious objects”) comes in two varieties. The first one might be characterized, in a somewhat simplified fashion, as follows: To every set of properties, there is/exists a corresponding abstract object. These abstract objects exist necessarily. Some of them occur in fictional stories, and these are what we call “fictitious objects”. Thus, fictitious objects are necessarily existent objects that have been somehow “discovered” or “selected” by the authors of fictional stories. (For this position, see, for instance, Parsons 1975, Zalta 1983 and 1988, Jacquette 1996, Berto 2008 and Priest 2011. Actually, this is one of the applications of contemporary versions of Meinongianism. See Sections 5.4 and 5.5 below.) According to the other variety of abstractionism, fictitious objects are abstract artefacts, i.e., they are not discovered or selected but created by the authors of fictional stories.[16]
The latter view (today often referred to as “creationism”) fits well into a general ontology of abstract artefacts (like, for instance, literary and other works of fiction as well as non-fictional cultural entities) and does justice to the intuition that fictitious objects as well as the works in which they occur are literally brought into being through human acts of creation. However, it is objected against creationism that the creation of an abstract object is something deeply mysterious.
3.3 The Problem of Discourse about the Past and the Future
The structure of the problem of discourse about the past and the future is very similar to the structure of the problem of fictional discourse. Consider the following sentences:
(1) Socrates was a philosopher.(2) The first female pope will be black.
Given that the sentences (1) and (2) have the logical structure of predications, i.e., the structure “Fb”, and given that (PP) is valid, (1) implies that Socrates exists and (2) implies that the first female pope exists.
Indeed, the sentences (1) and (2) look like predications. Grammatically speaking, they consist of a subject term (“Socrates”, “the first female pope”) and a predicate term (“was a philosopher”, “will be black”.) But while it is certainly true now (in the third millennium C.E.) that Socrates was a philosopher, it is also certainly true now that Socrates does not exist anymore.
Second, let’s assume, for the sake of argument, that indeed there will be a female pope (and exactly one first female pope) at some time in the far future and that she will be black and that she has not even been fathered yet. Given these assumptions, it is certainly true now that the first female pope does not yet exist.
Again, there are several attempts to resolve this problem. One possible strategy is to deny that sentences like (1) and (2) really have the logical structure of predications. One might suggest the following alternative interpretations, using “P” (read: “It has been the case”) and “F” (read: “It will be the case”) as “tense operators”:
(1′) P(Socrates is a philosopher).(2′) F(The first female pope is black).
Note that the tense operators “P” and “F” are sentence operators, like the story operator from above. Just as the story operator blocks the inference to existence claims about fictitious objects, the tense operators block the inference from (1′) to
(3) Socrates exists.
and from (2′) to
(4) The first female pope exists. (For a tense operator strategy see Prior 1968.)
There is a lot to be said in favor of this logical interpretation of tenses. Yet, it leaves some problems unresolved. One of them is the problem of tensed plural quantifiers. Consider, for instance:
(5) There have been two kings named Charles.
The standard tense operator interpretation of (5) yields:
(5′) P(There are two kings named Charles).
However, while (5) is true, (5′) is false, since at no time in the past there have been two kings named Charles simultaneously. (See Lewis 2004.) Thus, the standard tense operator strategy seems to fail in cases like this one.
Another problem that the tense operator strategy leaves unresolved is the problem of relations between present and non-present objects. Given the principle that a real (two-place) relation can obtain only if both terms of the relation exist, and given that past and future objects do not (now) exist, relations between present and past or future objects are impossible. Yet it seems that there are plenty of relations between present and past (or future) objects. For instance, I stand in the relation of being one of six granddaughters of to my grandmother. Likewise, perhaps I stand in the relation of being the grandmother of to a future child.
Here is a Meinongian solution: Suppose objects pop in and out of existence but thereby do not gain or lose their being. (For a Meinongian, all existent objects have being but not all being objects exist.) According to this picture, “Socrates” now denotes the nonexistent Socrates and “the first female pope” now denotes the nonexistent first female pope. Accordingly, although we cannot allow for the inference from
(1) Socrates was a philosopher.
and
(2) The first female pope will be black.
to
(3) Socrates exists.
and
(4) The first female pope exists.
we can allow for the inference from (1) and (2) to
(3′) There is something that is identical with Socrates.
and
(4′) There is something that is identical with the first female pope.[17]
This result does justice to two otherwise incompatible intuitions, namely (i) the intuition that neither Socrates nor the first female pope exist right now, and (ii) the intuition that it is nevertheless possible to refer to Socrates and to the first female pope (or, to put it another way: the intuition that the name “Socrates” and the description “the first female pope” are not empty).
Tensed plural quantifiers do not pose a problem for a Meinongian. Tensed quantifiers in general may be interpreted as restricted quantifiers that range over a particular subdomain of nonexistent objects: “there was” may be interpreted as a quantifier that ranges over the subdomain of past objects (i.e., objects that have existed but do not exist anymore); analogously, “there will be” may be interpreted as a quantifier that ranges over the subdomain of future objects (i.e., objects that will exist but do not exist yet).[18]
Furthermore, from a Meinongian point of view, relations between existent and nonexistent objects are ubiquitous. Remember the Meinongian solution to the problem of intentionality: people fear, admire, dream of, hope for, or imagine nonexistent objects. Thus, relations between present and non-present objects do not pose a particular problem for a Meinongian.
3.4 The Problem of Alleged Analytic Truths Like “The round square is square”
Sentences like
(1) The round square is round and a square.
seem to be logically true (at least according to the intuitions of some logicians—see Lambert 1983). Furthermore, they seem to have the logical structure of predications. According to (PP) and (EG), (1) implies
(2) There is something that is identical with the round square.
and
(3) There is something that is both round and a square.
If “there is” means the same as “exist”, these are, of course, unacceptable consequences.
There are two obvious ways out: (i) One could simply reject (1) as false (or truth-valueless). (ii) One could try to find an adequate paraphrase for (1) which accounts for the intuition that (1) is “in some sense” true. Such a paraphrase might be
(1′) If there were such a thing as the round square, it would be round and a square.
But according to the Meinongian picture, (2) and (3) are acceptable consequences, since they do not entail the existence of something that is both round and square. Something that is both round and square is an impossible object, according to Meinong, which means that it cannot exist, but this does not entail that there is no such thing. Therefore, the Meinongian can accept (1) as true, without resorting to any kind of paraphrase.
We have seen that there are alternative solutions for every single one of the abovementioned problems. But, for all we know, the assertion that there are nonexistent objects is the only way to resolve all these diverse problems in a uniform way.
3.5 Nonexistent Objects in Practical Philosophy
There is a debate in practical philosophy as to whether nonexistent persons are morally relevant. The basic question is this: do nonexistent people have interests that we ought to take into account in our decisions? Obviously, some of our decisions affect not only existent but also future (i.e., not yet existent) persons; matters of climate change or the disposal of radioactive waste are relevant cases in point. Intuitively, we ought to act in such a way as to prevent disasters for future generations. It is a matter of controversy, though, whether, in order to take into account this moral intuition, we have to commit ourselves to an ontology of not yet existent beings. Some, however, go still a step further and argue that not only future persons are morally relevant but even persons who will never exist (and never existed). In particular, this debate concerns questions of procreative ethics and population policies.[19]
4. Problems with Belief in Nonexistent Objects
The foregoing considerations suggested that the claim that there are nonexistent objects has considerable explanatory force. Why, then, is this claim not generally accepted but, rather to the contrary, so controversial? Is the reason just, as Meinong has put it, “a prejudice in favor of the actual”? — Although ontological prejudices may play a role, there are also some good reasons for reservations (to put it very carefully).
Even in Meinong’s own writings, there are (roughly) two versions of the theory, the original one and a later, revised one. In what follows, we will refer to the original Meinongian object theory by means of the abbreviation “MOTo”.
Perhaps the most basic principle of MOTo is the so-called “principle of independence”, which says, literally: So-being is independent from being (see Meinong 1959). Ignoring, for the sake of simplicity, Meinong’s particular use of the term “being”, we can paraphrase this principle as: So-being is independent from existence.
The “so-being” of an object is the totality of the object’s properties apart from the object’s existence or non-existence. The principle of independence says, thus, that an object may have any properties whatsoever, independently of whether the object exists or not. For instance, the (nonexistent) golden mountain literally is golden and a mountain; the round square literally is round and a square.
To every single property and to every set of properties, there is a corresponding object, either an existent or a nonexistent one. Thus, there is, for instance, an object that has the property of being round as its sole property; one might call it “the object round”, or simply “round”. There is also an object that has the property of being blue as its sole property (the object blue, or blue, for short). Furthermore, there is an object that has the property of being round and the property of being blue, and no other properties (the object round and blue); and so forth.
In the notation of classical logic extended with definite descriptions of the form ιxφ(x), the object that has the property of being blue as its sole property may be represented by “ιx∀F(Fx ≡ F = B)”[20] (where “B” stands for “is blue”), the object that has the property of being blue and the property of being round as its sole properties by “ιx∀F(Fx ≡ F = B ∨ F = R)” (where “R” stands for “is round”), and so forth.
The object blue is not identical with the property of being blue; neither is it identical with the set that contains the property of being blue as its sole member. Neither is the object round and blue identical with the set of the property of being blue and the property of being round. The property of being blue is not itself blue, the property of being round is not itself round. Analogous considerations hold for sets of properties: sets have neither colors nor shapes. But the object blue is blue, and the object round is round, and so forth.
One might wish to ask: Isn’t it impossible that there exists an object that has the property of being blue as its sole property? Isn’t it necessarily the case that every colored object also has some particular shape, some particular size, is made of some particular material, and so forth?
The Meinongian answer to this question is as follows: It is indeed impossible that such an object exists! Therefore, the object blue is not only nonexistent but even necessarily nonexistent. Of course, the same holds for the object round, the object red and round, and infinitely many other objects as well. Every existing object has infinitely many properties. Every existing object is a completely determined (or, in short: a complete) object. Objects like blue and round and blue are incompletely determined (or, in short: incomplete) objects.[21]
Incomplete objects are necessarily nonexistent. They are, in this sense, impossible objects (even though their properties may not be contradictory). It should be noted, however, that not every complete object exists. Consider, for instance, the object that looks exactly like me except that it has green eyes instead of blue ones. Let’s assume that this object (my nonexistent green-eyed counterpart) has all the properties that I have except for those that are entailed by the difference in eye color, given the actual laws of nature. My nonexistent green-eyed counterpart is completely determined and nevertheless does not exist. But, in contrast to blue, this counterpart could exist, i.e., it is a possible nonexistent object.[22]
Unfortunately, however, MOTo has a number of paradoxical consequences. Bertrand Russell, Meinong’s most famous critic, put forward two objections against MOTo.[23] The first objection goes as follows: According to MOTo, there is an object that is both round and square, but such an object is “apt to infringe the law of contradiction”, since it would be both round and not round (Russell 1973c, 107).
Meinong perhaps could have replied to this objection that the object called “the round square” has the properties of being round and being square, but not the property of being not round, and thus the round square does not infringe the law of contradiction (but only the geometrical law that everything that is square is not round). Such a reply, however, would have been a bit beside the point, since it is clear that, according to the principles of MOTo, there is an object that is both round and not round (and evidently the object that Russell had in mind was of this sort). Indeed, Meinong did not deny that the round square infringes the law of contradiction. Instead, he replied to Russell’s first objection that the law of contradiction holds for existent objects only. Objects that are both round and not round, however, are necessarily nonexistent.
Russell accepted this reply but forged a second objection that could not be dismissed in the same vein. Russell argues that since it is a principle of MOTo that to every set of properties there is a corresponding object and since existence is treated as a property within MOTo, there must be an object that has exactly the following three properties: being golden, being a mountain, and being existent. If “G” stands for “is golden”, “M” stands for “is a mountain” and “E!” stands for “is existent”, this object is denoted by “ιx∀F(Fx ≡ F = G ∨ F = M ∨ F = E!)”. Thus, it follows from the principles of MOTo that there is an existent object that is golden and a mountain. But it is an empirical fact that no golden mountain exists. Given the (apparently trivial) assumption that “b is existent” is equivalent with “b exists”, this is a contradiction.
A further paradox seems to arise from the incompleteness of many Meinongian objects:
- The object blue (i.e., ιx∀F(Fx ≡ F = B), according to MOTo) has the property of being blue as its sole property. (Theorem of MOTo)
- The object blue has exactly one property. (1)
- The object blue has the property of having exactly one property. (2)
- The property of being blue is not identical with the property of having exactly one property.
- Thus, blue has (at least) two properties, namely the property of being blue and the property of having exactly one property. (1, 3, 4)
- Thus, blue has exactly one property and blue has (at least) two properties. (2, 5)
Furthermore, it seems that many Meinongian objects do not only infringe laws of logic and geometry, but also intuitively plausible principles like “If something is round, it occupies some region in space” and “If something is a mountain, it is accessible to the senses”. It seems that having a particular shape entails occupying a region in space and that being a mountain entails accessibility to the senses (in principle). According to MOTo, the round square is round and the golden mountain is a mountain, but obviously neither the round square nor the golden mountain occupies any region in space and neither of them is accessible to the senses.
Another strange consequence of MOTo is the following: If an object comes into existence, all that happens is that the object turns from a nonexistent into an existent one. Analogously, if an object goes out of existence, all that happens is that the object turns from an existent again into a nonexistent one. Apart from this, neither the object in question nor the world as a whole changes in any way. For instance, when I cease to exist, all that happens is that I will again be nonexistent (as it was from the beginning of time to 1966). In all other respects, I will stay just the same. Maybe such a thought is potentially comforting for those who love me, but it is surely at odds with our normal understanding of coming into existence and passing away.
5. Contemporary Theories of Nonexistent Objects: From Nonexistence to Abstractness
There is a diversity of contemporary theories of nonexistent objects, where “theory of nonexistent objects” is meant to include any theory that attempts to make sense of (alleged) talk about nonexistent objects and/or (seeming) intentional directedness to nonexistent objects. Some of them, like the de-ontologization strategy and fictionalism, take a reductionist route. The de-ontologization strategy claims that there can be true sentences about nonexistent objects, although there are no nonexistent objects. Fictionalism claims that talk about nonexistent objects is not to be taken literally but as a sort of “pretense”. The other worlds strategy makes use of the assumption of merely possible (and even impossible) worlds. Other contemporary theories of nonexistent objects, however, are closer to Meinong’s original theory but have amended MOTo in such a way as to avoid at least some of the abovementioned paradoxes. Those are often called “neo-Meinongian theories”. Usually, they adopt either the nuclear-extranuclear strategy or the dual copula strategy in order to free Meinongian object theory from inconsistencies and counterintuitive consequences.
5.1 The De-ontologization Strategy
Tim Crane (see Crane 2012 and 2013) holds that all of the following claims are true:
- We can think and talk about nonexistent objects.
- Nonexistent objects do not have any kind of being whatsoever.
- The sentence “There are nonexistent objects” is true.
- Some predications with non-referring singular terms in subject positions are true, e.g.: “Vulcan was a planet postulated by Le Verrier”; “Sherlock Holmes is more famous than any living detective”; “Pegasus is a mythical horse”.
- Contrary to what Meinongians think, nonexistent objects do not have all of the properties they are characterized as having. For instance, Pegasus is a not a horse; thus, “Pegasus is a horse” is not true (although “Pegasus is a mythical horse” is). Neither is the round square round.
Crane can hold the conjunction of 1 and 2 because he interprets aboutness in a non-relational way. He can hold the conjunction of 2 and 3 because he denies that “there are” and its cognates (both in natural and formal languages) are ontologically committing in any way. (For this reason, I call this the de-ontologization strategy.) He can hold the conjunction of 4 and 5 because he endorses a positive free logic, i.e., the view that there may be true as well as false sentences of the form Fb, where “b” stands for a non-referring singular term.
By denying that Pegasus is a horse and the round square is round Crane circumvents some of the above-mentioned problems of Meinongianism. However, his view raises another problem: Why is “Pegasus is a mythical horse” true, while “Pegasus is a horse” is not? In general, why is it that certain predications with non-referring singular terms are true and others are not? For, according to the de-ontologization strategy, neither “Pegasus is a mythical horse” nor “Pegasus is a horse” can be made true by the referent of “Pegasus”, because there is no such thing.
Crane (2013) offers what he calls a “reductionist” solution to this problem. That is, according to Crane, sentences “about” nonexistent objects are made true by something else, i.e., by something existent. For instance, the sentence “Vulcan was a planet postulated by Le Verrier in 1859 to explain the perturbations in the orbit of Mercury” is made true by certain events in 1859, namely by postulation events; the sentence “Sherlock Holmes is more famous than Sir Ian Blair” is made true by the fact that more people have heard about Sherlock Holmes than about Sir Ian Blair (where to have heard about Holmes is to have heard about the respective stories); the sentence “Pegasus is a mythical winged horse that sprung into being from the blood of Medusa” is made true by a myth which represents Pegasus as being such-and-such; the sentence “Siegfried is one of the most unappealing heroes in all dramatic works” is made true by certain facts about the last two parts of Wagner’s Ring. As these examples already show, Crane does not give a uniform, systematic account of the truth of sentences about fictitious objects, as he himself concedes. (See Crane 2013, Section 5.5.)For another example of a reductionist solution, Frank Jackson holds that one can assent to “Mr. Pickwick is Dickens’ most famous character” without an ontological commitment to fictitious characters in general and Mr. Pickwick in particular. For, according to Jackson’s de-ontologization strategy, object language sentences are ontologically neutral. Ontological commitment comes in only at the meta-language level, for instance, if we would claim that the name “Mr. Pickwick” denotes Dickens’s most famous character or that the predicate “a character in Dickens” applies to something. (See Jackson 1980.)
A de-ontologization strategy with respect to fictitious characters is also to be found in Crittenden 1973 and in Azzouni 2010.
5.2 Fictionalism and Indifferentism
In recent years, something close to the de-ontologization strategy—or rather a bundle of more or less similar strategies—became prominent, known under the heading “fictionalism”. The basic idea of fictionalism is, roughly put, that utterances belonging to a certain region of discourse are not to be taken literally, that speakers producing such utterances have a fictional attitude towards them and are engaged in a sort of pretense or make-believe. (For an overview of the diverse versions of fictionalism as well as a succinct presentation of its most important pros and cons see the entry on fictionalism.)
Fictionalism differs from the de-ontologization strategy since fictionalists do not claim that the relevant utterances are literally true; to the contrary, according to fictionalism, certain kinds of discourse consist of utterances that are false (if taken literally), but nevertheless it may be useful in some respects to stick to that sorts of discourse.
A general assessment of fictionalism is difficult since the positions included under this heading differ considerably from each other. Much depends on how exactly the “fictional attitude” is spelled out. Many versions of fictionalism are prone to the “phenomenological objection”: external talk about fictitious objects—to mention one of the applications of the fictionalist strategy that is particularly relevant in the context of the present entry—does not feel like “make-believe”; introspection does not reveal that we are engaged in any kind of pretense when we say things like “Sherlock Holmes is one of the most famous characters of popular literature” and the like.
A position inspired by and in important respects similar to fictionalism that, however, avoids the phenomenological objection is Eklund’s “indifferentism”. Indifferentism is the view that speakers outside the “philosophy room” are often simply indifferent with regards of the ontological implications of their utterances and thus are not committed to the existence of those entities whose existence is implied by their utterances. As Eklund emphasizes, however, indifferentism does not say anything about which entities one should accept in one’s ontology; it is, in this sense, not an ontological thesis. (See Eklund 2005.)
5.3 The Other Worlds Strategy
The other worlds strategy has been proposed by Graham Priest (2005) and Francesco Berto (2008). Priest calls his theory noneism; Berto names it modal Meinongianism. The term “noneism” has been coined by Richard Routley, and Priest not only takes over the name but also essential features of Routley’s theory (among other things the assumption that basic principles of standard logics, like the principle of contradiction, do not hold without restriction—without, of course, accepting that everything is true).
Proponents of the other worlds strategy reject both the nuclear-extranuclear strategy and the dual copula strategy. Instead, they assume merely possible and even impossible worlds. All worlds (possible as well as impossible ones) share the same domain of discourse. But not all objects of the domain exist in all worlds. Thus, Pegasus does not exist in the actual world, but it exists in a variety of merely possible worlds (namely in those which are such as represented by the Greek mythology).
According to the other worlds strategy, nonexistent objects literally have the properties through which they are “characterized”—but they have these properties not in the actual world but only in those worlds in which they exist.
The other worlds strategy provides the following solution to the paradox of contradiction: The round square exists only in impossible worlds. In impossible worlds, however, the principle of contradiction does not hold. Therefore, the round square’s being both round and not round does not infringe the laws of logic which hold in those worlds in which the round square exists.
In the actual world, however, the round square is neither round nor square, since roundness and squareness are “existence-entailing properties”, i.e., “b is round/square” entails “b exists”. Therefore, even if in the actual world (and in all other possible worlds) the law of contradiction holds, the round square does not infringe this law, since in these worlds the round square is neither round nor not round.
In the light of this theory, it is easy to explain why nobody has ever seen the round square or a golden mountain and why the round square is obviously not located in space: since the round square is neither round nor square in the actual world, there is no reason to assume that it occupies space or is accessible to the senses. Similar considerations hold for the golden mountain.
It is worth noting that the postulation of existence-entailing properties is an implicit rejection of Meinong’s principle of independence, which is one of the cornerstones of Meinongian object theory.
Proponents of the other worlds strategy reject the nuclear-extranuclear distinction because they find it “difficult to avoid the feeling that the class [of nuclear predicates] has been gerrymandered simply to avoid problems” (Priest 2005, 83).
But Priest’s proposal has difficulties of its own.[24] To mention some of them: First, Priest does not give a principled characterization of which properties are existence-entailing and which are not (which looks quite similar to the problem with the nuclear-extranuclear distinction which Priest points out in the above quotation). Second, it remains unclear which properties nonexistent objects have in the actual world (apart from logical properties like being self-identical and intentional properties like being thought of by Priest).[25] Furthermore, Priest’s noneism raises difficult questions about cross-world identity and the ontological status of non-actual worlds. The ontological status of non-actual worlds is far from obvious: they may be taken to be concrete objects (structured sets of physical objects) or abstract objects (sets of sentences, propositions, or states of affairs). (For an elaborate survey of various conceptions of non-actual worlds see Menzel 2014.)[26] Apart from this, it is doubtful whether Priest’s theory provides an adequate account of fictitious objects. Among other things, it does not do justice to the widespread intuition that fictitious objects are created by the authors of the stories to which they belong.[27]
5.4 Nuclear and Extranuclear Properties
According to the nuclear-extranuclear strategy, there are two kinds of properties: nuclear and extranuclear ones. (Meinong 1972, §25)[28] An object’s nuclear properties are supposed to constitute the object’s “nature”, while its extranuclear properties are supposed to be external to the object’s nature. Nuclear properties are, for instance: being blue, being tall, kicking Socrates, having been kicked by Socrates, kicking somebody, being golden, being a mountain (Parsons 1980, 23).
Which properties are extranuclear? Terence Parsons distinguishes four categories of “extranuclear predicates” (i.e., predicates that stand for extranuclear properties): ontological (“exists”, “is mythical”, “is fictional”), modal (“is possible”, “is impossible”), intentional (“is thought about by Meinong”, “is worshipped by someone”), technical (“is complete”) (Parsons 1980, 23).[29]
Nuclear properties are either constitutive or consecutive, in Meinong’s terms (Meinong 1972, 176). An object’s constitutive properties are those properties that are mentioned explicitly in a description that is used to pick out the object. Thus, the constitutive properties of the golden mountain are being golden and being a mountain. An object’s consecutive properties are those properties that are somehow included or implied by the object’s constitutive properties. Thus, among the consecutive properties of the golden mountain are probably the properties of being a material thing and of being extended.
According to MOTo, the object called “the golden mountain” was ιx∀F(Fx ≡ F = G ∨ F = M), i.e., the object that has the property of being golden and the property of being a mountain (and no other properties). According to the revised version of object theory, the object called “the golden mountain” is the object that has all the nuclear properties that are implied by the nuclear property of being golden and the nuclear property of being a mountain, i.e., ιx∀Fn(Fnx ≡ Gn ⇒ Fn ∨ Mn ⇒ Fn).[30]
How does the nuclear-extranuclear distinction help to avoid the paradoxes mentioned in the section above? — Consider again the paradox from incompleteness: According to MOTo, there is an object that has the property of being blue as its sole property (we’ve called it “the object blue”, for short), in logical notation: ιx∀F(Fx ≡ F = B). It seems to be true of the object blue, by definition, that it has exactly one property. Yet, the property of having exactly one property is clearly distinct from the property of being blue. Thus, it seems that the object blue has at least two properties.
According to the revised version of object theory with the nuclear-extranuclear distinction (MOTne, for short), this paradox is avoided in the following way: The property of being blue is a nuclear (constitutive) property, the property of having exactly one property, however, is an extranuclear property. There aren’t any objects that have exactly one property. There are only objects that have exactly one constitutive (nuclear) property. Objects that have only a limited number of constitutive properties may (and necessarily do) have additional extranuclear properties—like the property of having exactly n constitutive properties or the property of being incomplete. The object called “blue” is ιx∀Fn(Fnx ≡ Bn ⇒ Fn), i.e., the object that has the property of being blue as its sole constitutive property. This does not rule out that the object blue may have additional extranuclear properties. Thus, the paradox from incompleteness does not arise in MOTne.[31]
To Russell’s objection that the existent golden mountain infringes the law of contradiction (since it is both existent and nonexistent), advocates of MOTne may reply as follows: Existence is an extranuclear property, but only nuclear properties can be constitutive properties of an object. Therefore, according to MOTne, there simply is no such object as ιx∀F(Fx ≡ F = G ∨ F = M ∨ F = E!) (i.e., the existent golden mountain). (This route is taken by Dale Jacquette and Richard Routley. See Jacquette 1996, 81 and Routley 1980, 496.)
This solution, however, imposes quite a heavy restriction on the theory of objects. Probably this was the reason why Meinong himself did not even mention it as a possible solution. Instead, he introduced in addition to the nuclear-extranuclear distinction the doctrine of watered-down extranuclear properties: at least some extranuclear properties (existence, possibility) have nuclear counterparts, i.e., “watered-down” versions of extranuclear properties (Meinong 1972, §37).[32]
If the extranuclear property of existence has a watered-down nuclear counterpart, the following answer to Russell’s objection is available: “The existent golden mountain exists” is ambiguous. It may be read as “The existent golden mountain exemplifies extranuclear existence” (which is false), or it may be read as “The existent golden mountain exemplifies nuclear existence” (which is true). There is no contradiction between “The existent golden mountain exemplifies nuclear existence” and “The existent golden mountain does not exist” (in the proper, extranuclear sense).
Do other extranuclear properties (besides existence) also have nuclear counterparts? Do perhaps all extranuclear properties have nuclear counterparts? Meinong himself is not explicit about this point, but it seems very natural to extend the theory in this way. Terence Parsons has adopted this extension (Parsons 1980, 68), while Dale Jacquette rejects the doctrine of watered-down extranuclear properties altogether, even for existence and possibility (Jacquette 1996, 85–87).
There are several paradoxes for which MOTne does not supply a solution (even if it is supplemented with the doctrine of watered-down extranuclear properties). It still seems that the round square infringes the law of contradiction; one still may wonder why it is impossible to discover round squares and golden mountains; and one still may be baffled by the doctrine that nonexistent objects differ from existent ones only in that the former lack existence.[33]
5.5 The Dual Copula Strategy
According to the dual copula strategy, there are two kinds of relations between properties and individuals.[34] Different advocates of this strategy use different terminologies for it. Here are some of them:
The golden mountain is determined by the property of being golden and by the property of being a mountain. The golden mountain satisfies the property of being incompletely determined. (Mally 1912) The golden mountain has the property of being golden and the property of being a mountain assigned to it. The golden mountain immanently contains the property of being incompletely determined. (Ingarden 1931 [1973], §20, p. 122) The golden mountain is consociated with the property of being golden and the property of being a mountain. The golden mountain is consubstantiated with the property of being incompletely determined. (Castañeda 1972) The property of being golden and the property of being a mountain are ascribed to the golden mountain. The golden mountain has the property of being incompletely determined. (van Inwagen 1977)[35] The golden mountain is constituted by the properties of being golden and being a mountain. The golden mountain exemplifies the property of being incompletely determined. (Rapaport 1978) The golden mountain encodes the property of being golden and the property of being a mountain. The golden mountain exemplifies the property of being incompletely determined. (Zalta 1983)
The various versions of the dual copula strategy share the assumption that the copula “is” is ambiguous. In what follows, we will use the exemplification-encoding terminology. In addition, we will borrow from Zalta the following notational convention: “Fb” stands for “b exemplifies the property of being F”. “bF” stands for “b encodes the property of being F”. Furthermore, we will use MOTdc as an abbreviation for “the revised version of Meinongian object theory which makes use of a dual copula distinction”.
According to MOTdc, the object called “the round square” is the object that encodes the property of being round and the property of being square (and all of the properties that are implied by these properties) and no other properties. Thus, according to MOTdc, the object called “the round square” is ιx∀F(xF ≡ R ⇒ F ∨ S ⇒ F).
Thus, according to MOTdc, the object called “the round square” encodes exactly two constitutive properties (being round and being square). However, over and above this, there are many (indeed infinitely many) properties that are exemplified by this object, for instance: the property of not being red, the property of not encoding the property of being red, the property of not being determined with respect to its side length, the property of having thought of by Bertrand Russell, the property of encoding exactly two constitutive properties, the property of being incompletely determined.
To mention another popular example, consider Pegasus: Among other things, Pegasus encodes the properties of being a horse, of having wings, of having been tamed by Bellerophon. But there are also infinitely many properties that Pegasus exemplifies, for instance, the property of not being determined with respect to the number of hairs in its tail, the property of being a character of Greek mythology, the property of being a fictitious object.
It must be emphasized that something that encodes the property of being a horse is not a horse (in the usual predicative sense of “is”). Analogously, something that encodes the properties of being round and square is neither round nor square. That is to say, something that encodes the property of being a horse does not belong to the class of horses, and something that encodes the properties of being round and square does neither belong to the class of round things nor to the class of square things. Rather, things that encode the properties of being a horse or being a square or being a Danish prince are abstract objects—abstract in the sense that they are neither mental nor spatio-temporal things. In general, everything which encodes at least one property is an abstract object in this sense.[36]
Let’s see how MOTdc avoids the alleged paradoxes mentioned in section 4. The first objection was that objects like the round square infringe the law of contradiction, since such objects would be both round and not round. According to MOTdc, however, the object called “the round square”—ιx∀F(xF ≡ R ⇒ F ∨ S ⇒ F)—is not round (i.e., does not exemplify the property of being round). Thus, no contradiction arises.
The second objection was that the existent golden mountain would infringe the law of contradiction, since, if there were such an object, it would be both existent and nonexistent. According to MOTdc, one could answer to this objection as follows: The object called “the existent golden mountain” is ιx∀F(xF ≡ G ⇒ F ∨ M ⇒ F ∨ E! ⇒ F). This object encodes the property of being existent, but it does not exemplify it. Since “b encodes F” does not imply “b exemplifies F”, there is no contradiction involved here.
According to MOTdc, the object blue is ιx∀F(xF ≡ B ⇒ F), i.e., the object that encodes exclusively the properties that are implied by being blue. Thus, the object blue exemplifies the property of encoding only the properties that are implied by being blue. It is not the case that the object blue has exactly one property and at the same time has at least two properties, at least not, if “has” is used in the same sense in both occurrences. In this way, the apparent contradiction disappears.
Furthermore, according to MOTdc, the object called “the round square”, i.e., ιx∀F(xF ≡ R ⇒ F ∨ S ⇒ F), does not occupy any region in space. More exactly, it does not exemplify the property of occupying some region in space (though, perhaps it encodes this property, if being round implies occupying some region in space). Analogously, according to MOTdc, the object called “the golden mountain”, i.e., ιx∀F(xF ≡ G ⇒ F ∨ M ⇒ F), does not exemplify the property of being accessible to the senses (at best, it encodes this property). Therefore, there is nothing paradoxical in the fact that nobody has ever seen a golden mountain and that it is impossible to determine the location of the round square.
Finally, MOTdc does not have the counterintuitive consequence that the only difference between existent and nonexistent objects is that the latter lack the property of being existent, such that if an object goes out of existence, the vast majority of its properties (like being human, loving pancakes, being violent-tempered, and so forth) stay exactly the same. Consider again my nonexistent green-eyed counterpart. According to MOTdc, this object encodes being human, being female, being a philosopher, and so forth, but does not exemplify these properties; therefore, it does not belong to the class of female philosophers, not even to the class of humans or to the class of living beings. Thus, it is clear that my green-eyed counterpart’s nonexistence is by far not the only difference between it and myself. In general, nonexistent objects are a particular kind of objects, according to MOTdc—very different from ordinary existent objects. In what follows, we’ll call them “Meinongian objects”.
5.6 Nonexistence Does Not Hold the Key
MOTdc is very remote from MOTo. Recall that, according to MOTo, the object called “the golden mountain” is not an abstract object but something as concrete as every existent mountain in the world. Secondly, and related to this, the idea that some objects do not exist is one of the cornerstones of MOTo—but it is not an essential feature of MOTdc, i.e., it doesn’t play an essential role within MOTdc. Within MOTdc, Meinongian objects are defined as a particular kind of abstract objects (namely abstract objects to which two kinds of predicates apply). Of course, one can decide to say that these objects are “nonexistent”; but nothing hinges upon this decision. According to MOTo, the only difference between Meinongian objects and normal objects consists in the alleged nonexistence of the former. However, in MOTdc, Meinongian objects are distinct from normal objects because only the former are abstract objects which encode properties. This suffices to distinguish Meinongian objects from normal objects. Thus, there is no need to assume that existence is a property of individuals and that there is a difference between “There are objects that are such-and-such” and “Objects that are such-and-such exist”.
If MOTdc is essentially different from MOTo, the question arises to what extent MOTdc can fulfill the tasks MOTo was supposed to fulfill. It seems that MOTdc cannot do everything MOTo was supposed to do. First, consider the problem of intentionality: if somebody fears the devil, does he fear an abstract object? — This seems to be psychologically impossible, for an abstract object cannot do any harm to anybody.[37] Second, recall the problem of negative singular existence sentences: Astronomers claim that Vulcan does not exist. Do they thereby intend to deny the existence of an abstract object that only encodes being such-and-such a planet? — Probably not. They rather deny the existence of something that is a planet, i.e., a concrete material thing. Finally, consider the problem of discourse about the past and the future: when a teacher in a history of philosophy class talks about Socrates, does she then intend to talk about an abstract object that only encodes all of the properties that Socrates (the “real” one) once exemplified? — Presumably not. If there is an object which she is intentionally directed at, then it is probably the “real” Socrates, not its abstract counterpart.
It may be that proponents of MOTdc find ways to meet these objections such that their theories provide solutions for the problem of intentionality, the problem of singular existence sentences, and the problem of reference to past and future objects. But even if they don’t, it is beyound doubt that Neo-Meinongian theories can be and indeed are fruitful in many ways. In particular, they provide the basis for a consistent realist ontology of fictitious objects. (For a variety of further applications see in particular the writings of Jacquette, Parsons, and Zalta.)
6. Themes for Further Investigation
There are several ways in which Meinongian object theory can be developed further. Here are some of them:[38]
1. Both MOTne and MOTdc could perhaps benefit from a clarification of their basic distinctions, namely the nuclear-extranuclear distinction and the dual copula distinction, respectively.
2. One feature of Meinong’s mature object theory not mentioned so far is the “doctrine of implexion”. Implexion is a relation between incomplete and complete objects which seems to be very close to what is often called “instantiation”, i.e., a relation between universals and particulars. Incomplete objects are “implected” in complete ones. (See Meinong 1972, §29.) Meinong himself eventually came to interpret incomplete objects as universals (see Meinong 1972, 739f). Meinongian object theory may thus be interpreted as a sophisticated theory of universals, in particular as a theory of types (as opposed to properties), which might open further fields of application.
3. Throughout this entry, we have presupposed realism with respect to properties. However, it is doubtful whether a theory of Meinongian objects is necessarily ontologically committed to properties. An ontologically neutral quantifier and the use of non-objectual variables for predicates (not for names of predicates or properties) may help to avoid this commitment and thus could make Meinongian object theory much more parsimonious.
Bibliography
- Alai, Mario, 2006, “Speaking of Nonexistent Objects,” in Raspa, Venanzio (ed.), Meinongian Issues in Contemporary Italian Philosophy, Heusenstamm: Ontos, 119–159.
- Azzouni, Jody, 2004, Deflating Existential Consequence: A Case for Nominalism, New York: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2010, Talking about Nothing: Numbers, Hallucinations, and Fictions, New York: Oxford University Press.
- Barbero, Carola, 2005, Madame Bovary: Something Like a Melody, Milano: Edizioni Albo Versorio.
- Berto, Francesco, 2008, “Modal Meinongianism for Fictional Objects,” Metaphysica, 9: 205–218.
- Brentano, Franz, 1874, Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, translated by Anto C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, and Linda L. McAlister, introduction by Peter Simons, London: Routledge, 1995.
- Braun, David, 2005, “Empty Names, Fictional Names, Mythical Names,” Noûs, 39: 596–631.
- Brock, Stuart, 2002, “Fictionalism about Fictional Characters,” Noûs, 36: 1–21.
- Castañeda, Hector-Neri, 1972, “Thinking and the Structure of the World,” Critica, 6: 43–86.
- –––, 1979, “Fiction and Reality: Their Fundamental Connections. An Essay on the Ontology of Total Experience,” Poetics, 8: 31–62.
- –––, 1990, “Fiction, Perception, and Forms of Predication (Reply to Künne),” in Klaus Jacobi and Helmut Pape (eds.), Thinking and the Structure of the World. Hector-Neri Castañeda’s Epistemic Ontology Presented and Criticised, Berlin: de Gruyter, 268–284.
- Chakrabarti, Arindam, 1997, Denying Existence. The Logic, Epistemology and Pragmatics of Negative Existentials and Fictional Discourse (Synthese Library, Volume 261), Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Chisholm, Roderick M., 1972, “Beyond Being and Nonbeing,” in Rudolf Haller (ed.), Jenseits von Sein und Nichtsein. Beiträge zur Meinong-Forschung, Graz: Akademische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt, 25–33.
- Crane, Tim, 2012, “What Is the Problem of Non-existence?,” Philosophia: Philosophical Quarterly of Israel, 40: 417–434.
- –––, 2013, The Objects of Thought, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Crittenden, Charles, 1973, “Thinking about Non-being,” Inquiry, 16: 290–312.
- Einheuser, Iris, 2012, “Nonexistence, Vague Existence, Merely Possible Existence,” Disputatio, 5: 428–443.
- Eklund, Matti, 2005, “Fiction, Indifference, and Ontology,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71: 557–579.
- Everett, Anthony, 2005, “Against Fictional Realism,” Journal of Philosophy, 102: 624–649.
- –––, 2007, “Pretense, Existence, and Fictional Objects,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74: 56–80.
- –––, 2013, The Nonexistent, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Ferrater-Mora, J., 1976/77, “Fictions, Universals, and Abstract Entities,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 37: 353–367.
- Findlay, John N., 1963, Meinong’s Theory of Objects and Values, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Fine, Kit, 1981, “Model Theory for Modal Logic – Part III. Existence and Predication,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 10: 293–307.
- –––, 1982, “The Problem of Non-existents. I. Internalism,” Topoi, 1: 97–140.
- –––, 1983, “Symposium: A Defence of Arbitrary Objects, I,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 57: 55–77.
- –––, 1984, “Critical Review of Parsons’ Nonexistent Objects,” Philosophical Studies, 45: 94–142.
- –––, 1985, Reasoning With Arbitrary Objects, Oxford: Blackwell.
- Frege, Gottlob, 1966, “Function and Concept,” translated by P. T. Geach, in Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, edited by Peter Geach and Max Black, Oxford: Blackwell, 21–41.
- Friend, Stacie, 2007, “Fictional Characters,” Philosophy Compass, 2: 141–156.
- Geach, Peter Thomas, 1971, [Review of:] Rush Rhees, Without Answers, Journal of Philosophy, 68: 531–532.
- Goodman, Jeffrey, 2010, “Fictionalia as Modal Artifacts,” Grazer Philosophische Studien, 80: 21–46.
- Griffin, Nicholas, 1985–86, “Russell’s Critique of Meinong’s Theory of Objects,” in Rudolf Haller (ed.), Non-Existence and Predication, Amsterdam: Rodopi (= Grazer Philosophische Studien, Volumes 25/26), 375–401.
- Grossmann, Reinhardt, 1974, Meinong, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
- –––, 2001, “Meinong’s Main Mistake,” in Liliana Albertazzi, Dale Jacquette, and Roberto Poli (eds.), The School of Alexius Meinong (Western Philosophy Series 57), Aldershot: Ashgate, 477–488.
- Hale, Bob, 2007, “Into the Abyss”. A critical study of Graham Priest: Towards Non-being. The Logics and Metaphysics of Intentionality, Philosophia Mathematica, 15: 94–110.
- Herstein, Ori J., 2013, “Why ‘Nonexistent People’ Do Not Have Zero Wellbeing but No Wellbeing at All,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 30: 136–145.
- Hinchliff, Mark, 1988, A Defense of Presentism, Doctoral dissertation, Princeton University.
- Hintikka, Jaakko, 1959, “Existential Presuppositions and Existential Commitments,” Journal of Philosophy, 56: 125–137.
- –––, 1984, “Are There Nonexistent Objects? Why Not? But Where Are They?” Synthese, 60: 451–458.
- Howell, Robert, 1979, “Fictional Objects: How They Are and How They Aren’t,” Poetics, 8: 129–177.
- Hume, David, 2000, A Treatise of Human Nature, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Ingarden, Roman, 1931 [1973], The Literary Work of Art. An Investigation on the Borderlines of Ontology, Logic, and Theory of Literature, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1973. [German original first published in 1931.]
- Jackson, Frank, 1980, “Ontological Commitment and Paraphrase,” Philosophy, 55: 303–315.
- Jacquette, Dale, 1989a, “On the Objects’ Independence from Thought, by Ernst Mally: Translation and Commentary,” Man and World, 22: 215–231.
- –––, 1989b, “Mally’s Heresy and the Logic of Meinong’s Object Theory,” History of Philosophical Logic, 10: 1–14.
- –––, 1996, Meinongian Logic. The Semantics of Existence and Nonexistence (Perspectives in Analytical Philosophy 11), Berlin–New York: de Gruyter.
- Jorgensen, Andrew Kenneth, 2002, Meinong’s Theory of Non-existent Objects (Ph.D. Thesis, Temple University), Ann Arbor, MI: University Microfilms International.
- Kant, Immanuel, 2003, Critique of Pure Reason, translated by Norman Kemp Smith, with a new preface by Howard Caygill, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
- Kripke, Saul A., 1980, Naming and Necessity, Oxford: Blackwell.
- Kroon, Frederick, 2008, “Much Ado about Nothing: Priest and the Reinvention of Noneism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76: 199–207.
- –––, 2011, “The Fiction of Creationism,” in Franck Lihoreau (ed.), Truth in Fiction, Heusenstamm: Ontos, 203–221.
- –––, 2012, “Characterization and Existence in Modal Meinongianism,” Grazer Philosophische Studien, 86: 23–34.
- Künne, Wolfgang, 1990, “Perception, Fiction, and Elliptical Speech,” in Klaus Jacobi and Helmut Pape (eds.), Thinking and the Structure of the World. Hector-Neri Castañeda’s Epistemic Ontology Presented and Criticised, Berlin: de Gruyter, 259–267.
- Lambert, Karel, 1982, “A Logical Interpretation of Meinong’s Principle of Independence,” Topoi 1–2, 87–96.
- –––, 1983, Meinong and the Principle of Independence. Its Place in Meinong’s Theory of Objects and Its Significance in Contemporary Philosophical Logic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Lambert, Karel (ed.), 1991, Philosophical Applications of Free Logic, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 1976, Discourse on Metaphysics / Correspondence with Arnauld / Monadology, Chicago: Open Court.
- Lejewski, Czeslaw, 1954, “Logic and Existence,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 5: 104–119.
- Leonard, Henry S., 1956, “The Logic of Existence,” Philosophical Studies, 7: 49–64.
- Lewis, David, 1990, “Noneism or Allism?” Mind 99, 23–31.
- –––, 2004, “Tensed Quantifiers,” in D. Zimmerman (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics (Volume 1), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3–14.
- Linsky, Bernard, and Zalta, Edward N., 1994, “In Defense of the Simplest Quantified Modal Logic,” Philosophical Perspectives, 8: 431–458.
- Lihoreau, Franck (ed.), 2011, Truth in Fiction, Heusenstamm: Ontos.
- Macdonald, Margaret, 1954, “The Language of Fiction,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supp. Vol. 27: 165–184.
- Mally, Ernst, 1912, Gegenstandstheoretische Grundlagen der Logik und Logistik, (Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 148), Leipzig: Barth.
- Markosian, Ned, 2004, “A Defense of Presentism,” in D. Zimmerman (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics (Volume 1), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 47–82.
- McGinn, Colin, 2000, Logical Properties. Identity, Existence, Predication, Necessity, Truth, Oxford: Clarendon.
- Meinong, Alexius, 1960, “On the Theory of Objects,” in Roderick Chisholm (ed.), Realism and the Background of Phenomenology, Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 76–117. [German original first published in Meinong 1904.]
- –––, 1972, Über Möglichkeit und Wahrscheinlichkeit, in Rudolf Haller and Rudolf Kindinger (eds.), Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe VI, Graz: Akademische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt. [Originally published in 1915.]
- –––, 1973, “Über die Stellung der Gegenstandstheorie im System der Wissenschaften,” in Rudolf Haller and Rudolf Kindinger (eds.), Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe V, Graz: Akademische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt, 197–365. [Originally published in 1907.]
- Meinong, Alexius (ed.), 1904, Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie, Leipzig: Barth.
- Menzel, Christopher, “Possible Worlds,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/possible-worlds/>.
- Milne, Daniel Alexander, 2013, “Everett’s Dilemma: How Fictional Realists Can Cope with Ontic Vagueness,” Grazer Philosophische Studien, 88: 33–54.
- Murday, Brendan, 2015, “Fictional Realism and Indeterminate Identity,” Journal of Philosophical Research, 40: 205–225.
- Nolan, Daniel, 2008, “Properties and Paradox in Graham Priest’s Towards Non-Being,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76 (1): 191–198.
- Noth, Winfried, 2006, “Representations of Imaginary, Nonexistent, or Nonfigurative Objects,” Cognitio: Revista de Filosofía, 7: 277–291.
- Orlando, Eleonora, 2008, “Fictional Names Without Fictional Objects,” Crítica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía, 40: 111–127.
- Parsons, Terence, 1975, “A Meinongian Analysis of Fictional Objects,” Grazer Philosophische Studien, 1: 73–86.
- –––, 1980, Nonexistent Objects, New Haven: Yale University Press.
- –––, 1982, “Are There Nonexistent Objects?” American Philosophical Quarterly, 19: 365–371.
- Pasniczek, Jacek, 1997, The Logic of Intentional Objects: A Meinongian Version of Classical Logic, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- –––, 2001, “The Meinongian Logic of Fiction,” in Liliana Albertazzi, Dale Jacquette, and Roberto Poli (eds.), The School of Alexius Meinong (Western Philosophy Series 57), Aldershot: Ashgate, 457–476.
- Perszyk, Kenneth J., 1993, Nonexistent Objects. Meinong and Contemporary Philosophy (Nihoff International Philosophy Series 49), Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Plantinga, Alvin, 1983, “On Existentialism,” Philosophical Studies, 44: 1–20.
- Priest, Graham, 2005, Towards Non-Being. The Logic and Metaphysics of Intentionality, Oxford: Clarendon.
- –––, 2008, “Replies to Nolan and Kroon,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76: 208–214.
- –––, 2011, “Creating Non-existents,” in Franck Lihoreau (ed.), Truth in Fiction, Heusenstamm: Ontos, 107–118.
- Prior, A. N., 1968, Papers on Time and Tense, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- –––, 1971, Objects of Thought, P. T. Geach and A. J. P. Kenny (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Proudfoot, Diane, 2006, “Possible Worlds, Semantics and Fiction,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 35: 9–40.
- Quine, Willard Van Orman, 1953, “On What There Is,” in From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1–19; originally published in Review of Metaphysics, 2 (1948): 21–38.
- Rapaport, William J., 1978, “Meinongian Theories and a Russellian Paradox,” Noûs, 12: 153–180.
- –––, 1981, “How to Make the World Fit Our Language: An Essay in Meinongian Semantics,” Grazer Philosophische Studien, 14: 1–21.
- Reid, Thomas, 1785, Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, Derek R. Brookes (ed.), University Park, Penns.: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2002.
- Reicher, Maria Elisabeth, 2001, “Predicable and Non-Predicable Universals,” in Uwe Meixner (ed.), Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age. Proceedings of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium. Kirchberg am Wechsel (Austria) 1999 (Schriftenreihe der Wittgenstein-Gesellschaft 28), Wien: öbv&hpt, 89–98.
- –––, 2005a, Referenz, Quantifikation und ontologische Festlegung, Frankfurt am Main: Ontos.
- –––, 2005b, “Russell, Meinong, and the Problem of Existent Nonexistents,” in Imaguire, Guido/ Linsky, Bernard (eds.), On Denoting: 1905–2005, München: Philosophia, 167–193.
- –––, 2010, “The Ontology of Fictional Characters,” in J. Eder, F. Jannidis, and R. Schneider (eds.), Characters in Fictional Worlds, Berlin: de Gruyter, 111–133.
- Rescher, Nicholas, 1969, “The Concept of Non-Existent Possibles,” in Essays in Philosophical Analysis, Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
- Routley, Richard, 1966, “Some Things Do Not Exist,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 7: 251–276.
- –––, 1979, “The Semantical Structure of Fictional Discourse,” Poetics, 8: 3–30.
- –––, 1980, Exploring Meinong’s Jungle and Beyond, Canberra: Research School of the Social Sciences.
- Russell, Bertrand, 1903, Principles of Mathematics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- –––, 1973a, “Review of: A. Meinong, Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie,” in Douglas Lackey (ed.), Bertrand Russell. Essays in Analysis, London: Allen and Unwin, 77–88. [Originally published in Mind, 14 (1905): 530–538].
- –––, 1973b, “Review of: A. Meinong, ‘Über die Stellung der Gegenstandstheorie im System der Wissenschaften’,” in Douglas Lackey (ed.), Bertrand Russell. Essays in Analysis, London: Allen and Unwin, 89–93. [Originally published in Mind, 16 (1907): 436–439].
- –––, 1973c, “On Denoting,” in Douglas Lackey (ed.), Bertrand Russell. Essays in Analysis, London: Allen and Unwin, 103–119. [Originally published in Mind 14 (1905), 479–493.]
- Sainsbury, R. M., 2010, Fiction and Fictionalism, Oxon–New York: Routledge.
- Salmon, Nathan, 1998, “Nonexistence,” Noûs, 32 (3): 277–319.
- Sauchelli, Andrea, 2012, “Fictional Objects, Non-existence, and the Principle of Characterization,” Philosophical Studies, 159: 139–146.
- Schnieder, Benjamin and von Solodkoff, Tatjana, 2009, “In Defence of Fictional Realism,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 59: 138–149.
- Searle, John R., 1983, Intentionality. An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Sierszulska, Anna, 2005, Meinong on Meaning and Truth, Frankfurt/Main: Ontos.
- Simons, Peter, 1992, “On What There Isn’t: The Meinong-Russell Dispute,” in Philosophy and Logic in Central Europe from Bolzano to Tarski. Selected Essays, Dordrecht: Kluwer, 159–191.
- –––, 1994, “Meinong’s Contribution to the Development of Non-Classical Logic,” Conceptus, 27 (71): 187–202.
- Smith, Barry, 1980/81, “Ingarden vs. Meinong on the Logic of Fiction,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 4 (1): 93–105.
- Smith, David W., 1975, “Meinongian Objects,” Grazer Philosophische Studien, 1: 43–71.
- Smith, Janet Farrell, 1985, “The Russell-Meinong Debate,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 45: 305–350.
- Swanson, Carolyn, 2011, Reburial of Nonexistents. Reconsidering the Meinong-Russell-Debate, Amsterdam–New York: Rodopi.
- Thomasson, Amie L., 1996, “Fiction, Modality and Dependent Abstracta,” Philosophical Studies, 84: 295–320.
- –––, 1999, Fiction and Metaphysics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- van Inwagen, Peter, 1977, “Creatures of Fiction,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 14 (4): 299–308.
- Voltolini, Alberto, 2006, How Ficta Follow Fiction. A Syncretistic Account of Fictional Objects, Dordrecht: Springer.
- –––, 2006, “Are There Non-existent Intentionalia?,” Philosophical Quarterly, 56: 436– 441.
- –––, 2010, “Against against Fictional Realism,” Grazer Philosophische Studien, 80: 47–63.
- Weinberg, Rivka, 2013, “Existence: Who Needs It? The Non-identity Problem and Merely Possible People,” Bioethics, 27: 471–484.
- White, Morton, 1968, “The Use of ‘Exists’,” in Iseminger, Gary (ed.), Logic and Philosophy, New York: Appleton–Century–Crofts, 127–145.
- Williams, C. J. F., 1981, What Is Existence? Oxford: Clarendon.
- Williamson, Timothy, 2013, Modal Logic as Metaphysics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Wolterstorff, Nicholas, 1980, Works and Worlds of Art, Oxford: Clarendon.
- Zalta, Edward N., 1983, Abstract Objects. An Introduction to Axiomatic Metaphysics, Dordrecht: Reidel.
- –––, 1988, Intensional Logic and the Metaphysics of Intentionality, Cambridge: MIT Press.
- –––, 1992, “On Mally’s Alleged Heresy: A Reply,” History of Philosophical Logic, 13 (1): 59–68.
- –––, 1995, “Two (Related) World Views,” Noûs, 29 (2): 189–211.
- Zemach, Eddy M., 1993, “Existence and Nonexistents,” Erkenntnis, 39: 145–166.
- –––, 1996, “Emotion and Fictional Beings,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 54: 41–48.
Academic Tools
How to cite this entry. Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society. Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.
Other Internet Resources
- Plato and Meinong, web page relating Meinong’s objects and Platonic objects, maintained by Edward N. Zalta (Stanford University).
- The Vocabulary of Ontology: Existence, web page on the definition of existence, maintained by Raul Corazzon, at the website Ontology. A Resource Guide for Philosopher.
Acknowledgments
This article is an outcome of the project “Philosophie et histoire de la logique. Les concepts formels” at the University of Geneva, in which I was involved from January to September 2004. I am indebted to the University of Geneva for financial support. I also wish to thank Gideon Rosen and Edward N. Zalta for constructive criticism and helpful advice.