Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
A |
B |
C |
D |
E |
F |
G |
H |
I |
J |
K |
L |
M |
N |
O |
P |
Q |
R |
S |
T |
U |
V |
W |
X |
Y |
Z
Bernard Bosanquet
Bernard Bosanquet (1848-1923), British philosopher, political theorist
and social reformer, was one of the principal exponents (with
F.H. Bradley) of late nineteenth and early
twentieth century `Absolute Idealism.'
Bernard Bosanquet was born on July 14, 1848 in Rock Hall (near
Alnwick), Northumberland, England. He was the youngest of five sons of
the Reverend Robert William Bosanquet by the latter's second wife,
Caroline (MacDowall). Bernard's eldest brother, Charles, was one of
the founders of the Charity Organization Society and its first
Secretary. Another brother, Day, was an Admiral in the Royal Navy and
served as Governor of South Australia. Yet another, Holford, was
elected to the Royal Society and was a fellow of St John's College,
Oxford.
Bosanquet studied at Harrow (1862-1867) and at Balliol College, Oxford
(1867-1870), where he fell under the influence of idealist `German'
philosophy, principally through the work of Edward Caird and
T.H. Green. (Green described him as "the most gifted man of his
generation.") Bosanquet received first class honors in classical
moderations (1868) and literae humaniores (1870) and, upon
graduation, was elected to a Fellowship of University College, Oxford,
over F.H. Bradley. While at University College, Bosanquet taught the
history of logic and the history of moral philosophy; his only
published work during this time was a translation of G.F. Schoemann's
Athenian Constitutional History.
Upon receipt of a small inheritance in 1881, Bosanquet left Oxford for
London, where he became active in adult education and social work
through such organizations as the London Ethical Society (founded
1886), the Charity Organisation Society, and the short-lived London
School of Ethics and Social Philosophy (1897-1900). During this time
he met and married (in 1895) Helen Dendy, an activist in social work
and social reform, who was to be a leading figure in the Royal
Commission on the Poor Laws (1905-1909).
While in London, Bosanquet was also able to engage in
philosophical work, and many of his major publications date from this
time. Some of them--such as The Philosophical Theory of the
State and Psychology of the Moral Self--were developed from
lectures that he gave to adult education groups. He was an early
member of the Aristotelian Society, and served as its Vice President
(1888) and President (1894-1898).
At the age of 55, Bosanquet briefly returned to professorial life,
as Professor of Moral Philosophy at the University of St Andrews in
Scotland (1903-1908), but his health was not good and he wished to
devote more time to original philosophical writing. He retired to
Oxshott, Surrey, where he nevertheless remained active in social work
and philosophical circles. In 1911 and 1912, Bosanquet was elected
Gifford Lecturer in the University of Edinburgh. The text of these
lectures--The Principle of Individuality and Value and The
Value and Destiny of the Individual--serve as the most developed
statement of his metaphysical views. It is important for a proper
understanding of Bosanquet's philosophy that one recognize that the
elaboration of his metaphysics came some time after his work in
ethics, social work and political philosophy.
The publication of the Gifford lectures incited a good deal of
critical reaction to Bosanquet's views, particularly in metaphysics
(e.g., on the `idealism/materialism' controversy and on the nature of
finite individuality), logic (e.g., concerning the status of
propositions and the nature of inference), and ethics. Despite his
vigorous participation in such exchanges, present throughout
Bosanquet's work is his desire to find common ground among
philosophers of various traditions and to show relationships among
different schools of thought, rather than to dwell on what separates
them.
In spite of the challenges to idealism from both within and
outside of the academic world, discussion of Bosanquet's work
continued through the early decades of the 20th century. He died in
his 75th year in London on February 8, 1923.
At the time of his death, Bosanquet was arguably "the most popular
and the most influential of the English idealists" (J.H. Randall). He
was the author or editor of more than 20 books and some 150
articles. The breadth of his philosophical interests is obvious from
the range of topics treated in his books and essays--logic,
aesthetics, epistemology, social and public policy, psychology,
metaphysics, ethics and political philosophy. For his contributions to
philosophy and to social work, he had been made a Fellow of the
British Academy in 1907, and had received honorary degrees from
Glasgow, Birmingham, Durham, and St Andrews.
Bosanquet was one of
the earliest philosophers in the Anglo-American world to appreciate
the work of Edmund Husserl, Benedetto Croce, Giovanni Gentile and
Emile Durkheim, and the relation of his thought to that of Ludwig
Wittgenstein, G.E. Moore and Bertrand Russell is significant, though
still largely unexplored. Although F.H. Bradley is today far better
known in philosophical circles, in his obituary in the Times,
Bosanquet was said to have been "the central figure of British
philosophy for an entire generation."
Bosanquet's philosophical views were in many ways a reaction to 19th
century Anglo-American empiricism and materialism (e.g., that of
Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill and Alexander Bain), but also to that
of contemporary personalistic idealism (e.g. that of Andrew Seth
Pringle-Pattison, James Ward, Hastings Rashdall, W.R. Sorley, and
J.M.E. McTaggart) and organicism (e.g. Herbert Spencer). Bosanquet
held that the inspiration of many of his ideas could be found in
Hegel, Kant, and Rousseau and, ultimately, in classical Greek thought.
Indeed, while at the beginning of his philosophical career Bosanquet
described Kant and Hegel as "the great masters who `sketched the
plan'," he said that the most important influence on him was that of
Plato. The result was a brand of idealist philosophical thought that
combined the Anglo-Saxon penchant for empirical study with a
vocabulary and conceptual apparatus borrowed from the
continent. Bosanquet is generally considered to be one of the most
`Hegelian' of the British Idealists, though the extent to which the
term `Hegelian' is appropriate or illuminating in describing his work
has been a matter of some recent debate.
More directly, Bosanquet's thought shows a number of similarities
to that of T.H. Green, his teacher, and to Bradley, his
contemporary. Bosanquet himself acknowledges that these similarities
are far from coincidental. He frequently admits his debt to Green's
works and, as late as 1920, he wrote that "since the appearance of
Ethical Studies... I have recognized [Bradley] as my master; and
there is never, I think, any more than a verbal difference or
difference of emphasis, between us".
There is, however, at least some hyperbole in such comments.
Bosanquet did not follow either Green or Bradley blindly, and there
are important differences in his work. While he defended Green's
ethical theory and many of Green's conclusions, he addressed a number
of issues never dealt with in Green's corpus. Moreover, while it is
clear that Bosanquet considered Bradley's work in metaphysics and
ethics to have been momentous, this admiration was no doubt influenced
by the fact that Bradley's philosophy and method reflected interests
and an approach that Bosanquet had arrived at quite independently.
[In progress.]
[In progress.]
[In progress.]
[In progress.]
Bosanquet's social and political philosophy is called `idealist'
because of his view that social relations and institutions were not
ultimately material phenomena, but best understood as existing at the
level of human consciousness. Writing largely in reaction to the
utilitarianism of Bentham and Mill and to the natural-rights based
theory of Herbert Spencer, Bosanquet's views show both a strong
influence of Hegel and an important debt to Kant and to the classical
Greek thought of Plato and Aristotle. Indeed, Bosanquet often spoke of
his political theory as reflecting principles found in `classical
philosophy,' and one of his early works was a commentary on Plato's
Republic. Nevertheless, his political thought lies clearly within the
tradition of liberalism.
The main source for Bosanquet's social and political philosophy is
The Philosophical Theory of the State (1899; 4th ed., 1923),
though many of his ideas are developed in dozens of articles and
essays which he wrote for professional academic journals, for
publications of the Charity Organisation Society and for the popular
press. Like many of his fellow idealists (notably T.H. Green, D.G.
Ritchie, William Wallace, John Watson and, to a lesser degree, F.H.
Bradley). Bosanquet's principal concern was to explain the basis of
political authority and the state, the place of the citizen in
society, and the nature, source and limits of human rights. The
political theory that he develops is importantly related to his
metaphysics and logic--particularly to such notions as the individual,
the general will, `the best life', society, and the state. In order to
provide a coherent account of such issues, Bosanquet argued, one must
abandon some of the assumptions of the liberal tradition--particularly
those that reveal a commitment to 'individualism'.
Bosanquet saw authority and the state neither as based on
individual consent or a social contract, nor as simply institutions
where there is a general recognition of a sovereign, but as products
of the natural development of human life, and as expressions of what
he called the `real' or general will. On Bosanquet's view, the will of
the individual is "a mental system" whose parts--"ideas or groups of
ideas"--are "connected in various degrees, and more or less
subordinated to some dominant ideas which, as a rule, dictate the
place and importance of the others" (i.e., of the other ideas that one
has). Thus, Bosanquet writes that, "[i]n order to obtain a full
statement of what we will, what we want at any moment must at least be
corrected and amended by what we want at all other moments." But the
process does not stop there. He continues: "this cannot be done
without also correcting and amending it so as to harmonise it with
what others want, which involves an application of the same process to
them." In other words, if we wish to arrive at an accurate statement
of what our will is, we must be concerned not only with what we wish
at some particular moment, but also with all of the other wants,
purposes, associations and feelings that we and others have (or might
have) given all of the knowledge available. The result is one's `real'
or the `general will'.
Bosanquet sees a relation between the 'real' or 'general will' and
the `common good.' He writes that "The General Will seems to be, in
the last resort, the ineradicable impulse of an intelligent being to a
good extending beyond itself." This `good' is nothing other than "the
existence and the perfection of human personality" which he identifies
with "the excellence of souls" and the complete realisation of the
individual. It is so far as the state reflects the general will and
this common good that its authority is legitimate and its action
morally justifiable. Bosanquet describes the function of the state,
then, as `the hindrance of hindrances' to human development.
The influence of Rousseau and Hegel is clearly evident here. Indeed,
Bosanquet saw in Hegel's Philosophy of Right a plausible
account of the modern state as an `organism' or whole united around a
shared understanding of the good. Moreover, like Hegel, he argued that
the state, like all other social `institutions,' was best understood
as an ethical idea and as existing at the level of consciousness
rather than just material reality. Within nation states, Bosanquet
held that the authority of the state is absolute, because social life
requires a consistent co-ordination of the activities of individuals
and institutions.
Still, although Bosanquet believed that the state was absolute, he
did not exclude the possibility of an organized system of
international law. The conditions for an effective recognition and
enforcement of such a system were, he thought, absent at that
moment--though he held out hope that the League of Nations reflected
the beginnings of the consciousness of a genuine human community and
that it might provide a mechanism by which multinational action could
be accomplished.
Because the state can be said to reflect the general will that is
also each individual's real will, Bosanquet held (following Rousseau)
that sometimes individuals can be required to engage in certain
activities for their own good--that is they can be `forced to be
free.' Moreover, he maintained that it is in terms of the 'common
good' that one's `station' or `function' in society is defined, and it
is the conscientious carrying out of the duties that are attached to
one's `station' that constitutes ethical behaviour. In fact, on
Bosanquet's account, it is primarily in light of one's service in the
state that a person has the basis for speaking of his or her
particular identity. Not surprisingly, then, Bosanquet was frequently
challenged by those who claimed that he was anti-democratic and that
his philosophical views led to a devaluation of the individual. Such
attacks ignore, however, Bosanquet's insistence on liberty as the
essence and quality of the human person and his emphasis on the moral
development of the human individual and on limiting the state from
directly promoting morality (which reflects both his own reading of
Kant and the influence of Green's Kantianism.) Moreover, while
Bosanquet did not hold that there were any a priori
restrictions on state action, he held that there were a number of
practical conditions that did limit it. For example, while law was
seen as necessary to the promotion of the common good, it could not
make a person good, and social progress could often be better achieved
by volunteer action. (It is just this emphasis that Bosanquet found
and defended in the approach to social work of the Charity
Organisation Society.)
Although the state and law employ compulsion and restraint, they
were considered to be `positive' in that they provided the material
conditions for liberty, the functioning of social institutions, and
the development of individual moral character. For Bosanquet, then,
there was no incompatibility between liberty and the law. Moreover,
since individuals are necessarily social beings, their rights were
neither absolute and inalienable, but reflected the `function' or
`positions' they held in the community. For such rights to have not
only moral but legal weight, Bosanquet insisted that they had to be
`recognized' by the state in law. Strictly speaking, then, there could
be no rights against the state. Nevertheless, Bosanquet acknowledged
that, where social institutions were fundamentally corrupt, even
though there was no right to rebellion, there could be a duty to
resist.
Although Bosanquet is sometimes regarded as a
conservative, recent studies have pointed out that he was an active
Liberal and, in the 1910s, supported the Labour Party. He insisted on
the positive role that the state can have in the promotion of social
well being and he was in favour of worker ownership. It is also worth
noting that Bosanquet's audience was as much the professional in
social work or the politician, as the philosopher. He was
well-informed of the political situation in Britain, on the continent,
and in the United States. His interests extended to economics and
social welfare, and his work in adult education and social work
provides a strong empirical dimension to his work. This background
provided him with a broad base from which to reply to challenges from
many of his critics-- e.g., from philosophers, like Mill and Spencer,
and from social reformers, such as Sidney and Beatrice Webb and, the
founder of the Salvation Army, General William Booth. Despite charges
that Bosanquet's political philosophy is simplistic, inconsistent, or
naive, Adam Ulam notes that The Philosophical Theory of the
State "has a comprehensiveness and an awareness of conflicting
political and philosophical opinions which give it a supreme
importance in modern political thought. Bosanquet is both a political
theorist and a political analyst."
It has sometimes been suggested that the influences of Kant and
Hegel lead to a tension in Bosanquet's political thought. Bosanquet's
emphasis on the moral development of the human individual and on
limiting the state from directly promoting morality clearly reflects
both his own reading of Kant and the Kantian influences on
Green. Moreover, Bosanquet believed that the `best life' that he
describes as the `end' of the individual and of the state alike,
approximates what Kant referred to as `the kingdom of ends'. Even
Bosanquet's justification of the authority of the state can be seen as
a reflection of a Kantian imperative that one wills the state as a
necessary means to the moral end.
[In progress.]
[In progress.]
Interest in Bosanquet's work--as with idealism as a whole--waned
during the middle decades of the 20th century. Of the idealists, the
writings of Bradley and, in political theory, Green, are now much
better known. There is no simple explanation of this; many factors
seem relevant.
First, some of the work that made Bosanquet's reputation in his
time--his popular essays, the books and articles that came out of his
university extension courses, and his involvement in social
policy--now seems largely dated. For example, several of his essays
lack the logical rigor that one finds in material destined for the
more specialized audience of academic philosophers. While insightful
and wide ranging--and while accessible to a much wider audience than
the work of other idealists, such as Bradley and
J.M.E. McTaggart--Bosanquet's writings lack the sharpness, the
density, and, at times, the outrageousness of those of some of his
contemporaries.
It has been suggested, as well, that some of the concepts central
to Bosanquet's work are not clearly defined, and Bosanquet himself was
an indifferent literary stylist. His work often betrays a looseness
that one tends to find in texts based on lectures prepared for general
audiences or for classes, and even his early work on logic was
remarked upon for its "stiffness." But these primarily stylistic
concerns may also be a product of refusing to sever the analysis of
concepts from the experience which Bosanquet was trying to describe.
There are other reasons that no doubt contributed to the decline
of interest in Bosanquet's work. Aside from the general collapse of
idealism as a philosophical movement--by the early part of the 20th
century, it was seen by many as a philosophical dead- end--and the
suspicion of what was regarded by later generations as its obscure
vocabulary, Bosanquet's association with the majority report of the
Poor Law Reform Commission and his alleged championing of the nation
state, led many to see him as a conservative if not reactionary
thinker whose contributions to philosophy and politics were outdated
almost as soon as they had been published.
In recent years, however, there has been a renewed interest in
Bosanquet's work--particularly concerning his philosophical and social
thought, which is experiencing a revival in the work of some
contemporary liberal theorists. Given the number of studies published
during the past twenty years on Hegel, Green and, more recently,
Bradley, and given the reevaluation of the significance of the work of
British idealism and its place in the history of philosophy, it seems
likely that there will be a reconsideration of the contribution of
Bosanquet's philosophy as well.
A Comprehensive Listing:
The most comprehensive list of Bosanquet's work is found in Peter
P. Nicholson, "A Bibliography of the Writings of Bernard Bosanquet
(1848-1923)," Idealistic Studies, 8 (1978): 261-280.
Principal Works
The publication of a 20 volume set of The Works of Bernard
Bosanquet (edited by William Sweet) is planned by Thoemmes
Press (Bristol, U.K.) for 1999. This will include the following
principal works:
- Knowledge and Reality, A Criticism of Mr. F. H. Bradley's
'Principles of Logic'. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, 1885.
- Logic, or the Morphology of Knowledge. Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1888. 2d ed., 1911.
- Essays and Addresses. London, Swan Sonnenschein, 1889.
- A History of Aesthetic, London: Swan Sonnenschein,
1892. 2d ed., 1904.
- The Civilization of Christendom and Other Studies.
London: Swan Sonnenschein, 1893.
- The Essentials of Logic: Being Ten Lectures on Judgement
and Inference. London and New York: Macmillan, 1895.
- Aspects of the Social Problem, London, 1895.
- A Companion to Plato's Republic for English Readers: Being
a Commentary adapted to Davies and Vaughan's Translation. New
York/London, 1895.
- "Hegel's Theory of the Political Organism," Mind, n.s.
VII
(1898): 1-14.
- The Philosophical Theory of the State, London, 1899;
4th
ed., 1923.
- Psychology of the Moral Self, London and New York:
Macmillan, 1897.
- "The Meaning of Teleology," Proceedings of the British
Academy, II (1905-1906): 235-245.
- "Les idees politiques de Rousseau," Revue de metaphysique
et de morale, XX (1912): 321-340.
- The Principle of Individuality and Value. The Gifford
Lectures for 1911 delivered in Edinburgh University. London:
Macmillan, 1912.
- The Value and Destiny of the Individual. The Gifford
Lectures for 1912 delivered in Edinburgh University. London:
Macmillan, 1913.
- The Distinction Between Mind and its Objects. The Adamson
Lecture for 1913 with an Appendix. Manchester: University
Press, 1913
- Three Lectures on Aesthetic, London: Macmillan, 1915.
- Social and International Ideals: Being Studies in
Patriotism, London: Macmillan, 1917.
- Some Suggestions in Ethics, London: Macmillan, 1918;
2nd ed. 1919.
- "Do Finite Individuals possess a substantive or an
adjectival mode of being?", Life and Finite Individuality,
(ed. H. Wildon Carr), Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, supp.
vol. 1, (1918): 75-102; 179-194 (Reprinted from Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society, n.s. XVIII (1917-1918): 479-506.)
- Implication and Linear Inference, London: Macmillan,
1920.
- What Religion Is, London: Macmillan, 1920.
- The Meeting of Extremes in Contemporary Philosophy.
London: Macmillan, 1921.
- Three Chapters on the Nature of Mind, London:
Macmillan, 1923.
- "Life and Philosophy," Contemporary British Philosophy,
(ed. J.H. Muirhead), London, 1924, pp. 51-74.
- Science and Philosophy and Other Essays by the Late Bernard
Bosanquet, (ed. J.H. Muirhead and R.C. Bosanquet), London,
Allen and Unwin, 1927.
- Acton, H.B. "Bernard Bosanquet," The Encyclopedia of
Philosophy. Ed. Paul Edwards, New York, 1967, Vol. 1, pp. 347-
350.
- Acton, H.B. "The Theory of Concrete Universals," Mind,
n.s. XLV (1936): 417-31; n.s. XLVI (1937): 1-13.
- Armour, Leslie. "The Dialectics of Rationality: Bosanquet, Newman
and the Concept of Assent," in Rationality Today, Ottawa, ON:
University of Ottawa Press, 1979, pp. 491-497.
- Barker, Ernest. Political Thought in England from Spencer to
Today. London, 1915. (Later editions appear under the title:
Political Thought in England: 1848-1914.) Ch. 3.
- Bedau, Hugo Adam. "Retribution and the Theory of Punishment,"
Journal of Philosophy 75
(1978): 601-620.
- Bellamy, Richard. "T.H. Green, J.S. Mill, and Isaiah Berlin on
the Nature of Liberty and Liberalism," in Jurisprudence: Cambridge
Essays. Ed. H. Gross and R. Harrison, Oxford, 1992,
pp. 257-285.
- Bellamy, Richard (ed.) Victorian Liberalism:
Nineteenth-century Political Thought and Practice. London,
1990.
- Bonville, William James. Footnotes to a Fairytale: a study of
the nature of expression in the
arts. St. Louis: Green, 1979.
- Bosanquet, Helen. Bernard Bosanquet: A Short Account of his Life
. London, 1924.
- Bradley, Andrew Cecil. Bernard Bosanquet. London, 1924;
reprinted in Proceedings of the British Academy, IX (1924).
- Bradley, James. "Hegel in Britain: A Brief History of British
Commentary and Attitudes," The Heythrop Journal, Vol. 20,
(1979): 1-24; 163-182.
- Broad, C.D. "The Notion of a General Will," Mind, n.s.
XXVIII, (1919): 502-504.
- Bussey, Gertrude Carman. "Dr. Bosanquet's Doctrine of Freedom,"
Philosophical Review, XXV (1916): 711-719 and 728-730.
- Cain, Edward Robert. The Rationalist Conception of Freedom in
the Political Theory of Bernard Bosanquet. Ph.D. thesis in
political science, Columbia University, New York, 1952.
- Calleo, David Patrick. The Nationalist State and Co-Existence:
Herder, Coleridge, and Bosanquet. Ph.D. thesis in political
science, Yale University, New Haven, 1959.
- Carr, H. Wildon. "In memoriam Bernard Bosanquet: Some personal
recollections," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
n.s. XXIII (1922-1923): 263-272.
- Carritt, E.F. Morals and Politics: Theories of their Relation
from Hobbes and Spinoza to Marx and Bosanquet. Oxford, 1935.
- Cole, G.D.H. "Loyalties," Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, n.s. XXVI (1925-1926): 151-170.
- Collini, S. "Hobhouse, Bosanquet and the State: Philosophical
Idealism and Political Argument in England: 1880-1918," Past and
Present, 72 (1976): 86-111.
- Collini, S. "Sociology and Idealism in Britain: 1880-1920,"
Archives europeennes de sociologie, 19 (1978): 3-50.
- Crane, Marion Delia. "Dr. Bosanquet's Doctrine of Freedom,"
Philosophical Review, XXV (1916): 719-728.
- Crane, Marion Delia. "The Method in the Metaphysics of Bernard
Bosanquet," Philosophical Review, XXIX (1920): 437-452.
- Crane (Carroll), Marion. The Principles of Absolutism in the
Metaphysics of Bernard Bosanquet. New York. Ph.D. thesis in
philosophy, Cornell University, 1921. (Reprinted in "The Principle of
Individuality in the Metaphysics of Bernard Bosanquet,"
Philosophical Review, XXX (1921): 1-23 and "The Nature of the
Absolute in the Metaphysics of Bernard Bosanquet, Philosophical
Review, XXX (1921): 178-191.)
- Cunningham, G. Watts. "Bosanquet on Philosophic Method,"
Philosophical Review, XXXV (1926): 315-327.
- Cunningham, G. Watts. "Bosanquet on Teleology as a Metaphysical
Category," Philosophical Review, XXXII (1923): 612-624.
- Cunningham, G. Watts. The Idealist Argument in Recent British
and American Philosophy. New York, 1933.
- den Otter, Sandra. British Idealism and Social Explanation: A
Study in Late Victorian Thought, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996.
- Dockhorn, Klaus. Die Staatsphilosophie des Englischen
Idealismus. Koeln/Bochum-Langendreer: Heinrich Poppinghaus o.
H.-G., 1937. (Bosanquet is discussed on pp. 61-116.)
- Emmet, Dorothy. "Bosanquet's social theory of the state," The
Sociological Review, 37 (1989): 104-127.
- Ewing, A.C. The Individual, the State, and World
Government. New York, 1947.
- Feinberg, Walter. A Comparative Study of the Social
Philosophies of John Dewey and Bernard Bosanquet. Ph.D. thesis in
philosophy, Boston University, 1966.
- Fisher, John. "The Ease and Difficulty of Theory," Dialectics
and Humanism, 3 (1976)): 117-
124.
- Fowler, W.S. "Neo-Hegelianism and State Education in England,"
Educational Theory, 9 (1959): 55-61.
- Gaus, Gerald. "Green, Bosanquet and the philosophy of coherence"
in Routledge History of Philosophy, Volume 7 - The Nineteenth
Century, Ed. C.L. Ten, London, 1994.
- Gaus, Gerald. The Modern Liberal Theory of Man. Canberra:
Croom Helm, 1983.
- Geyer, Denton L. "Democratic and Totalitarian Conceptions of
Freedom," Santiniketan - The Visvabharti Quarterly, 18 (1952):
111-121.
- Gibbins, John R. "Liberalism, Nationalism and the English
Idealists," in History of European Ideas, 15 (1992): 491-497.
- Gilbert, K. "The Principle of Reason in the Light of Bosanquet's
Philosophy," Philosophical Review, XXXII (1923): 599-611.
- Ginsberg, Morris. "Is there a general will?," Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society, XX (1919-1920): 89-112.
- Greenleaf, W.H. The British Political Tradition, 3 vols.,
London: Methuen, 1983-1987.
- Harris, Frederick Philip. The Neo-Idealist Political Theory:
Its Continuity with the British Tradition. New York. King's Crown
Press, 1944 (Ph.D. thesis, Columbia University).
- Haldar, Hira-lal. Neo-hegelianism. London, 1927.
- Hemingway, John Luther. The Emergence of an Ethical
Liberalism: A Study in Idealist Liberalism from Thomas Hill Green to
the Present. Ph.D. thesis in political science. University of
Iowa, 1979.
- Hobbs, Grimsley, T. Personality and Self in the Views of
Francis Herbert Bradley and Bernard Bosanquet. Ph.D. thesis in
philosophy, Duke University, 1955.
- Hobhouse, Leonard T. The Metaphysical Theory of the State.
London, 1918.
- Hoernle, R.F.A. "Bernard Bosanquet's Philosophy of the State,"
Political Science Quarterly, 34 (1919): 609-631.
- Hoernle, R.F.A. "In Memoriam: Bernard Bosanquet," The Journal
of Philosophy, XX (1923): 505-516.
- Hogdson, S.H. "Bernard Bosanquet's Recent Criticism of Green's
Ethics," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, II
(1901-1902): 66-71.
- Houang, Francois. "Bernard Bosanquet," Dictionnaire des
philosophes. 2 vols. Vol. 1, Paris, 1984. pp. 360-365.
- Houang, Francois. De l'humanisme a l'absolutisme: l'evolution
de la pensee religieuse du neo-hegelien anglais Bernard Bosanquet.
Paris, Vrin, 1954.
- Houang, Francois. Le neo-hegelianisme en Angleterre: la
philosophie de Bernard Bosanquet (1848-1923). Paris: Vrin, 1954.
- Jacobs, Ellen. Bernard Bosanquet: Social and Political
Thought. Ph.D. thesis, City University of New York, 1986.
- Jacquette, Dale, "Bosanquet's Concept of Difficult Beauty,"
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 43 (1984): 79-88.
- Joad, C.E.M. Guide to the Philosophy of Morals and Politics.
London, 1947.
- Kimpel, Benjamin Franklin. The Religious Significance of the
Philosophy of F.H. Bradley, with Special Reference to the Philosophy
of Bernard Bosanquet. Ph.D. thesis in religious studies, Yale
University, 1932.
- Lacock, Darrell Dexter. The Political Philosophy of Bernard
Bosanquet. Ph.D. thesis in philosophy, Yale University, 1967.
- Lang, Berel. "Bosanquet's Aesthetic: A History and Philosophy of
the Symbol," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 26 (1968): 377-387.
- Laski, H. "Bosanquet's Theory of the General Will,"
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, n.s. supp. vol. VIII
(1928): 45-61.
- Laslett, P. "The General Will," The Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, Ed. Paul Edwards, New York, 1967. Vol. 3, pp.
279-281.
- Laslett, P. and P.W. Cummings. "History of Political Philosophy,"
The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Ed. Paul Edwards, New York,
1967. Vol. 6, pp. 370-387.
- LeChevalier, Charles. La pensee morale de Bernard Bosanquet
(1848-1923): Etude sur l'univers moral de l'idealisme anglais au 19e
siecle. (These complementaire pour le doctorat es lettres) Paris:
Vrin, 1963. (Republished under the title Ethique et idealisme: le
courant neo-hegelien en Angleterre, Bernard Bosanquet et ses
amis. Paris: Vrin, 1963.)
- Leighton, Joseph A. "An Estimate of Bosanquet's Philosophy,"
Philosophical Review, XXXII (1923): 625-632.
- Lindsay, A.D. "Bosanquet's Theory of the General Will,"
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, n.s., supp. vol. VIII
(1928): 31-44.
- Lindsay, A.D. "Sovereignty," Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, XXIV (1923-1924): 235-254.
- Lindsay, A.D. "The State in Recent Political Theory," The
Political Quarterly, 1 (1914): 128-145.
- Mabbott, J.D. The State and Citizen. 2nd ed. London, 1952.
- MacAdam, James I. "What Rousseau Meant by the General Will", in
Rousseau's Response to Hobbes, Eds. Howard R. Cell and James
I. MacAdam, New York: Peter Lang, 1988, pp. 152-153. (This chapter
originally appeared as an article in Dialogue, V, (1966-1967):
498-515.)
- MacIver, R.M. Community: A Sociological Study. New York,
1917. (Esp. Appendix A on the individual, the association, and the
community, pp. 421-425, and Appendix B, "A Criticism of the Neo-
Hegelian Identification of Society and the State," pp. 425-433.)
- MacIver, R.M. Politics and Society, Ed. David Spitz, New
York: Atherton Press, 1969. (Contains letters between Bosanquet and
MacIver on the distinction between society and the state.)
- MacIver, R.M. "Society and the State," Philosophical
Review, XX (1911): 30-45.
- MacIver, R.M. The Modern State. London, 1926. (See
Muirhead's (1928) criticisms in Mind.)
- MacIver, R.M. The Web of Government. London, 1947.
- Marcuse, Herbert. Reason and Revelation: Hegel and the rise of
Social Theory. Boston: Beacon Press, 1960.
- Mathew, M.C. "Bosanquet's Logical Theory," Philosophical
Quarterly of India 17 :314-324.
- McBriar, A.M. An Edwardian Mixed Doubles: The Bosanquets
versus the Webbs; A Study in British Social Policy. Oxford, 1987.
- McTaggart, J. Ellis. "The Conception of Society as an Organism,"
International Journal of Ethics, VII (1896-1897): 414-434.
(Reprinted, with minor revisions, as Chapter 7 of Studies in
Hegelian Cosmology.)
- McTaggart, J.M.E. Studies in Hegelian
Cosmology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1901.
- Meadowcroft, James. Conceptualizing the State, Oxford,
1995.
- Metz, Rudolf. Die philosophischen Stromungen der Gegenwart in
Grossbritannien. Leipzig: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1935; (A Hundred
Years of British Philosophy. Trans. J.W. Harvey, T.E. Jessop and
Henry Sturt; Ed. J.H. Muirhead. London, 1938).
- Milne, A.J.M. The Social Philosophy of English Idealism.
London, 1962.
- Morrow, John. "Ancestors, Legacies and Traditions: British
Idealism in the History of Political Thought," History of Political
Thought, 6 (1985): 491-515.
- Morrow, John. "Liberalism and British Idealist Political
Philosophy: A Reassessment," History of Political Thought, 5
(1984): 91-108.
- Morris-Jones, Huw. "Bernard Bosanquet," International
Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. Ed. David L. Sills, New York:
The Free Press, 1968, Vol. 2, pp. 131-134.
- Moser, Claudia. Die Erkenntnis- und Realitaets-problematik bei
F.H. Bradley und B. Bosanquet. Wuerzburg, 1989.
- Mowat, Charles L. The Charity Organization
Society. London, 1961.
- Muirhead, J.H. (ed.) Bernard Bosanquet and his Friends.
London, 1935.
- Muirhead, J.H. The Platonic Tradition in Anglo-Saxon
Philosophy; studies in the history of idealism in England. London:
Allen and Unwin, 1931.
- Murray, Robert H. Studies in the English Social and Political
Thinkers of the Nineteenth Century. 2 vols. Cambridge: W. Heffer,
1929.
- Newman, Herbert L. Individuality in Bosanquet's Philosophy of
Society and of Religion. Ph.D. thesis in philosophy, Boston
University, 1939.
- Nicholson, Peter P. "A Bibliography of the Writings of Bernard
Bosanquet (1848-1923)," Idealistic Studies, 8 (1978): 261- 280.
- Nicholson, Peter P. "Philosophical Idealism and International
Politics: A Reply to Dr. Savigear," British Journal of
International Studies, 2 (1976): 76-83.
- Nicholson, Peter P. The Political Philosophy of the British
Idealists: Selected Studies. Cambridge, 1990.
- O'Sullivan, Noel. The Problem of Political Obligation.
London, 1986.
- Oakeshott, Michael. "Review of Bertil Pfannenstill, Bernard
Bosanquet's Philosophy of the State," Philosophy, 11 (1936):
482-483.
- Pant, Nalini. Theory of Rights: Green, Bosanquet, Spencer, and
Laski. Varanasi, Vishwavidyalaya Prakashan, 1977.
- Parker, Christopher. "Bernard Bosanquet, Historical Knowledge,
and the History of Ideas," Philosophy of Social Science, 18
(1988): 213-230.
- Paul, Leslie. The English Philosophers. London, 1953.
- Pearson, Robert and Geraint Williams, Political Thought and
Public Policy in the Nineteenth Century: An introduction. London,
1984.
- Pfannenstill, Bertil. Bernard Bosanquet's Philosophy of the
State. Lund, 1936.
- Primoratz, Igor. "The Word `Liberty' on the Chains of Galley-
Slaves: Bosanquet's Theory of the General Will," History of
Political Thought, 15 (1994): 249-267.
- Pucelle, Jean. L'idealisme en angleterre de Coleridge a
Bradley. Neuchatel, 1955.
- Quinton, Anthony. "Absolute Idealism," Proceedings of the
British Academy, LVII (1971): 303-
329.
- Rabenstein, William L. The Problem of Teleology in Relation to
the Views of Bosanquet, Royce, B. Russell, and S. Alexander.
Ph.D. thesis in philosophy, Cornell University, 1934.
- Randall, J.H., Jr. "Idealistic Social Philosophy and Bernard
Bosanquet," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, XXVI
(1966): 473-502. (Reprinted in The Career of Philosophy. 3
vols., Vol. 3, New York, Columbia University Press, 1977, pp. 97-
130.)
- Robbins, Peter. The British Hegelians: 1875-1925. New
York, 1982.
- Robinson, Jonathan. "Bradley and Bosanquet," Idealistic
Studies, 10 (1980): 1-23.
- Russell, Bertrand, C. Delisle Burns, and G.D.H. Cole. "The Nature
of the State in its External Relations," Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, n.s. vol. XVI (1915-1916): 290-310. (A round
table, with a discussion of Bosanquet's theory of international
politics.)
- Russell, Bertrand. "Philosophy in the Twentieth Century," in
Sceptical Essays. London, 1962.
- Sabine, George. "Bosanquet's Theory of the Real Will,"
Philosophical Review, XXXII (1923): 633-651.
- Sabine, George. A History of Political Theory. 4th ed.,
Hinsdale, IL: The Dryden Press, 1973. (A discussion and critique of
Bosanquet and Green, pp. 725-753.)
- Salomaa, J.A. Idealismus und Realismus in der englischen
Philosophie der Gegenwart. Helsinki, 1929.
- Schnaidman, Marvin M. The Individual and Society in Bernard
Bosanquet's Social Philosophy. Ph.D. thesis in philosophy, Cornell
University, 1975.
- Seth Pringle-Pattison, Andrew. "Do Finite Individuals possess a
substantive or an adjectival mode of being?", in Life and Finite
Individuality, Ed. H. Wildon Carr, Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, supp. vol. I, (1918): 103-126.
- Seth Pringle-Pattison, Andrew. The Idea of God in the Light of
Recent Philosophy. Oxford, 1917.
- Spiller, Gustav. The Ethical Movement in Britain: A
Documentary History. London, 1934.
- Stedman, R.E. "Nature in the Philosophy of Bosanquet,"
Mind, n.s. XLIII (1934): 321-334.
- Stedman, Ralph. "Bosanquet's Doctrine of Self-Transcendence,"
Mind, n.s. XL (1931):
- Stocks, J. L., W. G. DeBurgh and W. D. Ross. "Is there a Moral
End?," Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, n.s. supp. vol. VIII (1928):
62-98.
- Sturt, Henry. Idola Theatri: A Criticism of Oxford Thought and
Thinkers from the Standpoint of Personal Idealism. London, 1906.
- Sweet, William. "Bernard Bosanquet and the Development of
Rousseau's Idea of the General Will," in Man and Nature - L'homme
et la nature, X (1991): 179-197.
- Sweet, William. "Bosanquet and British Political Thought," in
Laval theologique et philosophique, forthcoming
- Sweet, William. "Bosanquet et les droits de la personne," in
Cahiers de l'equipe de recherche en e‚thique sociale, no. 9701,
Montreal: Equipe de recherche en ethique sociale, 1997.
- Sweet, William. "British Idealism," in The Philosophy of Law:
An Encyclopedia, (ed.
Christopher B. Gray), New York: Garland Publishing,
forthcoming 1997.
- Sweet, William. "Critical Review of Peter P. Nicholson, The
Political Philosophy of the British Idealists: Selected Studies," in
Laval theologique et philosophique, Vol. 48 (1992): 477- 480.
- Sweet, William. "F.H. Bradley and Bernard Bosanquet," in
Philosophy after F.H. Bradley, Ed. James Bradley, Bristol, UK:
Thoemmes Press, 1996.
- Sweet, William. Idealism and Rights, Lanham, MD:
University Press of America, 1997.
- Sweet, William. "Individual Rights, Communitarianism, and British
Idealism," in The Bill of Rights: Bicentennial Reflections,
(ed. Yeager Hudson and Creighton Peden), Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen
Press, 1993, pp. 261-277.
- Sweet, William. "Is Later British Idealist Political Theory
Fundamentally Conservative?," in The European Legacy: Toward New
Paradigms, Vol. 1, No. 1 (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
1996): 403-408.
- Sweet, William. "Law and Liberty in J.S. Mill and Bernard
Bosanquet," in The Social Power of Ideas, (ed. Yeager Hudson
and W. Creighton Peden), Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen Press, 1995,
pp. 361-385.
- Sweet, William. "The Legitimacy of Law: From Contract to
Community," in Indian Socio-Legal
Journal, Vol. XIX, No. 2 (1993): 69-84.
- Sweet, William. "Liberalism, Bosanquet and the Theory of the
State," in Liberalism, Oppression, and Empowerment,
(ed. Creighton Peden and Yeager Hudson), Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen
Press, 1995, pp. 3-34.
- Sweet, William. "L'individu et les droits de la personne selon
Maritain et Bosanquet," Etudes Maritainiennes / Maritain
Studies, VI (1990): 141-166.
- Sweet, William. "Was Bosanquet a Hegelian?," in Bulletin of
the Hegel Society of Great Britain, No. 31 (1995): 39-60.
- Tallon, Hugh Joseph. The Concept of Self in British and
American Idealism. Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of
America Press, 1939.
- Thakurdas, Frank. The English Utilitarians and the
Idealists. Delhi: Vishal Publication, 1978.
- Tsanoff, Radoslav A. "The Destiny of the Self in Professor
Bosanquet's Theory," Philosophical Review, XXIX (1920): 59-79.
- Turner, Frank M. The Greek Heritage in Victorian Britain.
New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981.
- Ulam, Adam. The Philosophical Foundations of English
Socialism. Cambridge, MA, 1951.
- Varma, Vishwanath Prasad. Political Philosophy. Agra,
1970.
- Vincent, Andrew. "Citizenship, poverty and the real will," The
Sociological Review, 40 (1992): 702-725.
- Vincent, Andrew. "The Individual in Hegelian Thought,"
Idealistic Studies, 12 (1982): 156-168.
- Vincent, Andrew and Raymond Plant. Philosophy, Politics and
Citizenship: the Life and Thought of the British Idealists.
Oxford, 1984.
- von Trott, A. "Bernard Bosanquet und der Einfluss Hegels auf die
englische Staatsphilosophie," Zeitschrift fuer Deutsche
Kulturphilosophie, Band 4, Heft 2 (1938): 193-199.
- Wahl, Jean. Les philosophes pluralistes d'angleterre et
d'amerique. Paris, 1920.
- Walsh, W. H. Hegelian Ethics. London: Macmillan, 1969.
- Watson, John. "Bosanquet on Mind and the Absolute,"
Philosophical Review, XXXIV (1925): 427-442.
- Weldon, T.D. States and Morals. London, 1946.
- White, David A. "Revealment: A Meeting of Extremes in Aesthetics"
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 515-520.
- Wilde, Norman. The Ethical Basis of the State. Princeton,
1924.
- Willis, Kirk. "The Introduction and Critical Reception of
Hegelian Thought in Britain 1830-1900," Victorian Studies, 32
(1988): 85-111.
[In progress.]
Bradley, F. H. |
British Idealism |
liberalism |
Copyright © 1997 by
William Sweet
wsweet@stfx.ca
A |
B |
C |
D |
E |
F |
G |
H |
I |
J |
K |
L |
M |
N |
O |
P |
Q |
R |
S |
T |
U |
V |
W |
X |
Y |
Z
Table of Contents
First published: June 15, 1997
Content last modified: June 15, 1997