Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
A |
B |
C |
D |
E |
F |
G |
H |
I |
J |
K |
L |
M |
N |
O |
P |
Q |
R |
S |
T |
U |
V |
W |
X |
Y |
Z
Bertrand Russell
Bertrand Arthur William Russell (b.1872 - d.1970), British
philosopher, logician, essayist, and social critic, best known for his
work in mathematical logic and analytic philosophy. His most
influential contributions include his defense of logicism (the view
that mathematics is in some important sense reducible to logic), and
his theories of definite descriptions and logical atomism. Along with
G.E. Moore, Russell is generally recognized as one of the founders of
analytic philosophy. He is also usually credited with being one of the
two most important logicians of the twentieth century, the other being
Kurt Gödel.
Over the course of his long career, Russell made significant
contributions, not just to philosophy, but to a range of other
subjects as well. Many of Russell's writings on a wide variety of
topics (including education, ethics, politics, history, religion and
popular science) have influenced generations of general readers. After
a life marked by controversy (including dismissals from both Trinity
College, Cambridge, and City College, New York), Russell was awarded
the Order of Merit in 1949 and the Nobel Prize for Literature in 1950.
Also noted for his many spirited anti-war and anti-nuclear protests,
Russell remained a prominent public figure until his death at the age
of 97.
For an excellent short introduction to Russell's life,
work and influence the reader is encouraged to consult John Slater's
accessible and informative Bertrand Russell (Bristol:
Thoemmes, 1994).
A short chronology of the major events in Russell's life is as
follows:
- (1872) Born May 18 at Ravenscroft, Wales.
- (1874) Death of mother and sister.
- (1876) Death of father. His grandfather, Lord John Russell (the
former Prime Minister), and grandmother succeed in overturning his
father's will to win custody of Russell and his brother.
- (1878) Death of grandfather. His grandmother, Lady Russell,
supervises his upbringing.
- (1890) Enters Trinity College, Cambridge.
- (1893) Awarded first class B.A. in Mathematics.
- (1894) Completed the Moral Sciences Tripos (Part II)
- (1894) Marries Alys Pearsall Smith.
- (1900) Meets Peano at International Congress in Paris.
- (1901) Discovers Russell's
paradox.
- (1902) Corresponds with Frege.
- (1908) Elected Fellow of the Royal Society.
- (1916) Fined 110 pounds and dismissed from Trinity College in
connection with anti-war protests.
- (1918) Imprisoned for six months in connection with anti-war
protests.
- (1921) Divorce from Alys and marriage to Dora Black.
- (1927) Opens experimental school with Dora.
- (1931) Becomes the third Earl Russell upon the death of his
brother.
- (1935) Divorce from Dora.
- (1936) Marriage to Patricia (Peter) Helen Spence.
- (1940) Appointment at City College New York revoked following
public protests.
- (1943) Dismissed from Barnes Foundation in Pennsylvania.
- (1949) Awarded the Order of Merit.
- (1950) Awarded Nobel Prize for Literature.
- (1952) Divorce from Peter and marriage to Edith Finch.
- (1955) Releases Russell-Einstein Manifesto.
- (1957) Organizes the first Pugwash Conference.
- (1958) Becomes founding President of the Campaign for Nuclear
Disarmament.
- (1961) Imprisoned for one week in connection with anti-nuclear
protests.
- (1970) Dies February 02 at Penrhyndeudraeth, Wales.
For a chronology of Russell's major publications, consult the
section below entitled Russell's Writings.
For more detailed information about Russell's life, the reader is
encouraged to consult Russell's four autobiographical volumes,
My Philosophical Development (London: George Allen &
Unwin, 1959) and The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell (3
vols, London: George Allen & Unwin, 1967, 1968, 1969).
Other
excellent sources of biographical information include C.D. Broad's
"Bertrand Russell, as Philosopher" (Bulletin of the
London Mathematical Society, 5 (1973), 328-341), Ronald Clark's
The Life of Bertrand Russell (London: J. Cape, 1975),
R.O. Gandy's "Bertrand Russell, as Mathematician"
(Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society, 5 (1973),
342-348), Georg Kreisel's "Bertrand Arthur William Russell, Earl
Russell: 1872-1970" (Biographical Memoirs of Fellows of the
Royal Society, 19 (1973), 583-620), Ray Monk's Bertrand
Russell: The Spirit of Solitude (London: J. Cape, 1996), and
John Slater's Bertrand Russell (Bristol: Thoemmes, 1994).
Russell's contributions to logic and to the philosophy and
foundations of mathematics include his discovery of Russell's paradox,
his defense of logicism (the view that mathematics is, in some
significant sense, reducible to formal logic), his introduction of the
theory of types, and his refining of the first-order predicate
calculus.
Russell discovered the paradox which bears his name in 1901, while
working on his Principles of Mathematics (1903). The
paradox arises in connection with the set of all sets which are not
members of themselves. Such a set, if it exists, will be a member of
itself if and only if it is not a member of itself. The paradox is
significant since, using classical logic, all sentences are entailed
by a contradiction. Russell's discovery thus prompted a large amount
of work in logic, set theory, and the philosophy and foundations of
mathematics.
Russell's own response to the paradox came with the introduction
of his theory of types in 1903. It was clear to Russell that some
restrictions needed to be placed upon the original comprehension
(or abstraction) axiom of naive set theory, the axiom which formalized
the intuition that any coherent condition may be used to determine
a set (or class). Russell's basic idea was that reference to sets
such as the set of all sets which are not members of themselves
could be avoided by arranging all sentences into a hierarchy (beginning
with sentences about individuals at the lowest level, sentences
about sets of individuals at the next lowest level, sentences
about sets of sets of individuals at the next lowest level, etc.).
Using a vicious circle principle similar to that adopted by the
mathematician Henri Poincaré, and his own so-called "no
class" theory of classes, Russell was able to explain why
the unrestricted comprehension axiom fails: propositional functions,
such as the function "x is a set", may not be
applied to themselves since self-application would involve a vicious
circle. Thus, on Russell's view, all objects for which a given
condition (or predicate) holds must be at the same level or of
the same "type". The theory of types itself admitted
of two versions, the "simple theory" and the "ramified
theory". Although first introduced in 1903, the theory finds
its mature expression in Russell's 1908 article "Mathematical
Logic as Based on the Theory of Types" and in the monumental
work he co-authored with
Alfred North Whitehead,
Principia Mathematica
(1910, 1912, 1913). The theory later came under attack for being
both too weak and too strong. For some, it was too weak since
it failed to resolve all of the known paradoxes. For others, it
was too strong since it disallowed many mathematical definitions
which, although consistent, violated the vicious circle principle.
Russell's response was to introduce the axiom of reducibility,
an axiom which lessened the vicious circle principle's scope of
application, but which many claimed was too ad hoc to be
justified philosophically.
Of equal significance during this same period was Russell's defense
of logicism, the theory that mathematics was in some important sense
reducible to logic. First defended in his Principles of
Mathematics, and later in greater detail in Principia
Mathematica, Russell's logicism consisted of two main theses.
The first is that all mathematical truths can be translated into
logical truths or, in other words, that the vocabulary of mathematics
constitutes a proper subset of that of logic. The second is that all
mathematical proofs can be recast as logical proofs or, in other
words, that the theorems of mathematics constitute a proper subset of
those of logic.
Like Gottlob Frege, Russell's basic idea for
defending logicism was that numbers may be identified with classes of
classes and that number-theoretic statements may be explained in terms
of quantifiers and identity. Thus the number 1 would be identified
with the class of all unit classes, the number 2 with the class of all
two-membered classes, and so on. Statements such as "There are
two books" would be recast as statements such as "There is a
book, x, and there is a book, y, and x is not
identical to y". It followed that number theoretic
operations could be explained in terms of set theoretic operations
such as intersection, union, and difference. In Principia
Mathematica, Whitehead and Russell were able to provide many
detailed derivations of major theorems in set theory, finite and
transfinite arithmetic, and elementary measure theory. A fourth volume
on geometry was planned but never completed.
Russell's most important writings relating to these topics include
not only Principles of Mathematics (1903),
"Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types" (1908),
and Principia Mathematica (1910, 1912, 1913), but also
his An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry (1897), and
Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy (1919).
In much the same way that Russell used logic in an attempt to clarify
issues in the foundations of mathematics, he also used it in an
attempt to clarify issues in philosophy. As one of the founders of
analytic philosophy, Russell made significant contributions to a wide
variety of areas, including metaphysics, epistemology, ethics and
political theory, as well as to the history of philosophy. Underlying
these various projects was Russell's long-standing aim of discovering
"how much we can be said to know and with what degree of
certainty or doubtfulness". More than this, though, Russell's
various contributions were also unified by views about the centrality
of logic and about the importance of scientific knowledge and its
underlying methodology. In fact, Russell often claimed that he had
more confidence in his philosophical/scientific methodology than in
any particular philosophical conclusion.
Russell's conception of philosophy arose in part from his idealist
origins. This is so even though he believed that his "one, true
revolution" in philosophy came with his break from idealism.
Russell saw that the idealist doctrine of internal relations led to a
series of contradictions regarding asymmetrical (and other) relations
necessary for mathematics. Thus, in 1898, he abandoned idealism and
his Kantian methodology in favour of a pluralistic realism. Emerging
"from the bath of German idealism" which he had encountered
as a student at Cambridge, Russell became famous for his defense of
the "new realism" and for his "new philosophy of
logic", emphasizing as it did the importance of modern logic for
philosophical analysis. The underlying themes of this
"revolution", such as his belief in pluralism, his emphasis
upon anti-psychologism, and the importance of science, remained
central to Russell's philosophy for the remainder of his life.
Russell's methodology consisted of the making and testing of
hypotheses through the weighing of evidence (hence Russell's comment
that he wished to emphasize the "scientific method" in
philosophy), together with a rigorous analysis of problematic
propositions using the machinery of first-order logic. It was
Russell's belief that by using the new logic of his day, philosophers
would be able to exhibit the underlying "logical form" of
natural language statements. A statement's logical form, in turn,
would help the philosopher resolve problems of reference associated
with the ambiguity and vagueness of natural language. Thus, just as we
distinguish three separate sense of "is" -- the is of
predication, the is of identity, and the is of
existence -- and exhibit these three senses by using three
separate logical notations -- Px, x = y, and
(
x) respectively -- we will
also discover other ontologically significant distinctions by being
aware of a sentence's correct logical form. On Russell's view, the
subject matter of philosophy is then distinguished from that of the
sciences only by the generality and the a prioricity of
philosophical statements, not by the underlying methodology of the
discipline. In philosophy, as in mathematics, Russell believed that it
was by applying logical machinery and insights that advances would be
made.
Russell's most famous example of his "analytic" methodology
concerns denoting phrases such as descriptions and proper names. In
his Principles of Mathematics, Russell had adopted the
view that every denoting phrase (for example, "Scott",
"blue", "the number two", "the golden
mountain") was assumed to refer to an existing entity. By the
time his landmark article, "On Denoting", appeared two years
later, in 1905, Russell had modified this extreme realism and had
instead become convinced that denoting phrases need not possess a
theoretical unity. While logically proper names (words such as
"this" or "that" which refer to sensations of
which an agent is immediately aware) do have referents associated with
them, descriptive phrases (such as "the smallest number less than
e") should be viewed a collection of quantifiers (such as
"all" and "some") and propositional functions
(such as "x is a number"). As such, they are not to
be viewed as referring terms but, rather, as "incomplete
symbols". In other words, they should be viewed as symbols which
take on meaning within appropriate contexts, but which are meaningless
in isolation.
Thus, in the sentence
(1) The present King of France is bald,
the definite description "The present King of France" plays
a role quite different from that of a proper name such as
"Scott" in the sentence
(2) Scott is bald.
Letting "K" abbreviate the predicate "is
a present King of France" and "B" abbreviate
the predicate "is bald", Russell assigns sentence (1)
the logical form
(1' ) There is an x such that (i) Kx, (ii) for any
y, if Ky then y = x, and (iii) Bx.
In the notation of the predicate calculus, the logical form of
(1') is
In contrast, he assigns sentence (2) the logical form
(2' ) Bs.
This distinction between various logical forms allows Russell
to explain three important puzzles. The first concerns the operation
of the Law of Excluded Middle and how it relates to denoting terms.
According to one reading of the Law of Excluded Middle, it must
be the case that either "The present King of France is bald"
is true or "The present King of France is not bald"
is true. But if so, both sentences appear to entail the existence
of a present King of France, clearly an undesirable result. Russell's
analysis shows how this conclusion can be avoided. By appealing
to analysis (1' ), it follows that there is a way to deny (1)
without being committed to the existence of a present King of
France.
The second puzzle concerns the Law of Identity as it operates in
(so-called) opaque contexts. Even though "Scott is the author of
Waverley" is true, it does not follow that the two
referring terms "Scott" and "the author of
Waverley" are interchangeable in all contexts. Thus
although "George wanted to know whether Scott was the the author
of Waverley" is true, "George wanted to know
whether Scott was Scott" is false. Russell's distinction between
the logical forms associated with the use of proper names and definite
descriptions shows why this may be so.
The third puzzle relates to true negative existential claims, such as
the claim that "The golden mountain does not exist". Here,
once again, by treating definite descriptions as having a logical form
distinct from that of proper names, Russell is able to give an account
of how a speaker may be committed to the truth of a negative
existential without also being committed to the belief that the
subject term has reference.
Russell's emphasis upon logical analysis also had consequences for
his metaphysics. In response to the traditional problem of the
external world which, it is claimed, can be known only by inference,
Russell developed his famous 1910 distinction between "knowledge
by acquaintance and knowledge by description". He then went on,
in his 1918 lectures on logical atomism, to argue that the world
itself consists of a complex of logical atoms (such as "little
patches of colour") and their properties. Together they form the
atomic facts which in turn are combined to form logically complex
objects. What we normally take to be inferred entities (for example,
enduring physical objects) are then thought of as being "logical
constructions" formed from the immediately given entities of
sensation, viz., "sensibilia". It is only these latter
entities which are known non-inferentially and with
certainty. According to Russell, the philosopher's job is then to
discover a logically ideal language which will exhibit the true nature
of the world in such a way that the speaker will not be misled by the
casual surface structure of natural language. Just as atomic facts
(the association of universals with an appropriate number of
individuals) may be combined into molecular facts in the world itself,
such a language would allow for the description of such combinations
using logical connectives such as "and" and
"or". In addition to atomic and molecular facts, Russell
also held that general facts (facts about "all" of
something) were needed to complete the picture of the world.
Famously, he vacillated on whether negative facts were also required.
Russell's most important writings relating to these topics include
not only "On Denoting" (1905), but also his "Knowledge
by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description" (1910), "The
Philosophy of Logical Atomism" (1918, 1919), "Logical
Atomism" (1924), The Analysis of Mind (1921), and
The Analysis of Matter (1927).
Russell's social influence stems from three main sources: his
long-standing social activism, his many writings on the social and
political issues of his day, and his popularizations of technical
writings in philosophy and the natural sciences.
Among Russell's many popularizations are his two best selling works,
The Problems of Philosophy (1912) and A History of
Western Philosophy (1945). Both of these books, as well as his
numerous but less famous books popularizing science, have done much to
educate and inform generations of general readers. Naturally enough,
Russell saw a link between education, in this broad sense, and social
progress. In Russell's words, "The desire to understand the world
and the desire to reform it are the two great engines of
progress." At the same time, Russell is also famous for
suggesting that a widespread reliance upon evidence, rather than upon
superstition, would have enormous social consequences: "I wish to
propose for the reader's favourable consideration," says Russell,
"a doctrine which may, I fear, appear wildly paradoxical and
subversive. The doctrine in question is this: that it is undesirable
to believe a proposition when there is no ground whatever for
supposing it true."
Still, Russell is best known in many circles as a result of his
campaigns against the proliferation of nuclear weapons and against
western involvement in the Vietnam War during the 1950s and 1960s.
However, Russell's social activism stretches back at least as far as
1910, when he published his Anti-Suffragist Anxieties,
and to 1916, when he was convicted and fined in connection with
anti-war protests during World War I. Following his conviction, he was
also dismissed from his post at Trinity College, Cambridge. Two years
later, he was convicted a second time. The result was six months in
prison. Russell also ran unsuccessfully for Parliament (in 1907, 1922,
and 1923) and, together with his second wife, founded and operated an
experimental school during the late 1920s and early 1930s.
Although he became the third Earl Russell upon the death of his
brother in 1931, Russell's radicalism continued to make him a
controversial figure well through middle-age. While teaching in the
United States in the late 1930s, he was offered a teaching appointment
at City College, New York. The appointment was revoked following a
large number of public protests and a 1940 judicial decision which
found him morally unfit to teach at the College.
In 1954 he delivered his famous "Man's Peril" broadcast on
the BBC, condemning the Bikini H-bomb tests. A year later, together
with Albert Einstein, he released the Russell-Einstein Manifesto
calling for the curtailment of nuclear weapons. In 1957 he was a prime
organizer of the first Pugwash Conference, which brought together a
large number of scientists concerned about the nuclear issue. He
became the founding president of the Campaign for Nuclear Disarmament
in 1958 and was once again imprisoned in connection with anti-nuclear
protests in 1961. The media coverage surrounding his conviction only
served to enhance Russell's reputation and to further inspire many of
the idealistic youth who were sympathetic to his anti-war and
anti-nuclear protests.
During these controversial years Russell also wrote many of the books
which brought him to the attention of popular audiences. These
included his Principles of Social Reconstruction (1916),
A Free Man's Worship (1923), On Education
(1926), Why I Am Not a Christian (1927), Marriage
and Morals (1929), The Conquest of Happiness
(1930), The Scientific Outlook (1931), and Power: A
New Social Analysis (1938).
Upon being awarded the Nobel Prize for Literature in 1950, Russell
took the opportunity to emphasize, once again, themes related to his
social activism, using his acceptance speech to warn of the dangers of
nuclear war.
Russell wrote approximately 55 books. In addition, hundreds of his
articles, both in philosophy and on other topics, have been published
in over 40 anthologies devoted to his writings. The most complete
listing of his publications is to be found in A Bibliography of
Bertrand Russell (3 vols, London: Routledge, 1994), by Kenneth
Blackwell and Harry Ruja. A less detailed, but still comprehensive,
list appears in Paul Arthur Schilpp's The Philosophy of Bertrand
Russell (3rd ed., New York: Harper and Row, 1963).
- (1905) "On Denoting", Mind, 14, 479-493.
Repr. in Russell, Bertrand, Essays in Analysis, London:
Allen & Unwin, 1973, 103-119.
- (1908) "Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of
Types", American Journal of Mathematics, 30,
222-262. Repr. in Russell, Bertrand, Logic and Knowledge,
London: Allen & Unwin, 1956, 59-102, and in van Heijenoort, Jean,
From Frege to Gödel, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1967, 152-182.
- (1910) "Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by
Description", Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, 11, 108-128. Repr. in Russell, Bertrand,
Mysticism and Logic, London: Allen & Unwin, 1963,
152-167.
- (1912) "On the Relations of Universals and
Particulars", Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, 12, 1-24. Repr. in Russell, Bertrand, Logic and
Knowledge, London: Allen & Unwin, 1956, 105-124.
- (1918, 1919) "The Philosophy of Logical Atomism",
Monist, 28, 495-527; 29, 32-63, 190-222, 345-380.
Repr. in Russell, Bertrand, Logic and Knowledge, London:
Allen & Unwin, 1956, 177-281.
- (1924) "Logical Atomism", in Muirhead, J.H.,
Contemporary British Philosophers, London: Allen &
Unwin, 1924, 356-383. Repr. in Russell, Bertrand, Logic and
Knowledge, London: Allen & Unwin, 1956, 323-343.
- (1896) German Social Democracy, London: Longmans,
Green.
- (1897) An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry,
Cambridge: At the University Press.
- (1900) A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of
Leibniz, Cambridge: At the University Press.
- (1903) The Principles of Mathematics, Cambridge: At
the University Press.
- (1910, 1912, 1913) (with Alfred North Whitehead) Principia
Mathematica, 3 vols, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Second edition, 1925 (Vol. 1), 1927 (Vols 2, 3). Abridged as
Principia Mathematica to *56, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1962.
- (1912) The Problems of Philosophy, London: Williams
and Norgate; New York: Henry Holt and Company.
- (1914) Our Knowledge of the External World, Chicago
and London: The Open Court Publishing Company.
- (1916) Principles of Social Reconstruction, London:
George Allen & Unwin. Repr. as Why Men Fight, New
York: The Century Company, 1917.
- (1917) Political Ideals, New York: The Century
Company.
- (1919) Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy,
London: George Allen & Unwin; New York: The Macmillan Company.
- (1921) The Analysis of Mind, London: George Allen
& Unwin; New York: The Macmillan Company.
- (1923) A Free Man's Worship, Portland, Maine: Thomas
Bird Mosher. Repr. as What Can A Free Man Worship?,
Girard, Kansas: Haldeman-Julius Publications, 1927.
- (1926) On Education, Especially in Early Childhood,
London: George Allen & Unwin. Repr. as Education and the
Good Life, New York: Boni & Liveright, 1926. Abridged as
Education of Character, New York: Philosophical Library,
1961.
- (1927) The Analysis of Matter, London: Kegan Paul,
Trench, Trubner; New York: Harcourt, Brace.
- (1927) An Outline of Philosophy, London: George
Allen & Unwin. Repr. as Philosophy, New York:
W.W. Norton, 1927.
- (1927) Why I Am Not a Christian, London: Watts, New
York: The Truth Seeker Company.
- (1929) Marriage and Morals, London: George Allen
& Unwin; New York: Horace Liveright.
- (1930) The Conquest of Happiness, London: George
Allen & Unwin; New York: Horace Liveright.
- (1931) The Scientific Outlook, London: George Allen
& Unwin; New York: W.W. Norton.
- (1938) Power: A New Social Analysis, London: George
Allen & Unwin; New York: W.W. Norton.
- (1940) An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, London:
George Allen & Unwin; New York: W.W. Norton.
- (1945) A History of Western Philosophy, New York:
Simon and Schuster; London: George Allen & Unwin, 1946.
- (1948) Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits,
London: George Allen & Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
- (1949) Authority and the Individual, London: George
Allen & Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
- (1949) The Philosophy of Logical Atomism,
Minneapolis, Minnesota: Department of Philosophy, University of
Minnesota. Repr. as Russell's Logical Atomism, Oxford:
Fontana/Collins, 1972.
- (1954) Human Society in Ethics and Politics, London:
George Allen & Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
- (1959) My Philosophical Development, London: George
Allen & Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
- (1967, 1968, 1969) The Autobiography of Bertrand
Russell, 3 vols, London: George Allen & Unwin; Boston and
Toronto: Little Brown and Company (Vols 1 and 2), New York: Simon and
Schuster (Vol. 3).
- (1910) Philosophical Essays, London: Longmans,
Green.
- (1918) Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays, London
and New York: Longmans, Green. Repr. as A Free Man's Worship and
Other Essays, London: Unwin Paperbacks, 1976.
- (1928) Sceptical Essays, London: George Allen &
Unwin; New York: W.W. Norton.
- (1935) In Praise of Idleness, London: George Allen
& Unwin; New York: W.W. Norton.
- (1950) Unpopular Essays, London: George Allen &
Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
- (1956) Logic and Knowledge: Essays, 1901-1950,
London: George Allen & Unwin; New York: The Macmillan Company.
- (1956) Portraits From Memory and Other Essays,
London: George Allen & Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
- (1957) Why I am Not a Christian and Other Essays on
Religion and Related Subjects, London: George Allen &
Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
- (1961) The Basic Writings of Bertrand Russell,
1903-1959, London: George Allen & Unwin; New York: Simon
and Schuster.
- (1969) Dear Bertrand Russell, London: George Allen
& Unwin; Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
- (1973) Essays in Analysis, London: George Allen
& Unwin.
- (1992) The Selected Letters of Bertrand Russell,
London: Penguin Press.
The Bertrand Russell Editorial Project is currently in the process
of publishing Russell's Collected Papers. When complete,
these volumes will bring together all of Russell's writings, excluding
his previously published monographs and his correspondence.
In Print
- Vol. 1: Cambridge Essays, 1888-99, London,
Boston, Sydney: George Allen & Unwin, 1983.
- Vol. 2: Philosophical Papers, 1896-99, London and
New York: Routledge, 1990.
- Vol. 3: Toward the Principles of Mathematics, London
and New York: Routledge, 1993.
- Vol. 4: Foundations of Logic, 1903-05, London and
New York: Routledge, 1994.
- Vol. 6: Logical and Philosophical Papers, 1909-13,
London and New York: Routledge, 1992.
- Vol. 7: Theory of Knowledge: The 1913 Manuscript,
London, Boston, Sydney: George Allen & Unwin, 1984.
- Vol. 8: The Philosophy of Logical Atomism and Other Essays,
1914-19, London: George Allen & Unwin, 1986.
- Vol. 9: Essays on Language, Mind and Matter,
1919-26, London: Unwin Hyman, 1988.
- Vol. 10: Philosophical Papers, 1927-43, London and
New York: Routledge.
- Vol. 11: Philosophical Papers, 1944-65, London and
New York: Routledge.
- Vol. 12: Contemplation and Action, 1902-14, London,
Boston, Sydney: George Allen & Unwin, 1985.
- Vol. 13: Prophecy and Dissent, 1914-16, London:
Unwin Hyman, 1988.
- Vol. 14: Pacifism and Revolution, 1916-18, London
and New York: Routledge, 1995.
Planned and Forthcoming
- Vol. 5: Philosophical Papers, 1906-08.
- Vol. 15: Uncertain Roads to Freedom: Russia and China,
1919-1922.
- Vol. 16: Labour and Internationalism, 1922-24.
- Vol. 17: Behaviourism and Education, 1925-28.
- Vol. 18: Science, Sex and Society, 1929-32.
- Vol. 19: Fascism and Other Depression Legacies,
1933-36.
- Vol. 20: The Man Who Stuck Pins in His Wife, and Other
Essays, 1936-39.
- Vol. 21: The Problems of Democracy, 1940-44.
- Vol. 22: Civilization and the Bomb, 1944-49.
- Vol. 23: Respectability At Last, 1949-53.
- Vol. 24: Man's Peril, 1954-57.
- Vol. 25: The Campaign for Nuclear Disarmament,
1958-60.
- Vol. 26: A New Plan for Peace and Other Essays,
1960-64.
- Vol. 27: The Vietnam Campaign, 1965-70.
- Vol. 28: Newly Discovered Papers.
- Vol. 29: Newly Discovered Papers.
- Vol. 30: Index.
No comprehensive bibliography of the secondary literature surrounding
Russell exists to date. A selected list (of approximately 1,000
entires) is to appear in A.D. Irvine (ed.), Bertrand Russell:
Critical Assessments (4 vols, London: Routledge, forthcoming).
- Broad, C.D. (1973) "Bertrand Russell, as Philosopher",
Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society, 5, 328-341.
- Carnap, Rudolf (1931) "The Logicist Foundations of
Mathematics", Erkenntnis, 2, 91-105. Repr. in
Benacerraf, Paul, and Hilary Putnam (eds), Philosophy of
Mathematics, 2nd ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1983, 41-52; in Klemke, E.D. (ed.), Essays on Bertrand
Russell, Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1970, 341-354;
and in Pears, David F. (ed.), Bertrand Russell: A Collection of
Critical Essays, Garden City, New York: Anchor Books, 1972,
175-191.
- Church, Alonzo (1976) "Comparison of Russell's Resolution of
the Semantical Antinomies With That of Tarski", Journal of
Symbolic Logic, 41, 747-760.
- Gandy, R.O. (1973) "Bertrand Russell, as
Mathematician", Bulletin of the London Mathematical
Society, 5, 342-348.
- Gödel, Kurt (1944) "Russell's Mathematical Logic",
in Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.), The Philosophy of Bertrand
Russell, 3rd ed., New York: Tudor, 1951, 123-153. Repr. in
Benacerraf, Paul, and Hilary Putnam (eds), Philosophy of
Mathematics, 2nd ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1983, 447-469; and in Pears, David F. (ed.) (1972) Bertrand
Russell: A Collection of Critical Essays, Garden City, New
York: Anchor Books, 192-226.
- Hylton, Peter W. (1990) "Logic in Russell's Logicism",
in Bell, David, and Neil Cooper (eds), The Analytic Tradition:
Philosophical Quarterly Monographs, Vol. 1, Cambridge:
Blackwell, 137-172.
- Irvine, A.D. (1989) "Epistemic Logicism and Russell's
Regressive Method", Philosophical Studies, 55,
303-327.
- Kaplan, David (1970) "What is Russell's Theory of
Descriptions?", in Yourgrau, Wolfgang, and Allen D. Breck, (eds),
Physics, Logic, and History, New York: Plenum,
277-288. Repr. in Pears, David F. (ed.), Bertrand Russell: A
Collection of Critical Essays, Garden City, New York: Anchor
Books, 1972, 227-244.
- Lycan, William (1981) "Logical Atomism and Ontological
Atoms", Synthese, 46, 207-229.
- Monro, D.H. (1960) "Russell's Moral Theories",
Philosophy, 35, 30-50. Repr. in Pears, David F. (ed.),
Bertrand Russell: A Collection of Critical Essays, Garden
City, New York: Anchor Books, 1972, 325-355.
- Putnam, Hilary (1967) "The Thesis that Mathematics is
Logic", in Schoenman, Ralph (ed.), Bertrand Russell:
Philosopher of the Century, London: Allen & Unwin,
273-303. Repr. in Putnam, Hilary, Mathematics, Matter and
Method, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975, 12-42.
- Quine, W.V. (1938) "On the Theory of Types",
Journal of Symbolic Logic, 3, 125-139.
- Ramsey, F.P. (1926) "Mathematical Logic",
Mathematical Gazette, 13, 185-194. Repr. in Ramsey, Frank
Plumpton, The Foundations of Mathematics, London: Kegan
Paul, Trench, Trubner, 1931, 62-81; in Ramsey, Frank Plumpton,
Foundations, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978,
213-232; and in Ramsey, Frank Plumpton, Philosophical
Papers, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990, 225-244.]
- Schultz, Bart (1992) "Bertrand Russell in Ethics and
Politics", Ethics, 102, 594-634.
- Strawson, Peter F. (1950) "On Referring",
Mind, 59, 320-344. Repr. in Flew, Anthony (ed.),
Essays in Conceptual Analysis, London: Macmillan, 1960,
21-52, and in Klemke, E.D. (ed.), Essays on Bertrand
Russell, Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1970, 147-172.
- Weitz, Morris (1944) "Analysis and the Unity of Russell's
Philosophy", in Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.), The Philosophy
of Bertrand Russell, 3rd ed., New York: Tudor, 1951, 55-121.
- Blackwell, Kenneth (1985) The Spinozistic Ethics of
Bertrand Russell, London: George Allen & Unwin.
- Blackwell, Kenneth, and Harry Ruja (1994) A Bibliography of
Bertrand Russell, 3 vols, London: Routledge.
- Chomsky, Noam (1971) Problems of Knowledge and Freedom: The
Russell Lectures, New York: Vintage.
- Clark, Ronald William (1975) The Life of Bertrand
Russell, London: J. Cape.
- Clark, Ronald William (1981) Bertrand Russell and His
World, London: Thames and Hudson.
- Dewey, John, and Horace M. Kallen (eds) (1941) The Bertrand
Russell Case, New York: Viking.
- Eames, Elizabeth R. (1969) Bertrand Russell's Theory of
Knowledge, London: George Allen & Unwin.
- Eames, Elizabeth R. (1989) Bertrand Russell's Dialogue with
his Contemporaries, Carbondale: Southern Illinois University
Press.
- Feinberg, Barry, and Ronald Kasrils (eds) (1969) Dear
Bertrand Russell, London: George Allen & Unwin.
- Feinberg, Barry, and Ronald Kasrils (1973, 1983) Bertrand
Russell's America, 2 vols, London: George Allen & Unwin.
- Grattan-Guinness, I. (1977) Dear Russell, Dear Jourdain: A
Commentary on Russell's Logic, Based on His Correspondence with Philip
Jourdain, New York: Columbia University Press.
- Griffin, Nicholas (1991) Russell's Idealist
Apprenticeship, Oxford: Clarendon.
- Hager, Paul J. (1994) Continuity and Change in the
Development of Russell's Philosophy, Dordrecht: Nijhoff.
- Hardy, Godfrey H. (1942) Bertrand Russell and
Trinity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970.
- Hylton, Peter W. (1990) Russell, Idealism, and the
Emergence of Analytic Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon.
- Irvine, A.D. (ed.) (1998) Bertrand Russell: Critical
Assessments, 4 vols, London: Routledge.
- Irvine, A.D., and G.A. Wedeking (eds) (1993) Russell and
Analytic Philosophy, Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
- Jager, Ronald (1972) The Development of Bertrand Russell's
Philosophy, London: George Allen & Unwin.
- Klemke, E.D. (ed.) (1970) Essays on Bertrand
Russell, Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
- Monk, Ray (1996) Bertrand Russell: The Spirit of
Solitude, London: J. Cape.
- Monk, Ray, and Anthony Palmer (eds) (1996) Bertrand Russell
and the Origins of Analytic Philosophy, Bristol: Thoemmes
Press.
- Moorehead, Caroline (1992) Bertrand Russell, New
York: Viking.
- Nakhnikian, George (ed.) (1974) Bertrand Russell's
Philosophy, London: Duckworth.
- Park, Joe (1963) Bertrand Russell on Education,
Columbus: Ohio State University Press.
- Patterson, Wayne (1993) Bertrand Russell's Philosophy of
Logical Atomism, New York: Lang.
- Pears, David F. (1967) Bertrand Russell and the British
Tradition in Philosophy, London: Collins.
- Pears, David F. (ed.) (1972) Bertrand Russell: A Collection
of Critical Essays, New York: Doubleday.
- Roberts, George W. (ed.) (1979) Bertrand Russell Memorial
Volume, London: Allen & Unwin.
- Rodriguez-Consuegra, Francisco A. (1991) The Mathematical
Philosophy of Bertrand Russell: Origins and Development, Basel:
Birkhauser Verlag.
- Ryan, Alan (1988) Bertrand Russell: A Political
Life, New York: Hill and Wang.
- Savage, C. Wade, and C. Anthony Anderson (eds) (1989)
Rereading Russell: Essays on Bertrand Russell's Metaphysics and
Epistemology, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
- Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.) (1944) The Philosophy of
Bertrand Russell, Chicago: Northwestern University; 3rd ed.,
New York: Harper and Row, 1963.
- Schoenman, Ralph (ed.) (1967) Bertrand Russell: Philosopher
of the Century, London: Allen & Unwin.
- Slater, John G. (1994) Bertrand Russell, Bristol:
Thoemmes.
- Tait, Katharine (1975) My Father Bertrand Russell,
New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
- Vellacott, Jo (1980) Bertrand Russell and the Pacifists in
the First World War, Brighton, Sussex: Harvester Press.
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1921) Logisch-philosophische
Abhandlung. Trans. as Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus, London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner,
1922.
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1956) Remarks on the Foundations of
Mathematics, Oxford: Blackwell.
- Wood, Alan (1957) Bertrand Russell: The Passionate
Sceptic, London: Allen & Unwin.
analytic philosophy |
descriptions |
Frege, Gottlob |
Gödel, Kurt |
knowledge by acquaintance vs. knowledge by description |
logic |
logical atomism |
logical construction |
logicism |
Moore, G. E. |
mathematics, philosophy of |
Principia Mathematica |
propositional function |
Russell's paradox |
type theory |
Whitehead, Alfred North |
Wittgenstein, Ludwig
Copyright © 1995, 1998
by
A. D. Irvine
irvine@unixg.ubc.ca
A |
B |
C |
D |
E |
F |
G |
H |
I |
J |
K |
L |
M |
N |
O |
P |
Q |
R |
S |
T |
U |
V |
W |
X |
Y |
Z
Table of Contents
First published: December 7, 1995
Content last modified: December 12, 1998