Thought Experiments
Thought experiments are devices of the imagination used to
investigate nature. We need only list a few of the well-known
thought experiments to be reminded of their enormous influence and
importance in the sciences: Newton's bucket, Maxwell's
demon, Einstein's elevator, Heisenberg's gamma-ray
microscope, Schrödinger's cat. The 17th century saw some
of its most brilliant practitioners in Galileo, Descartes, Newton,
and Leibniz. And in our own time, the creation of quantum mechanics
and relativity are almost unthinkable without the crucial role played
by thought experiments. Galileo and Einstein were, arguably, the most
impressive thought experimenters, but they were by no means the
first. Thought experiments existed throughout the middle ages, and
can be found in antiquity, too.
One of the most beautiful early examples (Lucretius, De Rerum
Natura) attempts to show that space is infinite: If there is a
boundary to the universe, we can toss a spear at it. If the spear
flies through, it isn't a boundary after all; if the spear
bounces back, then there must be something beyond the supposed edge
of space, a cosmic wall which is itself in space that stopped the
spear. Either way, there is no edge of the universe; space is
infinite. This example nicely illustrates many of the common
features of thought experiments: We visualize some situation; we
carry out an operation; we see what happens. It also illustrates
their fallibility. (In this case we've learned how to
conceptualize space so that it is both finite and unbounded.)
Often a real experiment that is the analogue of a thought experiment
is impossible for physical, technological, or just plain practical
reasons; but this needn't be a defining condition of thought
experiments. The main point is that we seem able to get a grip on
nature just by thinking, and therein lies the great interest for
philosophy. How is it possible to learn (apparently) new things
about nature without new empirical data?
Ernst Mach (who seems to have coined the expression
Gedankenexperiment) developed an interesting empiricist view
in his classic, The Science of Mechanics. We possess, he
says, a great store of "instinctive knowledge" picked up from
experience. This needn't be articulated at all, but comes to
the fore when we consider certain situations. One of his favourite
examples is due to Simon Stevin. When a chain is draped over a
double frictionless plane, as in Fig. 1a, how will it move? Add some
links as in Fig. 1b.
![](figure1a.gif) |
![](figure1b.gif) |
Figure 1a |
Figure 1b |
Now it is obvious. The initial setup must have been in static
equilibrium. Otherwise, we would have a perpetual motion machine;
and according to our experience-based "instinctive knowledge", says
Mach, this is impossible.
Thomas Kuhn's "A Function for Thought Experiments" employs many
of the concepts (but not the terminology) of his well-known Structure
of Scientific Revolutions. On his view a well-conceived thought
experiment can bring on a crisis or at least create an anomaly in the
reigning theory and so contribute to paradigm change. So thought
experiments can teach us something new about the world, even though
we have no new data, by helping us to reconceptualize the world in a
better way.
Recent years have seen a sudden growth of interest in thought
experiments. The views of Brown (1991) and Norton (1991, 1996)
represent the extremes of platonic rationalism and classic
empiricism, respectively. Norton claims that any thought experiment
is really a (possibly disguised) argument; it starts with premisses
grounded in experience and follows deductive or inductive rules of
inference in arriving at its conclusion. The picturesque features of
any thought experiment which give it an experimental flavour might be
psychologically helpful, but are strictly redundant. Thus, says
Norton, we never go beyond the empirical premisses in a way to which
any empiricist would object. (For criticisms see Brown (1991, 1993)
and for a defense see Norton (1996).)
By contrast, Brown holds that in a few special cases we do go
well beyond the old data to acquire a priori knowledge of
nature. Galileo showed that all bodies fall at the same speed with a
brilliant thought experiment that started by destroying the then
reigning Aristotelian account. The latter holds that heavy bodies
fall faster than light ones (H > L). But consider (Fig. 2), in which
a heavy canon ball (H) and light musket ball (L) are attached
together to form a compound object (H+L); the latter must fall faster
than the cannon ball alone. Yet the compound object must also fall
slower, since the light part will act as a drag on the heavy part.
Now we have a contradiction. (H+L > H and H > H+L) That's the
end of Aristotle's theory; but there is a bonus, since the right
account is now obvious: they all fall at the same speed (H = L =
H+L).
![](figure2.gif)
Figure 2
This is said to be a priori (though still fallible) knowledge
of nature since there are no new data involved, nor is the conclusion
derived from old data, nor is it some sort of logical truth. This
account of thought experiments is further developed by linking the a
priori epistemology to a recent account of laws of nature which holds
that laws are relations between objectively existing abstract
entities. It is thus a rather platonistic view, not unlike
platonistic accounts of mathematics such as that urged by Gödel.
(For details see Brown 1991.)
The two views just sketched might occupy the opposite ends of a
spectrum of positions on thought experiments. Some of the promising
new alternative views include those of Sorensen (somewhat in the
spirit of Mach) who holds that thought experiments are a "limiting
case" of ordinary experiments; they can achieve their aim, he says,
without being executed. (Sorensen's book is also valuable for
its extensive discussion of thought experiments in philosophy of
mind, ethics, and other areas of philosophy, as well as the
sciences.) Other promising views include those of Gooding (who
stresses the similar procedural nature of thought experiments and
real experiments), Miscevic and Nersessian (each of whom tie thought
experiments to "mental models"), and several of the accounts in
Horowitz and Massey (1991). More recent excellent discussions
include: Arthur (1999), Gendler (1998), Haggqvist (1996), Humphreys
(1994), Genz (1999), McAllister (1996). The literature on thought
experiments continues to grow rapidly.
- Arthur, R. (1999) "On Thought Experiments as A Priori Science,"
International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 13, 3,
215-229
- Brown, J.R. (1991) Laboratory of the Mind: Thought Experiments
in the Natural Sciences, London: Routledge
- Brown, J.R. (1993) "Why Empiricism Won't Work", in D. Hull,
M. Forbes, and K. Okruhlik (eds.) PSA 1992, vol. 2, East
Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association
- Gendler, T.S.(1998) "Galileo and the Indispensibility of
Scientific Thought Experiment", The British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science, Vol.49, No.3, (September), 397-424
- Genz, H. (1999) Gedanken-experimente, Wiley-VCH, Weinheim,
(in German)
- Gooding, D. (1993) "What is Experimental About Thought
Experiments?" in D. Hull, M. Forbes, and K. Okruhlik (eds.) PSA
1992, vol. 2, East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association
- Hacking, I. (1993) "Do Thought Experiments have a Life of Their
Own?" in D. Hull, M. Forbes, and K. Okruhlik (eds.) PSA 1992,
vol. 2, East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association
- Haggqvist, S. (1996) Thought Experiments in Philosophy,
(Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell International)
- Horowitz, T. and G. Massey (eds.) (1991) Thought Experiments in
Science and Philosophy, Savage MD: Rowman and Littlefield
- Humphries, P. (1994) "Seven Theses on Thought Experiments", in
Earman et al., (eds) Philosophical Problems of the
Internal and External World, Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh
Press
- Kuhn, T. (1964) "A Function for Thought Experiments", reprinted in
Kuhn, The Essential Tension, Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1977
- Mach, E. (1960) The Science of Mechanics, (Trans by
J. McCormack), sixth edition, LaSalle Illinois: Open Court
- Mach, E. (1976) "On Thought Experiments", in Knowledge and
Error, Dordrecht: Reidel
- McAllister, J. (1996) "The Evidential Significance of Thought
Experiments in Science", Studies in History and Philosophy of
Science, vol 27, no. 2, 233-250
- Miscevic , N. (1992) "Mental Models and Thought Experiments",
International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 6,
No. 3, pp. 215-226
- Nersessian, N. (1993) "In the Theoretician's Laboratory:
Thought Experimenting as Mental Modeling" in D. Hull, M. Forbes, and
K. Okruhlik (eds.) PSA 1992, vol. 2, East Lansing, MI:
Philosophy of Science Association
- Norton, J. (1991) "Thought Experiments in Einstein's Work", in
Horowitz and Massey (1991)
- Norton, J. (1996) "Are Thought Experiments Just What You Always
Thought?" Canadian Journal of Philosophy
- Sorensen, R. (1992) Thought Experiments, Oxford: Oxford
University Press
[Please contact the author with suggestions.]
Descartes, René |
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm |
Mach, Ernst |
science, philosophy of
Copyright © 1996, 2002
A |
B |
C |
D |
E |
F |
G |
H |
I |
J |
K |
L |
M |
N |
O |
P |
Q |
R |
S |
T |
U |
V |
W |
X |
Y |
Z
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy