Rights
Rights are entitlements (not) to perform certain actions or be in certain states, or entitlements that others (not) perform certain actions or be in certain states.
Rights dominate most modern understandings of what actions are proper and which institutions are just. Rights structure the forms of our governments, the contents of our laws, and the shape of morality as we perceive it. To accept a set of rights is to approve a distribution of freedom and authority, and so to endorse a certain view of what may, must, and must not be done.
This entry begins by describing the nature of rights: their classification, their composition, and their function. We then take a brief look at the history of the language of rights, and various relationships between rights and reasons. The major contemporary philosophical approaches to the justification of rights are compared, and the entry concludes by surveying criticisms of rights and "rights talk." The focus throughout is on theoretical questions concerning rights in general instead of on any particular controversial right.
- 1. Categories of Rights
- 2. The Analysis of Rights
- 3. The History of the Language of Rights
- 4. Rights and Freedom
- 5. Rights and Reasons
- 6. Two Approaches to the Justification of Rights
- 7. Critiques of Rights
- Bibliography
- Other Internet Resources
- Related Entries
1. Categories of Rights
A right to life, a right to choose; a right to vote, to work, to strike; a right to one phone call, to dissolve parliament, to operate a forklift, to asylum, to equal treatment before the law, to feel proud of what one has done; a right to exist, to sentence an offender to death, to launch a nuclear first strike, to carry a concealed weapon, to a distinct genetic identity; a right to believe one's own eyes, to pronounce the couple husband and wife, to be left alone, to go to hell in one's own way.
We encounter assertions of rights as we encounter sounds: persistently and in great variety. Making sense of this profusion of assertions requires that we class rights together by common attributes. Rights-assertions can be categorized, for example, according to:
Who is alleged to have the right: Children's rights, animal rights, workers' rights, states' rights, the rights of peoples.
What actions or states or objects the asserted right pertains to: Rights of free expression, to pass judgment; rights of privacy, to remain silent; property rights, bodily rights.
Why the rightholder (allegedly) has the right: Moral rights spring from moral reasons, legal rights derive from the laws of the society, customary rights are aspects of local customs.
How the asserted right can be affected by the rightholder's actions: The inalienable right to life, the forfeitable right to liberty, and the waivable right that a promise be kept.
Many of these categories have sub-categories. For instance, natural rights are the sub-class of moral rights that humans have because of their nature. Or again, the rights of political speech are a subclass of the rights of free expression.
The study of particular rights is primarily an investigation into how such categories and sub-categories overlap. There has been much discussion, for example, of whether human rights are natural rights, whether the right to privacy is a legal right, and whether the legal right to life is a forfeitable right.
2. The Analysis of Rights
Categorization sorts the profusion of rights assertions. To understand what the assertion of a particular right means, we need to understand more precisely how rights are constructed and what they do.
An analysis of rights has two parts: a description of the internal structure of rights (their form), and a description of what rights do for those who hold them (their function). The analytical system for describing the form of rights is widely accepted, although there are scholarly quarrels about its details. Which theory gives the best account of the function of rights has been much more contentious; we turn to that debate in section 3.
2.1 The Form of Rights: The Hohfeldian Analytical System
Most common rights, such as the right to free expression or the right of private property, have a complex internal structure. Such rights are ordered arrangements of several basic components—much in the same way that most molecules are ordered arrangements of several chemical elements. The four basic components of rights are known as "the Hohfeldian incidents" after Wesley Hohfeld (1879-1918), the American legal theorist who discovered them. These four basic "elements" are the privilege, the claim, the power, and the immunity. Each of these Hohfeldian incidents has a distinctive logical form; and each incident can be a right by itself, even when it is not a part of a complex "molecule."
2.1.1 Privileges (or Liberties)
You have a right to pick up a coin that you find by the side of the road. This right is a privilege:
A has a privilege to φ if and only if A has no duty not to φ.
To say that you have a right to pick up the coin is to say that you have no duty not to pick it up. You will not be violating any duty not to pick up the money should you decide to do so. Similarly your right to sit in an empty seat in the cinema, and your right to paint your bedroom blue, are also privileges. Privilege-rights mark out what their bearer has no duty not to do.
(Some writers on rights have preferred to speak of "liberties" instead of "privileges" (e.g., Steiner 1994, 59-60); others have given different definitions to these two terms (e.g., Thomson 1990, 53-55). To avoid confusion, this entry will always use "privilege" and never "liberty" to refer to the incident defined above.)
2.1.2 Claims
A contract between employer and employee confers on the employee a right to be paid his wages. This right is a claim:
A has a claim that B φ if and only if B has a duty to A to φ.
The employee has a claim that the employer pays him his wages, which means that the employer has a duty to the employee to pay these wages. As seen in the definition and the example, every claim-right correlates to a duty in (at least) one duty-bearer.
Not all claim-rights are created by voluntary actions like signing a contract; and not all claim-rights correspond to duties in just one agent. For example, a child's claim-right against abuse exists independently of anyone's actions, and the child's claim-right correlates to a duty in every other person not to abuse her. This example of the child's right also illustrates how a claim-right can require duty-bearers to refrain from performing some action (i.e., that "phi" can be a negative verb).
2.1.3 Powers
Privileges and claims define what Hart called "primary rules": rules requiring that people perform or refrain from particular actions (Hart 1961). Indeed privileges and claims define the primary rules for all physical actions. Were we to know all the privileges and claims that there are, we would know for every possible physical action whether it was required, forbidden, or permitted.
Two further Hohfeldian incidents define what Hart called "secondary rules": rules that specify how agents can introduce, change, and annul primary rules.
The Hohfeldian power is the incident that explains how agents can alter primary rules:
A has a power if and only if A has the ability within a set of rules to alter her own or another's Hohfeldian incidents.
A ship's captain has the power-right to order a midshipman to scrub the deck. The captain's exercise of this power changes the sailor's normative situation: it imposes a new duty upon him. Similarly, a promisor exercises a power-right to create in the promisee a claim that the promisor will perform a certain action. The promisor's exercise of her power-right to promise creates in the promisee a claim that the promisor do what she promised to do. Ordering, promising, sentencing, waiving, buying, selling, and abandoning are all acts by which a rightholder exercises a power to change his own normative situation or that of another.
Powers can alter not only "first-order" privileges and claims, but "second-order" incidents as well (Sumner 1987, 31). An admiral, for example, has the power-right to relieve a captain of his power-right to command a ship. The authority to alter the authority of others is, as we will see, part of what defines any legal or political system.
2.1.4 Immunities
The fourth and final Hohfeldian incident is the immunity. When A has the ability to alter B's Hohfeldian incidents, then A has a power. When A lacks the ability to alter B's Hohfeldian incidents, then B has an immunity:
B has an immunity if and only if A lacks the ability within a set of rules to alter B's Hohfeldian incidents.
The United States Congress lacks the ability to impose upon American citizens a duty to kneel daily before a cross. Since the Congress lacks a power, the citizens have an immunity. This immunity is part of each American citizen's right to religious freedom. Similarly, witnesses in court have a right not to be obliged to incriminate themselves, and civil servants have a right not to be dismissed after a new administration comes to power. All of these rights are immunities, corresponding to an absence of a power in some other party to alter the rightholder's normative situation in some way.
2.1.5 Opposites and Correlatives
Hohfeld arranged the four incidents in tables of "opposites" and "correlatives" so as to display the logical structure of his system. In order to fill out the tables he added some further terminology. For instance, if a person A has a claim, then A lacks a "no-claim" (a no-claim is the opposite of a claim). And if a person A has a power, then some person B has a "liability" (a liability is the correlative of a power).
Opposites If A has a Claim, then A lacks a No-claim. … Privilege, … Duty. … Power, … Disability. … Immunity, … Liability.
Correlatives If A has a Claim, then some person B has a Duty. … Privilege, … No-claim. … Power, … Liability. … Immunity, … Disability.
2.1.6 Molecular Rights
Each of the "atomic" incidents—the privilege, claim, power, and immunity—can be a right when it occurs in isolation. Yet as mentioned above these atomic incidents also bond together in characteristic ways to constitute many ordinary rights. Following, for example, is the "molecular" structure of a property right that you have over your computer:
A "Molecular" Property Right
In the figure, the "first-order" rights are your rights directly over your property—in this case, your computer. The privilege on this first level entitles you to use your computer. The claim correlates to a duty in every other person not to use your computer.
The "second-order" rights are your rights concerning the alteration of these first-order rights. You have several powers with respect to your claim—you may waive the claim (granting others permission to touch the computer), annul the claim (abandoning the computer as your property), or transfer the claim (making the computer into someone else's property). Also on the second order, your immunity prevents others from altering your first-order rights over your computer. Your immunity, that is, prevents others from waiving, annulling, or transferring your claim over your computer. The four incidents together constitute your property right.
Of course none of these incidents is entirely unqualified: you have no privilege to strike others with your computer, or to use your computer to hack into someone else's machine; and your immunity may not entirely block out the state's power of expropriation (if for example the computer becomes evidence in a criminal case). These qualifications to the incidents determine the details of the contours of your property right, but they do not affect its basic shape.
There may also be more incidents associated with ownership than shown in the figure above. Wellman (1985, 1995) describes each right as having a "defining core" surrounded by "associated elements"—much as a molecule has a nucleus surrounded by electrons which may be present or absent within a particular isotope. Your property right, for instance, may also be protected by a qualified third-order immunity against the government altering your second-order rights over your property (for example, under the "Takings Clause" of the Fifth Amendment to the US Constitution the government cannot simply annul your right to sell a parcel of your land).
2.1.7 Active and Passive Rights
The distinction between active and passive rights (Lyons 1970) maps neatly onto the Hohfeldian incidents. The privilege and the power are "active" rights that their holders exercise. The claim and the immunity are "passive" rights that their holders merely enjoy. Active rights are signaled by statements of the form "A has a right to φ"; while passive rights are signaled by statements of the form "A has a right that B φ" (in both of these formulas, "φ" is an active verb).
A naval captain has an active privilege-right to walk the decks and an active power-right to order that the ship set sail. A college professor has a passive claim-right that students not disrupt her lectures, and a passive immunity-right that her university not fire her for publishing unpopular views.
2.1.8 Negative and Positive Rights
A distinction between negative and positive rights is popular among some normative theorists, especially those with a bent toward libertarianism. The holder of a negative right is entitled to non-interference, while the holder of a positive right is entitled to provision of some good or service. A right against assault is a classic example of a negative right, while a right to welfare assistance is a prototypical positive right (Narveson 2001).
Since both negative and positive rights are passive rights, this division cannot capture all rights. Privileges and powers cannot be negative rights; and privileges, powers, and immunities cannot be positive rights. For example the right to enter into a binding agreement, and the right to veto a bill, are neither negative nor positive.
It is sometimes said that negative rights are easier to satisfy than positive rights. Negative rights can be respected simply by each person refusing to interfere with each other, while it may be impossible to respect everyone's positive rights if the sum of claims on goods and services outstrips the resources available.
However, when it comes to the enforcement of rights, this difference disappears. It may require more resources, for instance, for the state to run a legal system that enforces citizens' negative rights against assault than for the state to run a welfare system that realizes citizens' positive rights to assistance. As Holmes and Sunstein (1999, 43) put it, in the context of citizens' rights to state enforcement, all rights are positive. Moreover, the point is often made that the moral urgency of respecting positive rights may be just as great as the moral urgency of respecting negative rights (Shue 1996). Whatever is the justification of ascribing rights—autonomy, need, or something else—there may be just as strong a case for ensuring that a person has adequate nutrition as for ensuring that the person not be beat up.
2.2 The Function of Rights: The Will Theory and the Interest Theory
2.2.1 Conceptual Analysis versus Definitional Stipulation
All rights can be represented by Hohfeldian diagrams like the diagram of the property right above. Some diagrams that we could imagine, however, contain collections of Hohfeldian incidents that do not correspond to any real right. Rights are only those collections of Hohfeldian incidents that have a certain function (or perhaps certain functions). To take an analogy: all thrones are chairs, but only chairs with a certain function are thrones.
The question of the function of rights is the question of what rights do for those who hold them. Before discussing the two major positions on this issue, we can survey some statements that theorists have made that appear to be analyzing which Hohfeldian incidents are rights:
- "In the strictest sense" all rights are claims (Hohfeld 1919, 36).
- All rights are "valid claim[s]" (Feinberg 1970, 257).
- "A right, in the most important sense, is the conjunction of a [privilege] and a claim-right" (Mackie 1979, 169).
- "Rights are permissions rather than requirements. Rights tell us what the bearer is at liberty to do, not what he must or must not do" (Louden 1983, 95).
- "No one ever has a right to do something; he only has a right that some one else shall do (or refrain from doing) something" (Williams 1968, 125).
- "A right is an established way of acting" (Martin 1993, 1).
- "It is hard to think of rights except as capable of exercise" (Hart 1982, 185).
- "A right is a power which a creature ought to possess" (Plamenatz 1938, 82).
- "All rights are essentially property rights" (Steiner 1994, 93).
At first this survey might remind one the proverb of the blind men and the elephant. However, we should distinguish between two different aims that a theorist might have when he make a statement of the form "All rights are x." A theorist may be attempting to analyze the meaning of our ordinary concept of rights, or he may be stipulating a definition of "rights" within his own moral or legal theory.
Consider, for example, Mill's famous statement in Utilitarianism:
When we call anything a person's right, we mean that he has a valid claim on society to protect him in the possession of it, either by the force of law, or by that of education and opinion… To have a right, then, is, I conceive, to have something which society ought to defend me in the possession of (Mill 1861, 54).
As an analysis of our everyday concept of a right, this passage would be weak. There is nothing incoherent in asserting, for example, that God has a right to promulgate law to his creatures; yet presumably no one asserting such a right would hold that society ought to defend God in the possession of it. Indeed there seems nothing incoherent in asserting that individuals have a right not to be protected by society; yet this assertion could not make sense if Mill had located a valid analysis.
Mill's statement is better seen as a stipulative definition of "right." Mill stipulates this particular definition because the concept of "those possessive relations that are valuable enough that it is worthwhile to institute societal sanctions to protect them" is a concept that works well within his larger utilitarian theory. So where Mill's statement departs from the common understanding of rights, we should charitably read Mill as prescribing, instead of describing, usage. Many authors' pronouncements about rights are charitably interpreted as these kinds of exercises in stipulation, rather than as attempts to analyze the ordinary concept of rights.
2.2.2 The Will Theory and the Interest Theory
There are two main theories of the function of rights: the will theory and the interest theory. Each claims to capture our ordinary understanding of what rights do for those who hold them. Which theory offers the better account has been the subject of spirited dispute, literally for ages.
Will theorists maintain that a right makes the rightholder "a small scale sovereign" (Hart 1982, 183). More specifically, a will theorist asserts that the function of a right is to give its holder power over another's duty. You are the "sovereign" of your computer, in that you may allow others to touch it or not at your discretion. Your property molecule in the figure above is a right because it contains a power to waive others' duty not to touch your computer. Similarly a promisee has a right because he has the power to waive the promisor's duty to keep the promise. In Hohfeldian terms, will theorists assert that every right includes a Hohfeldian power over a claim. In colloquial terms, will theorists believe that all rights confer the ability to control whether others must or must not act in particular ways.
Interest theorists disagree. Interest theorists maintain that the function of a right is to further the right-holder's interests. An owner has a right, according to the interest theory, not because owners have choices, but because the ownership makes the owner better off. To take another example, according to the interest theory a promisee has a right because promisees have some interest in the performance of the promise. Rights, the interest theorist says, are the Hohfeldian incidents you have that are good for you.
The contest between will-based and interest-based theories of the function of rights has been waged for hundreds of years. Influential will theorists include Kant, Savigny, Hart, Kelsen, Wellman, and Steiner. Important interest theorists include Bentham, Ihering, Austin, Lyons, MacCormick, Raz, and Kramer. Each theory has its advantages and drawbacks as an account of what rights do for rightholders.
The will theory captures the powerful link between rights and normative control. To have a right is to have the ability to determine what others may and may not do, and so to exercise authority over a certain domain of affairs. The resonant connection between rights and freedom (of a certain sort) is for will theorists a matter of definition.
However, the will theorist's account of the function of rights leaves him unable to account for many rights that most think there are. Within the will theory there can be no such thing as an unwaivable right: a right over which its holder has no power. Yet intuitively it would appear that unwaivable rights are some of the most important rights that we have: consider, for example, the unwaivable right not to be enslaved (MacCormick 1977, 197). Moreover, since the will theorist holds that all rights confer sovereignty, he cannot acknowledge rights in beings incapable of exercising sovereignty. Within the will theory it is impossible for "incompetents" like infants, animals, and comatose adults to have rights. Yet we ordinarily would not doubt that these incompetents can have rights, for example the right not to be tortured (MacCormick 1982, 154-66).
The interest theory is more capacious than the will theory. It can accept as rights both unwaivable rights (the possession of which may be good for their holders) and the rights of incompetents (who have interests that rights can protect). The interest theory also taps into the deeply plausible connection between holding rights and being better off.
However, the interest theory is also misaligned with an ordinary understanding of rights. We appear to accept that people can have interests in x without having a right to x; and contrariwise that people can have a right to x without having interests sufficient to explain this. In the first category are "third party beneficiaries." (Lyons 1994, 36-46). You may have a powerful interest in the lottery paying out for your spouse's winning ticket, but you have no right that the lottery pays out to your spouse. In the second category are many of the rights of office-holders and role-bearers (Jones 1994, 31-32; Kamm 2002, 485). Whatever interest a judge may have in exercising her legal right to sentence a convict to life in prison, the judge's interests cannot possibly justify such a dramatic change in the convict's normative situation.
Over the centuries, will theorists and interest theorists have developed their positions with increasing technical sophistication. The issues that divide the two camps are clearly defined, and the debates between them are often intense (Kramer, Simmonds, and Steiner 1998). Which account of the functions of rights is correct—or whether we ought to think that rights have some single function at all (Wenar 2005)—is one of the major unresolved issues in the theory of rights.
3. The History of the Language of Rights
Intellectual historians have debated extensively the question of the origins of the idea of a right. These debates are sometimes framed in terms of when "the concept of a right" emerged. Yet insofar as it is really the emergence of the concept of a right that is at issue, the answer lies beyond the competence of the intellectual historian. Even the most primitive social order must include rules specifying that certain individuals or groups have special permission to perform certain actions. Moreover, even the most rudimentary human groups must have rules specifying that some are entitled to tell others what to do. Such rules ascribe rights. The genesis of the concept of a right must be simultaneous with reflective awareness of social norms.
The more productive debate within intellectual history concerns the question of when a word or phrase emerges whose meaning is close to the meanings of our modern sense of "a right." This debate turns on when terms indicating an older, "objective" sense of "right" came also to bear our modern, "subjective" sense of "a right."
"Right" in its older objective sense means "what is just" or "what is fair" (Finnis 1980, 206). Aristotle uses dikaion, for example, to indicate that a society is "rightly ordered": that it displays the correct structure of human relationships "Right" in this objective sense can also be attributed to individuals. The Roman jurist Ulpian, for instance, held that justice meant rendering each his right (ius). In this sense, a person's "right" is what is due to him given his role or status. This objective sense of "right" is not equivalent to our modern idea of a right. For instance, Ulpian noted that the ius of a parricide was to be sewn into a sack of snakes and tossed into the Tiber (Tierney 1997, 16).
The scholarly inquiry into when our modern, subjective sense of "a right" became established as a meaning of some word has proved long and divisive. The ancient authors often used words imprecisely, and smeared their meanings across and beyond the Hohfeldian categories. The intellectual historians themselves have occasionally congested the discussion by taking different features of rights as definitive of the modern concept. Moreover, the scholarly debate has sometimes appeared to be based on an over-optimistic assumption about the sharpness of conceptual boundaries (resembling, in this way, certain contemporary debates over when in embryological development "a person" comes into being).
Nevertheless, there have been two broad trends in the recent scholarly discussions. The first has been to push the emergence of a term indicating a modern, subjective sense of "a right" back further into history: from Locke in the seventeenth century, to Hobbes and Grotius in the sixteenth, to Gerson in the fifteenth century, Ockham in the fourteenth, perhaps even to Gratian in the twelfth (Brett 1997, Tierney 1997). The second and related trend has been to establish that terms referring to active rights (what we would call privilege-rights and power-rights) predate terms referring to passive rights (what we would call claim-rights and immunity-rights). It appears that the earliest debates using recognizably modern rights-language concerned topics such as whether the popes have a right to rule an earthly empire, and whether the poor have a right to take from the surplus of the rich.
4. Rights and Freedom
Most rights entitle their holders to freedom; indeed holding a right can entail that one is free in one or more of a variety of senses. In the most general terms, the active incidents—the privilege and the power—entitle their holders to the freedom to act in certain ways. The passive incidents—the claim and the immunity—often entitle their holders to freedom from unwanted actions or states.
We can be more specific. A privilege-right makes it holder "free to" in the sense of non-forbiddenness. A government employee with a security clearance, for instance, has a right that makes him free to read classified documents. One can be free in this "no duty not to do it" sense without having the physical ability to do what one is free to do. You may be free to march in the parade, even when both your knees are sprained. The actions you are free to do in this sense may or may not be possible for you, but at least they are not disallowed.
Someone who has a pair of privilege rights—no duty to perform the action, no duty not to perform the action—is free in an additional sense of having discretion over whether to perform the action or not. You are free to tie your left shoe first, or not, as you like. This dual non-forbiddenness again does not imply physical ability. A rightholder may be disallowed neither from performing nor not performing some action, but this still does not mean that she actually can perform the action that she is free to perform.
In contrast, the holder of a power-right does have an ability. This is the normative ability to exercise authority in a certain way (Sumner 1987, 28). This normative ability confers freedom in a different sense. A judge is free to sentence a convicted criminal to prison. The judge is not merely allowed to sentence the prisoner: her power-right gives her the ability—that is, the authority—to do so. Her right makes her free to sentence in a way that non-judges are not free to sentence.
As for the passive rights, many claim-rights entitle their holders to be "free from" the physical interference or surveillance of others. Other claim-rights entitle their holders to be free from undesirable conditions like hunger or fear. Immunity-rights parallel claim-rights at the next level up: immunity-rights make their holders free from the authority of others, and so free from conditions like tyranny or exploitation.
A legal system can be seen as a distribution of these various types of freedom. Any legal system will set out rules specifying who is free to act in which ways, and who should be free from the unwanted actions of others. A legal system will also determine who has the authority (and so who is free) to interpret and enforce these rules.
More generally, a political constitution can be seen as a multi-level structure of rights that distributes authority over rules of conduct in a distinctive way. A democratic constitution, for example, may give voters the power to elect legislators, who have certain powers to enact laws, which the judiciary has certain powers to interpret, and the police have certain powers to enforce. The facts about who should be free to do what within any legal or political system, as well as the facts about who should be free from which actions and conditions, will be expressible as a complex set of layered rights.
5. Rights and Reasons
5.1 Rights as Trumps
Though there is disagreement over the function of rights and the history of rights language, all agree that rights have special normative force. The reasons that rights provide are particularly powerful or weighty reasons, which override reasons of other sorts. Dworkin's metaphor is of rights as "trumps" (Dworkin 1984). Rights give reasons to treat their holders in certain ways or permit them to act in certain ways, even if some social aim would be served by doing otherwise. As Mill wrote about the trumping power of the right to free speech: "If all mankind minus one were of one opinion, mankind would be no more justified in silencing that one person than he, if he had the power, would be in silencing mankind" (Mill 1859, 20).
Dworkin's metaphor only requires that rights trump non-right objectives, such as increasing national wealth. What of the priority of one right with respect to another? We can keep to the trumps metaphor while recognizing that some rights have a higher priority than others. Within the trump suit, a jack still beats a seven or a three. Your right of way at a flashing yellow light has priority over the right of way of the driver facing a flashing red; and the right of way of an ambulance trumps you both.
This metaphor of trumps leads naturally to the question of whether there is any right that has priority to absolutely all other normative considerations: whether there is an "ace of rights." Gewirth (1981) asserts that there is at least one such absolute right: the right of all persons not to be made the victim of a homicidal project. For such a right to be absolute it would have to trump every other consideration whatsoever: other rights, economic efficiency, saving lives, everything. Not all would agree with Gewirth that even this very powerful right overrides every conceivable normative concern. Some would think it might be justifiable to infringe even this right were this somehow necessary, for example, to prevent the deaths of a great many people. If it is permissible to kill one in order to save a billion, then not even Gewirth's right is absolute.
5.2 Conflicts of Rights?
The trumping metaphor makes it tempting to characterize the normative force of rights in terms of conclusive reasons of some sort. We could indeed attempt to define the Hohfeldian incidents in these terms. A's having a privilege-right to φ would imply that A has no conclusive reason not to φ, and A's having a claim-right that B φ would imply that B has a conclusive reason to φ. Powers and immunities would then determine the ways in which agents were and were not able to alter the patterns of conclusive reasons in the world.
Were we to go this route, we would need to temper the "conclusiveness" of the conclusive reasons implied by rights assertions in recognition of the fact that, as we have seen, some rights have priority to others, and that few if any rights outweigh absolutely all non-right considerations in all circumstances. If we associate rights with conclusive reasons, then for at least most rights these reasons can only be conclusive with respect to some but not all competing considerations.
This line of thought could be developed by saying that the reasons associated with rights are conclusive within the area covered by the right, but are not conclusive outside of that area. Each right trumps competing considerations in most circumstances, but there are certain circumstances in which another right with higher priority (or a pressing non-right consideration) determines what should be done. From this perspective, the conclusive reasons implied by rights assertions really are conclusive, but only within defined circumstances. Every right is absolute, within a specifically delimited space.
The theoretical position at the end of this line of thought is called "specificationism" (Shafer-Landau 1995). The specificationist holds that each right is defined by an elaborate set of qualifications that specify when it does and when it does not apply: a set of qualifications that define the right's "space."
The test of specificationism is how convincingly it can explain what occurs when rights appear to conflict. Rights often appear to conflict (Sinnott-Armstrong 1996). For example, on a certain day it may seem that the public's right to protest is conflicting with the government's right to keep order on public property. When confronted with a specific case like this one, we will judge that one or the other (say, the public's) right should prevail. However, we do not believe that one of these rights is always stronger than the other. Given different circumstances, our judgment might favor the other (in this case, the government's) right. When rights appear to conflict like this, the usefulness of the image of rights as trumps begins to dim. Both of these rights are trump cards, yet it does not appear that one right always trumps the other.
A specificationist will attempt to dispel any appearance of conflict of rights. For example, a specificationist will say that what is colloquially referred to as "the public's right to protest" is actually, on closer examination, "the public's right to protest, unless the protest would cause serious risk to life or property, or would lead to the spread of a deadly disease, or…" Similarly, the government's right should be specified more fully as the right: "to control what happens on public property, but not to the extent of stopping peaceful protest, unless the protest would lead to the spread of deadly disease, but not…" On the specificationist view, rights never do conflict in the sense of overlapping in a given case. Rather, rights fit together like pieces in a jigsaw puzzle, so that in every circumstance there is only one right which determines what is permitted, forbidden or required. Each right is absolute within its own area, but the area in which each right prevails is elaborately gerrymandered. Rights never conflict: they are always, to use Steiner's phrase, "compossible" (Steiner 1994).
Feinberg (1980, 221-51) and Thomson (1990) put forward three objections to this specificationist view of rights. First, fully specified rights would be unknowable: no one could set out all of the qualifications that define even the simplest right. Second, rights so understood lose their explanatory force: for the specificationist rights can only be the conclusions, not the premises, of arguments concerning which side in any dispute should prevail. Third, specificationists cannot explain the "moral residue" of a "defeated" right. For instance, take a case in which your property right in the pie cooling on your window sill conflicts with my right to do what I must to keep from starving. My right may prevail in this case: I may have a right to eat your pie. Still, after I sate myself I should apologize to you, and compensate you if I can. Thomson alleges that specificationists cannot explain the requirements that I apologize to and compensate you, since on their view there is no right of yours that I have violated when I consume your food. Thomson prefers the view that there really are conflicts of rights, and suggests that we should speak of a "defeated" right as being permissibly "infringed" (instead of "violated").
5.3 Rights to Do Wrong
Are there rights to do wrong? Many have thought that there are. Waldron (1993, 63) gives the example of antiwar protesters organizing a rowdy demonstration near a Remembrance Day service; Wellman (1997, 33) offers the illustration of edging first into a checkout line with a full cart, ahead of a tired woman carrying triplets. The puzzle is how the positive normative force of "a right" can exist so close to an opposed normative pole, "wrong." In Hohfeldian terms, how can there be a right (no duty not) to do what it is wrong (duty not) to do? (Similar questions arise about "the abuse of rights" (Schauer 1984).)
There are two readings of rights to do wrong. The first characterizes most rights as furthering the holder's autonomy. Rights entitle their holders to make choices, and as Waldron says the importance of a person's having choices would be diminished if she were forced to do the right thing. Even though the person has no (privilege-) right to perform an action that is wrong, it would nevertheless violate an important (claim-) right of hers for others to interfere with her performance of that action. To take the speech example, we respect the autonomy of speakers when we allow them to speak unmolested—even when they do wrong by expressing themselves in a way that is disrespectful to others.
The second reading of rights to do wrong sees them as involving a mid-sentence shift in domains of reasons. There is no mystery, after all, in having a legal right to do something morally wrong. The potential for a legal right to do a moral wrong arises from the fact that the domains of legal and moral reasons are not perfectly aligned. One has a legal privilege to edge in front of the tired mother in the check-out line, but this is something that one has a moral duty not to do. Similarly, one could have a moral right to do what one has no customary right to do, and so on. Each domain of reasons is distinct, and however conclusive are the reasons that any particular rights-assertion implies, these are only reasons within a single domain of reasons (moral, or legal, or customary).
5.4 Rights to Believe, Feel, and Want
Moral rights, legal rights, and customary rights all define domains of rights within the realm of rights of conduct: rights concerning how agents should act. When our reasons within these three different domains conflict, we may have reasons of different kinds to act in different ways. Yet there are also rights that lie beyond the realm of conduct entirely. These are rights to believe, to feel and to want. For example, the president asserts that he had a right to believe what his advisors told him. The mother says that she has a right to be upset that her wayward son has failed again to keep his promise. The frustrated suburbanite complains he has a right to want more out of life.
The realm of rights of conduct is only one of four distinct realms of rights, the other three being the realms of epistemic, of affective, and of conative rights. Each of these four realms of rights defines a separate conceptual space: there are no epistemic rights to act, and no affective rights to believe. What is distinctive about the three realms of rights beyond the rights of conduct is that they contain only privilege-rights (Wenar 2003). One may, for example, have a privilege-right to believe what one's eyes tell one, and a privilege-right to feel proud of what one has done. It is interesting to consider why these epistemic, affective, and conative realms contain no claims, powers, or immunities.
Philosophers have long been interested in epistemic rights in particular. William James, for instance, begins The Will to Believe by calling it, "an essay in justification of faith, a defense of our right to adopt a believing attitude in religious matters, in spite of the fact that our merely logical intellect may not have been coerced." James's "radical" conclusion in the essay is that "we have the right to believe at our own risk any hypothesis that is live enough to tempt our will." (James 1897, 2, 29) Similarly the deepest questions in Kant's philosophy are framed in terms of rights. In the Critique of Pure Reason the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories aims to prove the validity of the employment of the concepts of pure understanding. In the Critique of Practical Reason the Deduction of Freedom aims to demonstrate our entitlement to regard ourselves as free. In both Deductions the central question is a quaestio iuris: "By what right?" Kant's questions are: By what right do we employ the categories; and by what right do we think of ourselves as free?
6. Two Approaches to the Justification of Rights
There are two major contemporary philosophical approaches to explaining which fundamental rights of conduct there are, and why these rights should be respected. These two approaches are broadly identifiable as deontological and consequentialist. Status theories hold that human beings have attributes that make it fitting to ascribe certain rights to them, and make respect for these rights appropriate. Instrumental theories hold that respect for particular rights is a means for bringing about some optimal distribution of interests. Each approach has characteristic strengths and weaknesses, and the long-running contest between them is ongoing.
Quinn (1993, 170) sketches a contemporary status theory this way:
A person is constituted by his body and his mind. They are parts or aspects of him. For that very reason, it is fitting that he have primary say over what may be done to them—not because such an arrangement best promotes overall human welfare, but because any arrangement that denied him that say would be a grave indignity. In giving him this authority, morality recognizes his existence as an individual with ends of his own—an independent being. Since that is what he is, he deserves this recognition.
Quinn claims that there is some attribute of the person—here, being "an individual with ends of his own"—that merits recognition from others. The recognition due to each individual can be accorded to that individual by respecting his fundamental rights.
Quinn contrasts his status approach to rights with one that ascribes rights "because such an arrangement best promotes overall human welfare." His target is consequentialist theories of rights, the paradigm of which are utilitarian theories. We met such a utilitarian theory of rights above in John Stuart Mill's conceptualization of rights as "something which society ought to defend me in the possession of." Mill believed that society ought to defend the individual in possession of his rights because doing so would bring about the greatest aggregate utility summed across the members of that society. For Mill, as for other instrumental theorists, rights are a tool for producing an optimal distribution of interests across some group.
The two approaches differ sharply over the role of consequences in the justification of ascribing rights. Status theorists hold that rights should be respected because it is fitting to do so, and not because of the good consequences that will flow from so doing. By contrast, within an instrumental theory good consequences are the justification for promulgating and enforcing rights. As Quinn (1993, 173) says about the status approach:
It is not that we think it fitting to ascribe rights because we think it is a good thing that rights be respected. Rather we think respect for rights a good thing precisely because we think people actually have them—and… that they have them because it is fitting that they should.
Within a status approach rights are not means for the promotion of good consequences. They are rather, in Nozick's phrase, side constraints on the pursuit of good consequences (Nozick 1974, 29). A status approach frowns on any rights violation, even for the sake of maximizing the non-violation of rights overall (as in a "utilitarianism of rights"). Such an approach emphasizes the "agent-relative" reasons that each person has to avoid violating the rights of others.
A status-based justification thus begins with the nature of the rightholder and arrives immediately at the right. The instrumental approach starts with the desired consequences (like maximum utility) and works backward to see which rights-ascriptions will produce those consequences.
6.1 Status-Based Rights
Status theories belong to the tradition of natural rights theories. All natural rights theories fix upon features that humans have by their nature, and which make respect for certain rights appropriate. The theories differ over precisely which attributes of humans give rise to rights, although non-religious theories tend to fix upon the same sorts of attributes described in more or less metaphysical or moralized terms: rationality, free will, autonomy, the ability to regulate one's life in accordance with one's chosen conception of the good life. Natural rights theorists agree that human reason can grasp the fact that it is appropriate to treat beings with such attributes in certain ways, although they disagree on whether such facts are "self-evident."
Natural rights theory reached its high point in the early modern era, in the work of Grotius, Hobbes, Pufendorf, and especially Locke. Locke argued that men have rights to "life, liberty, and estate" in a pre-political state of nature, and that these natural rights put limits on the legitimate authority of the state. Locke's influence can be seen in the revolutionary American and French political documents of the eighteenth century, and especially in Jefferson's Declaration of Independence: "We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable rights, that among these are Life, Liberty, and the Pursuit of Happiness."
The revival of status theory within contemporary philosophy began with Nozick's Anarchy State and Utopia (1974). While Nozick does bear a debt to Locke's theory of property, his work belongs more to the Kantian tradition of natural rights theorizing. Nozick centers his explanation of the moral force of individual rights on the Kantian imperative against treating persons merely as means to ends. Each person's rights impose side-constraints on the pursuit of others' goals, Nozick maintained, because that person possesses an inviolability that all others must respect. "Individuals have rights," he wrote, "and there are things no person or group may do to them (without violating their rights)" (Nozick 1974, ix).
Many find this grounding of rights in individual dignity appealing. There is also a directness and clarity to status explanations of fundamental rights. For example, Kamm (2002, 486-87) explains the right of free expression as follows:
The right to speak may simply be the only appropriate way to treat people with minds of their own and the capacity to use means to express [them]… It fails to respect people not to give them the option of speaking.
Moreover, status-based rights are attractively robust. While the justifications of instrumental rights are always contingent on calculations concerning consequences, status-based rights are anchored firmly in individual dignity. This makes it easy to explain why status-based rights are strong, almost unqualified rights, and this is a position which many believe properly expresses the great value of each individual.
However, the strength of status-based rights can also be seen as a weakness of the theory. One does not wish to be carried from the great importance of each individual to the implausible position that all fundamental rights are absolute. As Nagel (2002, 36) allows while defending a status view, "there are evils great enough so that one would be justified in murdering or torturing an innocent person to prevent them." Consequences, if bad enough, do justify the qualification of individual rights, which leaves the status theorist needing to explain how a theory which rejects consequences so resolutely at the outset can concede their importance later on.
Moreover, the directness of the status approach to rights can also appear to be a liability. On close examination, the fundamental rights that most people believe in are intricately "shaped." For example, consider the widely-accepted right to free speech. This right includes the right to make damning personal attacks on others. Yet the right that we acknowledge is much more permissive about assailing public figures than it is about attacking private citizens. Or again: the right to free speech contains a right to say what the speaker knows to be untrue. Yet we are much more tolerant of deceitful speech in politics than we are in advertising or in the courtroom. It is an open question whether status theory has the conceptual resources to explain why individual rights should be shaped in these specific ways.
Status theory also faces the challenge of vindicating its foundations and its scope. Why after all is it "fitting" to ascribe individuals rights? The Kantian value of inviolability can look puzzling when presented independently of a metaphysical grounding. As Nagel (2002, 34) admits, "it has proven extremely difficult to account for such a basic, individualized value such that it becomes morally intelligible." This is a soft echo of Bentham's protest that the doctrine of natural rights "is from beginning to end so much flat assertion: it lays down as a fundamental and inviolable principle whatever is in dispute" (Bentham 1796, 66).
Moreover, status theorists must also resolve an internal debate over exactly which rights should be thought express an individual's inviolability. Nozick held that private property rights are status-based, while other status theorists reject the libertarianism to which Nozick's position leads. The resolution of this debate has recently become more urgent, as a group of neo-Kantian and neo-Lockean "left libertarian" theorists have advanced the view that the status of individuals requires that each be accorded strong rights to self-ownership, along with initially equal shares of "world-ownership" (Vallentyne and Steiner 2000, Otsuka 2003).
6.2 Instrumental Rights
Instrumental theories depict rights as instruments for achieving an optimal distribution of interests. The archetypal instrumental theory is some form of two-level consequentialism, such as rule utilitarianism. Within such a theory rights are rules, the general observance of which will lead to an optimal distribution of interests. In rule utilitarianism the optimal distribution is the one that contains the greatest aggregate utility.
The most common objection to grounding rights in such a theory is that the resulting rights will be too flimsy. If rights are justified only insofar as they generate good consequences, it may seem that the theory will need to prune its rights, perhaps severely, whenever maximum utility lies elsewhere. Why should it not be a rule of such a system, for example, that one should frame an innocent man if this would prevent a major riot? Why should it not be a rule that one should "violate" the right of an innocent not to be killed if this would prevent the killings of two innocents elsewhere? While status-based rights can appear to be too strong, instrumental rights can appear to be too weak.
Weak rights are a problem for utilitarianism because its focus on maximization makes it indifferent to certain facts about how utility is distributed across individuals. However, utilitarianism is not the only kind of instrumental theory. Other instrumental theories, which do not define an optimal distribution in terms of maximization, may not have the same problems with weak rights (Scanlon 1977).
For example, a pure egalitarian theory will portray rights as instruments for achieving a more equal distribution of interests. A prioritarian theory will define an optimal distribution in a manner similar to egalitarianism, except that it will give extra weight to the interests of the worst off. Other theories may characterize an optimal distribution in other ways (Sumner 1987, 171). A contractualist theory may define an optimal distribution as one that no one could reasonably reject. A Rawlsian theory may define the optimal distribution as a fair one: i.e., the distribution that would be chosen from the perspective of an original position. A great many contemporary normative theorists have set out systems that give a central role to instrumental rights: for example, Dworkin, Hare, Harsanyi, Hayek, Hurka, Posner, Rawls, Scanlon, and Sen.
There is no reason to think that the rights grounded within non-maximizing instrumental theories must be weak. Rawls's justice as fairness, for example, generates a principle of justice that gives individual rights "absolute weight with respect to reasons of public good and perfectionist values" (Rawls 1971, 294). Here fundamental rights are not weak but, as in Dworkin's phrase, "trumps."
Instrumental theories differ over how they define what counts as an optimal distribution. They also differ in how they measure individual interests. For instance, a utilitarian's metric for interests is utility, Rawls works with a metric of primary goods, Sen with capabilities, Dworkin with resources, and so on.
Whatever metric they use, all instrumental theorists will have to address longstanding questions about the commensurability and interpersonal comparison of interests. Since instrumental theorists work with overall evaluations of how well off individuals would be were certain rights ascribed, they must explain how distinct categories of interests (e.g., health, income, opportunities for self-expression, social recognition) trade off against one another. They must also explain why they believe that these interests are similar enough across persons that it makes sense to use the same scales of measurement for different persons (Griffin 1989).
Status theories are subject to the objection that they lack the conceptual resources to explain why the rights we believe in are intricately "shaped" to accommodate the particularities of different contexts and different rightholders. Instrumental theories are vulnerable to the opposite objection. An instrumental theorist can appeal to any number of distinct interests, which are at stake for any number of differently-situated individuals, to explain why a certain right should be held only by certain persons or only in certain circumstances. The danger for such a theorist is that the wealth of conceptual resources at her command will permit the ascription of whatever rights she favors. The theorist begins with the rights that she wants to justify, and then gives a "just so" story in terms of an optimal distribution of interests that leads to exactly those rights (Tushnet 1984, Frey 1985). Moreover all instrumental justifications rely on empirical predictions concerning which ascriptions of rights would produce which consequences, and there will typically be enough slack in these empirical predictions for instrumental theorists to fudge their derivations in order to reach to the desired rights.
Both status theories and instrumental theories of rights have held an enduring attraction. Because of this, many have been tempted to search for a hybrid or unified approach that would combine the strengths of each (e.g., Sen, 1982). Locating a widely-acceptable and unified approach to the justification of rights remains a standing challenge in moral and political theory.
7. Critiques of Rights
Critiques of rights come in two forms. The first is an attack on the substance of doctrines that give rights a central place. These critiques allege that the content of such doctrines is, in one way or other, malformed or unjustified. Here we find, for example, the criticism that natural rights doctrines are "so much flat assertion," and that utilitarian rights tend to be implausibly weak. The second form of critique attacks the language of rights itself. The objection here is that it is inappropriate or counterproductive to express at least some kinds of normative concerns in terms of rights. We should, according to the second form of critique, reduce or avoid "rights talk."
7.1 Critiques of Rights Doctrine
Marx attacked the substance of the revolutionary eighteenth century American and French political documents that proclaimed the fundamental "rights of man": liberty, equality, security, property, and the free exercise of religion. Marx objected that these alleged rights derive from a false conception of the human individual as unrelated to others, as having interests can be defined without reference to others, and as always potentially in conflict with others. The rights-bearing individual is an "isolated monad…withdrawn behind his private interests and whims and separated from the community" (Marx 1844, 146).
The right of property, Marx asserted, exemplifies the isolating and anti-social character of these alleged rights of man. On the one hand, the right of property is the right to keep others at a distance: the legal equivalent of a barbed wire fence. On the other hand, the right of property allows an owner to transfer his resources at his own pleasure and for his own gain, without regard even for the desperate need for those resources elsewhere.
Similarly, Marx held that the much-celebrated individual right to liberty is based upon and reinforces selfishness. Those who are ascribed the right to do what they wish so long as they do not hurt others will perpetuate a culture of egoistical obsession. As for equality, the achievement of equal rights merely distracts people from noticing that their equality is purely formal: a society with formally equal rights will continue to be divided by huge inequalities in economic and political power. Finally, these so-called "natural" rights are in fact not natural to humans at all. They are simply the defining elements of the rules of the modern mode of production, perfectly suited to fit each individual into the capitalist machine.
Communitarians (Taylor, Walzer, MacIntyre, Sandel) sound several of the same themes in their criticisms of contemporary liberal and libertarian theories. The communitarians object that humans are not, as such theories assume, "antecedently individuated." Nozick's "state of nature" theorizing, for example, errs in presuming that individuals outside of a stable, state-governed social order will develop the autonomous capacities that make them deserving of rights. Nor should we attempt, as in Rawls's original position, to base an argument for rights on what individuals would choose in abstraction from their particular identities and community attachments. There is no way to establish a substantive political theory on what all rational agents want in the abstract. Rather, theorists should look at the particular socio-cultural contexts in which real people live their lives, and at what different goods mean to different people. This criticism continues by accusing liberal and libertarian theories of being falsely universalistic, in insisting that all societies should bend themselves to fit within a uniform structure of rights. Insofar as we should admit rights into our understanding of the world at all, communitarians say, we should see them as part of ongoing practices of social self-interpretation and negotiation—and so as rules that can vary significantly between cultures.
These kinds of criticisms have been discussed in detail (e.g., Gutmann 1985, Waldron 1987b, Mulhall and Swift 1992). Their validity turns on weighty issues in moral and political theory. What can be said here, however, is that a common thread in most of these criticisms—that prominent rights doctrines are in some way excessively individualistic or "atomistic"—need not cut against any theory merely because it uses the language of rights. Ignatieff (2003, 67) errs, for example, when he charges that "rights language cannot be parsed or translated into a nonindividualistic, communitarian framework. It presumes moral individualism and is nonsensical outside that assumption."
As we saw above, the language of rights is able to accommodate rightholders who are individuals as such, but also individuals considered as members of groups, as well as groups themselves, states, peoples, and so on. Indeed the non-individualistic potential of rights-language is more than a formal possibility. The doctrine of international human rights—the modern cousin of eighteenth century natural rights theory—ascribes several significant rights to groups. The Convention against Genocide, for example, forbids actions intending to destroy any national, ethnic, racial or religious group; and the Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural rights ascribes to peoples the right to self-determination. Such examples establish that the language of rights is not individualistic in its essence.
7.2 Critiques of the Language of Rights
The language of rights can resist the charge that it is necessarily complicit with individualism. However, critics have maintained that the language of rights hinders those who use it from achieving several morally valuable goals:
Our rights talk, in its absoluteness promotes unrealistic expectations, heightens social conflict, and inhibits dialogue that might lead toward consensus, accommodation, or at least the discovery of common ground. In its silence concerning responsibilities, it seems to condone acceptance of the benefits of living in a democratic social welfare state, without accepting the corresponding personal and civic obligations…. In its insularity, it shuts out potentially important aids to the process of self-correcting learning. All of these traits promote mere assertion over reason-giving.
Glendon (1991, 14) here draws out some of the detrimental practical consequences of the popular connection between rights and conclusive reasons that we saw above. Since rights assertions suggest conclusive reasons, people can be tempted to assert rights when they want to conclude a discussion instead of continuing it. It may seem appealing, that is, to play a right as a trump card when one has run out of arguments for one's position. Similarly, the ready availability of rights language may lead parties initially at odds with each other toward confrontation instead of negotiation, as each side escalates an arms-race of rights assertions that can only be resolved by a superior authority like a court. A certain strain of feminist theory has picked up on this line of criticism, identifying the peremptory and rigidifying discourse of rights with the confrontational masculine "voice" (Gilligan 1993).
It is not inevitable that these unfortunate tendencies will afflict those who make use of the language of rights. As we have seen, it may be plausible to hold that each right is "absolute" only within a elaborately gerrymandered area. And it may be possible to produce deep theories to justify why one has the rights that one asserts. However, it is plausible that the actual use of rights talk does have the propensities that Glendon suggests. It seems no accident that America, "the land of rights," is also the land of litigation.
Another deleterious consequence of rights talk that Glendon picks out is its tendency to move the moral focus toward agents as rightholders, instead of toward agents as bearers of responsibilities. This critique is developed by O'Neill (1996). A focus on rightholders steers moral reasoning toward the perspective of recipience, instead of toward the traditional active ethical questions of what one ought to do and how one ought to live. Rights talk also leads those who use it to neglect important virtues, such as courage and beneficence, which involve obligations to which no rights correspond. Finally, the use of rights language encourages people to make impractical demands, since one can assert a right without any attention to whether it is desirable or even possible to burden others with the corresponding obligations.
Criticisms such as O'Neill's do not target the language of rights as a whole. They aim squarely at the passive rights, and especially at claim-rights, instead of at the active privileges and powers. Nevertheless, it is again plausible that the spread of rights talk has had the effects that these criticisms suggest. The modern discourse of rights is characteristically deployed by those who see themselves or others as potential recipients, entitled to insist on certain benefits or treatment.
Describing fundamental norms in terms of rights has advantages as well as disadvantages. The language of rights can give clear expression to elaborate structures of freedom and authority. When embodied in particular doctrines, such as in the international human rights documents, the language of rights expresses in accessible terms the standards for minimally acceptable treatment that individuals can demand from each other and from their institutions. Rights are also associated with historical movements for greater liberty and equality, so appeals to rights in pursuit of justice can have a resonance that other assertions lack. Whether these benefits of using rights language are weighty enough to overbalance the costs remains a live question in moral, political and legal theory.
Bibliography
- Bentham, J., 1796, Anarchical Fallacies, in Waldron 1987a: 46-76.
- Brett, A., 1997, Liberty, Right, and Nature, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Dworkin, R., 1984, "Rights as Trumps", in Waldron, 1984: 153-67.
- Feinberg, J., 1970, "The Nature and Value of Rights", Journal of Value Inquiry, 4: 243-257.
- -----, 1980, Rights, Justice, and the Bounds of Liberty, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
- Finnis, J., 1980, Natural Law and Natural Right, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Frey R., 1985, "Act-Utilitarianism, Consequentialism, and Moral Rights", in Frey, R, (ed.), Utility and Rights, Oxford, Basil Blackwell: 61-85.
- Gewirth, A., 1981, "Are There any Absolute Rights?", in Waldron, 1984: 81-109.
- Gilligan, C., 1993, In a Different Voice, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Glendon, M., 1991, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse, New York: Free Press.
- Griffin, J., 1989, Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Importance, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Guttman, A., 1985, "Communitarian Critics of Liberalism", Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14: 308-322.
- Hart, H., 1961, The Concept of Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- -----, 1982, Essays on Bentham: Studies in Jurisprudence and Political Theory, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Hohfeld, W., 1919, Fundamental Legal Conceptions, W. Cook (ed.), New Haven: Yale University Press.
- Holmes, S., and Sunstein, S., 1999, The Costs of Rights, New York: W.W. Norton.
- Ignatieff, M., 2003, "Human Rights, Sovereignty, and Intervention", in Owen, N. (ed.) Human Rights and Human Wrongs: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 2001, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- James, W., 1897 The Will to Believe; page references in the text are to James, W., 1956, The Will to Believe and Human Immortality, New York: Dover.
- Jones, P., 1994, Rights, New York: St. Martin's Press.
- Kamm, F., 1992, "Non-Consequentialism, the Person as an End-in-Itself,and the Significance of Status", Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21: 354-89.
- -----, 2002, "Rights", in The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law, Coleman, J., and Shapiro, S. (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press: 476-513.
- Kramer, M., 2001, "Getting Rights Right", in Rights, Wrongs, and Responsibilities, ed. Kramer. M., London: Macmillan: 28-95.
- Kramer, M., Simmonds, N., and Steiner, H., 1998, A Debate Over Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Louden, R., 1983, "Rights Infatuation and the Impoverishment of Moral Theory", Journal of Value Inquiry, 17: 87-102.
- Lyons, D., 1970, "The Correlativity of Rights and Duties", Nous, 4: 45-57.
- Lyons, D., 1994, Rights, Welfare and Mill's Moral Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- MacCormick, N., 1977, "Rights in Legislation", in Law, Morality and Society: Essays in Honour of H.L.A. Hart, Hacker, P., and Raz, J. (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977: 189-209.
- -----, 1982, Legal Right and Social Democracy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Mackie, J., 1979, "Can There be a Rights-Based Moral Theory?", in Waldron 1984: 168-81.
- Martin, R., 1993, A System of Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Marx, K., 1844, "On the Jewish Question"; page reference in the text is to the reprint in Waldron 1987a: 137-50.
- Mill, J., 1859, On Liberty; page reference in the text is to the reprint in Mill, J., 1989, On Liberty and Other Essays, Collini, S. (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- -----, 1861, Utilitarianism; page reference in the text is to the reprint in Mill, J., 2002, Utilitarianism, Sher, G. (ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett.
- Mulhall, S., and Swift, A., 1992, Liberals and Communitarians, Oxford: Blackwell.
- Nagel, T., 2002, Concealment and Exposure, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Narveson, J., 2001, The Libertarian Idea, Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview.
- O'Neill, O., 1996, Toward Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reasoning, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Otsuka, M., 2003, Libertarianism Without Inequality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Plamenatz, J., 1938, Consent, Freedom, and Political Obligation, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Quinn, W., 1993, Morality and Action, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Rainbolt, G., 2006, The Concept of Rights, Dordrecht: Springer.
- Rawls, J., 1971, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Raz, J., 1986, The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- -----, 1994, Ethics in the Public Domain, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Sandel, M., 1982, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Scanlon, T., 1977, "Rights, Goals, and Fairness", in Waldron 1984: 137-52.
- Schauer, F., 1984, "Can Rights Be Abused?", Philosophical Quarterly 31: 225-30.
- Sen, A., 1982, "Rights and Agency", Philosophy and Public Affairs, 11: 3-39.
- Shafer-Landau, R., 1995, "Specifying Absolute Rights", Arizona Law Review, 37: 209-24.
- Shapiro, I., 1986, The Evolution of Rights in Liberal Theory: An Essay in Critical Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Shue, H., 1996, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
- Sinnott-Armstrong, W., 1996, "Moral Dilemmas and Rights", in Moral Dilemmas and Moral Theory, Mason, H. E. (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press: 48-65.
- Steiner, H., 1994, An Essay on Rights, Oxford, Blackwell.
- Sumner, L., 1987, The Moral Foundations of Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Taylor, C., 1979, "Atomism", in Powers, Possessions, and Freedom, Kontos, A., (ed.), Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
- Thomson, J., 1990, The Realm of Rights, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Tierney, B., 1997, The Idea of Natural Rights, Atlanta: Scholars Press.
- Tushnet, M., 1984, "An Essay on Rights", Texas Law Review, 62: 1363-1403.
- Vallentyne, P., and Steiner, H., 2000, Left Libertarianism and its Critics: The Contemporary Debate, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
- Waldron, J., (ed.), 1984, Theories of Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- -----, (ed.), 1987a, Nonsense Upon Stilts: Bentham, Burke, and Marx on the Rights of Man, London: Methuen.
- -----, 1987b, "Nonsense Upon Stilts?—A Reply", in Waldron 1987a: 151-209.
- Wellman, C., 1985, A Theory of Rights, Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld.
- -----, 1995, Real Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- -----, 1997, An Approach to Rights, Dodrecht: Kluwer.
- Wenar, L., 2003, "Legal Rights and Epistemic Rights", Analysis, 63: 142-46.
- -----, 2005, "The Nature of Rights", Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33: 223-53.
- Williams, G., 1968, "The Concept of a Legal Liberty", in Summers, R. (ed.), Essays in Legal Philosophy, Oxford: Blackwell: 121-44.
Related Entries
communitarianism | consequentialism | legal rights | liberalism | libertarianism | Locke, John | property | reasons for action: agent-neutral vs. agent-relative | rights: human