Incommensurable Values

First published Mon Jul 23, 2007; substantive revision Wed Jul 14, 2021

Values, such as liberty and equality, are sometimes said to be incommensurable in the sense that their value cannot be reduced to a common measure. And options, such as studying to become a lawyer or studying to become a philosopher, are sometimes said to be incomparable in the sense that neither option seems to be at least as good as the other. These possibilities are thought to raise deep questions about practical reason and rational choice as well as related questions concerning topics as diverse as akrasia, moral dilemmas, the plausibility of utilitarianism, and the foundations of liberalism. This entry outlines answers in the contemporary literature to these questions, starting with questions about the nature and possibility of these phenomena.

1. Value Incommensurability

Incommensurability between values must be distinguished from the kind of incommensurability associated with Paul Feyerabend (1978, 1981, 1993) and Thomas Kuhn (1977, 1983, 1996) in epistemology and the philosophy of science. Feyerabend and Kuhn were concerned with incommensurability between rival theories or paradigms — that is, the inability to express or comprehend one conceptual scheme, such as Aristotelian physics, in terms of another, such as Newtonian physics.

In contrast, contemporary inquiry into value incommensurability concerns comparisons among abstract values (such as liberty or equality) or particular bearers of value (such as a certain institution or its effects on liberty or equality). The term “bearer of value” is to be understood broadly. Bearers of value can be objects of potential choice (such as a career) or states of affairs that cannot be chosen (such as a beautiful sunset). Such bearers of value are valuable in virtue of the abstract value or values they instantiate or display (so, for example, an institution might be valuable in virtue of the liberty or equality that it engenders or embodies).

1.1 Measurement and Comparison

The term “incommensurable” suggests the lack of a common measure. This idea has its historical roots in mathematics. For the ancient Greeks, who had not recognized irrational numbers, the dimensions of certain mathematical objects were found to lack a common unit of measurement. Consider the side and the diagonal of a unit square. These can be compared or ranked ordinally, since the diagonal is longer. However, without the use of irrational numbers, there is no way to specify with cardinal numbers exactly how much longer the diagonal is than the side of a unit square. The significance of this kind of incommensurability, especially for the Pythagoreans, is a matter of some debate (Burkert 1972, 455–465). Hippasus of Metapontum, who was thought by many to have demonstrated this kind of incommensurability, is held by legend to have been drowned by the gods for revealing his discovery (Heath 1921, 154; von Fritz 1970, 407).

Given these historical roots, some authors reserve the term “incommensurable” for comparisons that can be made, but not cardinally (Stocker 1980, 176; Stocker 1997, 203; Chang 1997b, 2). Others interpret the idea of a common measure more broadly. On this broader interpretation, for there to be a common measure, all that is required is that ordinal comparisons or rankings are possible. Values or bearers of value are then incommensurable only when not even an ordinal comparison or ranking is possible (e.g., Raz 1986; Rabinowicz 2021a). On this interpretation, incommensurability is defined as the relation that holds between two items when neither is better than the other nor are they equally as good.

Others have not given an exact definition of the term, but use it as an inclusive umbrella term for comparability problems in general. This inclusive interpretation has the advantage of encompassing a field of diverse philosophical discussions which engages in problems concerning value comparisons. This entry encourages the use of “incommensurable” in the etymologically correct way i.e., to refer to the lack of a cardinal scale.

1.2 Incommensurable or Incomparable?

Because the idea of comparison is closely tied to the topic of value incommensurability, this has led to use of the term “incomparable” alongside “incommensurable” in the literature. Some authors use the terms interchangeably (e.g., Raz 1986). Others use them to refer to distinct concepts (e.g., Chang 1997b). This entry will use the term “incomparable” to refer to the possibility that no positive value relation holds between two value bearers (Chang 1997b). Positive value relations specify how two items compare (e.g., “better than”) rather than how two items do not compare (e.g., “not better than”).

Incomparability is often taken to be a three-place relation: A is incomparable with B with respect to V. “V” is here some specific consideration for which the items are being compared. One career may be incomparable to another with respect to the sense of purpose it will bring to your life, yet they may be comparable with respect to financial stability since one is clearly better than the other in this regard. Some argue that without specifying this “covering consideration” the comparative claim makes no sense (Chang 1997; Thomson 1997; Andersson 2016b). Often, however, the covering consideration is not explicitly expressed, but implicitly assumed by the context of utterance.

Specifying the covering consideration also allows us to identify “noncomparability”. If no single covering consideration is applicable to the things we are comparing, then the things are noncomparable. For example, the number four is noncomparable with the color blue with respect to their tastiness. This form of comparative failure is considered to be of no interest from the perspective of practical reasoning and is consequently not given much consideration in the literature.

From the fact that two things are incommensurable i.e., lack a common unit of measurement, it does not follow that they are incomparable. It is possible to correctly judge that one thing is better than the other while it being impossible to measure how much better it is. However, when there is incomparability there is also incommensurability. If no positive value relation holds between two things, then they cannot be placed on the same cardinal scale.

While both incommensurability and incomparability are important concepts, much of the recent research has focused on the more specific possibility of incomparable value bearers. Different competing accounts have been given for examples that seem to point to the possibility of things being incomparable. These examples often take the form similar to that of Joseph Raz’s example in which a person faces the choice between two successful careers: one as a lawyer and one as a clarinetist. Neither career seems better than the other, and they also do not appear to be equally good. If they were of equal value, then a slightly improved version of the legal career would be better than the musical career, but this judgment appears incorrect (Raz 1986, 332).

The focus on incomparability can be motived by its possible significance for rational choice. Comparing alternatives are central for rational choice, we want to know what alternative is the best, and thus examples of incomparability are taken to be a threat to rational decision-making. Incommensurability on the other hand is mostly of theoretical interest. The possibility of incommensurable values introduces restrictions for normative theories, in the sense that they should not assume that all values can be represented on the same cardinal scale. The focus on incomparability can thus be justified by referring to its relation to practical reason and rational choice.

The remainder of section 1 considers proposed ways in which to conceive of value incommensurability.

1.3 Conceptions of Value Incommensurability

This section outlines three conceptions of value incommensurability, each one capturing some sense in which incommensurability is due to the lack of a common measure.

The first conception characterizes value incommensurability in terms of restrictions on how the further realization of one value outranks realization of another value. James Griffin has proposed forms of value incommensurability of this sort. One form involves what he calls “trumping.” In a conflict between values A and B, A is said to trump B if “any amount of A, no matter how small, is more valuable than any amount of B, no matter how large” (Griffin 1986, 83). A weaker form of value incommensurability involves what Griffin calls “discontinuity.” Two values, A and B, are incommensurable in this sense if “so long as we have enough of B any amount of A outranks any further amount of B; or that enough of A outranks any amount of B” (Griffin 1986, 85).

If values are incommensurable in this first sense, there is no ambiguity whether the realization of one value outranks realization of the other. Ambiguity as to whether the realization of one value outranks realization of the other, however, is thought by many theorists to be a central feature of incommensurable values. The second and third conceptions of value incommensurability aim to capture this feature.

According to the second conception, values are incommensurable if and only if there is no true general overall ranking of the realization of one value against the realization of the other value. David Wiggins, for example, puts this forward as one conception of value incommensurability. He writes that two values are incommensurable if “there is no general way in which A and B trade off in the whole range of situations of choice and comparison in which they figure” (1997, 59).

This second conception of value incommensurability denies what Henry Richardson calls “strong commensurability” (1994, 104–105). Strong commensurability is the thesis that there is a true ranking of the realization of one value against the realization of the other value in terms of one common value across all conflicts of value. A denial of such a singular common value, however, does not rule out what Richardson calls “weak commensurability” (1994, 105). Weak commensurability is the thesis that in any given conflict of values, there is a true ranking of the realization of one value against the realization of the other value in terms of some value. This value may be one of the values in question or some independent value. This value also may differ across value conflicts. The denial of strong commensurability does not entail a denial of weak commensurability. Even if there is no systematic or general way to resolve any given conflict of values, there may be some value in virtue of which the realization of one value ranks against realization of the other. Donald Regan defends the thesis of strong commensurability (Regan 1997).

The third conception of value incommensurability denies both strong and weak commensurability (Richardson 1994, Wiggins 1997, Williams 1981). This conception claims that in some conflicts of values, there is no true ranking of values.

This third conception of value incommensurability is sometimes said to be necessary to explain why, in conflicts of value, a gain in one value does not always cancel the loss in another value. This view assumes that, whenever there is a true ranking between the realization of one value and the realization of another value, the gain in one of the values cancels the loss in the other. Many commentators question that assumption. This entry leaves open the possibility that when there is a true ranking between the realization of one value and the realization of another value, the gain in one of the two values need not cancel the loss in the other.

If we accept this possibility, a number of questions arise. One question is what a ranking of realizations of values means if a gain in one value does not cancel the loss in the other. A second question is whether the first and second conceptions of value incommensurability each admit of two versions: one version in which the gain in one value cancels the loss of the other and one version in which it does not. A third question concerns the relation between value incommensurability and tragedy. It may be thought that what makes a choice tragic is that, no matter which alternative is chosen, the gain in value cannot cancel the loss in the other value. Not all authors, however, regard all value conflicts involving incommensurable values as tragic (Richardson 1994, 117). Wiggins, for example, reserves the second conception of value incommensurability for what he calls “common or garden variety incommensurable” choices and the third conception for what he calls “circumstantially cum tragically incommensurable” choices (1997, 64).

2. Incomparability

Rather than focus on commensurability between abstract values, recent research focuses on the incomparability between concrete bearers of value, often in the context of choice (Broome 1997, 2000; Chang 1997, 2002; Griffin 1986; Raz 1986). Bearers of value sometimes appear incomparable in cases like Joseph Raz’s example of the choice between careers (described above in subsection 1.2).

The case for incomparability in such examples relies in part on what Ruth Chang calls the “Small Improvement Argument” (Chang 2002b, 667). As noted in the initial discussion of the example, if the legal and musical careers were of equal value, then a slightly improved version of the legal career would be better than the musical career, but this judgment appears incorrect. The Small Improvement Argument takes the following general form: “if (1) A is neither better nor worse than B (with respect to V), (2) A+ is better than A (with respect to V), (3) A+ is not better than B (with respect to V), then (4) A and B are not related by any of the standard trichotomy of relations (relativized to V)” where V represents the relevant set of considerations for purposes of the comparison (Chang 2002b, 667–668). In addition to Raz, Derek Parfit and Walter Sinnott-Armstrong are among those who have advanced the Small Improvement Argument (Parfit 1984; Sinnott-Armstrong 1985). A similar argument, but for preference relations has, however, a longer history. Leonard J. Savage hints towards this possibility already 1954, in 1958 R. Duncan Luce presents a version of the argument that he attributes to Howard Raiffa, and it is also discussed by Ronald de Sousa in 1974 (Savage 1954; Luce 1958; de Sousa 1974).

Focusing on the incomparability of bearers of value has given rise to two lines of inquiry in the literature. The first concerns the relation between incomparability and vagueness; some argue that alleged examples of incomparability are better understood in terms of vagueness. The second concerns the range of comparative relations that can hold between two items; some argue that the Small Improvement Argument does not establish incomparability but rather that there are more value relations than previously believed. This section summarizes debate within each line of inquiry.

2.1 Vagueness

Raz distinguishes incomparability from what he calls the “indeterminacy” of value. Recall that Raz defines two bearers of value as incomparable if and only if it is not true that “either one is better than the other or they are of equal value.” The indeterminacy of value is a case of vagueness: it is neither true nor false of two items that “either one is better than the other or they are of equal value.” Raz regards the indeterminacy of value to result from the “general indeterminacy of language” (1986, 324).

In contrast, other philosophers argue for interpreting alleged examples of incomparability as vagueness (Griffin 1986, 96; Broome 1997, 2000; Andersson 2017; Elson 2017; Dos Santos 2019). Some have argued that the Small Improvement Argument fails to rule out the possibility that it is indeterminate how the value bearers relate; they may be related by one of the standard trichotomous relations, but it could be indeterminate which (Wasserman 2004; Klockseim 2010; Gustafsson 2013).

There are also more positive arguments in favor of the vagueness interpretation. For example, Broome introduces what he calls a “standard configuration” (1997, 96; 2000, 23). Imagine the musical and legal careers from Raz’s example. Fix the musical career as the “standard.” Now imagine variations in the legal career arranged in a line such that in one direction, the variations are increasingly better than the standard and in the other direction, the standard is increasingly better than the variations. There is an intermediate zone of legal careers that are not better than the standard and such that the standard is not better than the legal careers. If this zone contains one item, Broome defines this legal career to be equally good with the standard. If this zone contains more than one item, the zone is either one of “hard indeterminacy” or one of “soft indeterminacy.” A zone cannot be both one of hard indeterminacy and one of soft indeterminacy. In a zone of hard indeterminacy, it is false that the legal careers are better than the standard and false that the standard is better than the legal careers (1997, 73, 76). In a zone of soft indeterminacy, it is neither true nor false that the legal careers are better than the standard and neither true nor false that the standard is better than the legal careers (1997, 76). The latter is a zone of vagueness. Broome argues that indeterminate comparatives, including “better than” are softly indeterminate, thus there is no hard indeterminacy and no room for the possibility suggested by the Small Improvement Argument.

By understanding incomparability to entail vagueness, Broome disagrees with Raz (Broome 2000, 30). Raz defines incomparability so that it is compatible with vagueness, but not so that it entails vagueness. Griffin also argues that incomparability entails vagueness (1986, 96). Where Broome disagrees with Griffin is with regard to the width and significance of the zone of soft indeterminacy. Broome takes Griffin to suggest that if there is a zone of soft indeterminacy, it is narrow and unimportant. Broome argues that vagueness need not imply either narrowness or lack of importance (2000, 30–31).

Central to Broome’s argument is his controversial “collapsing principle” for comparatives: For any x and y, if it is false that y is Fer than x and not false that x is Fer than y, then it is true that x is Fer than y (1997, 74). Many counterexamples have been presented to show the implausibility of the principle (Carlson 2004, 2013; Elson 2014b; Gustafsson 2018). While there are attempts to defend the collapsing principle, or versions of it, (Constantinescu 2012; Andersson & Herlitz 2018) the counterexamples make Broome’s argument less convincing. Another line of argument has consequently been developed in defense of the vagueness interpretation. It is argued that the vagueness interpretation is theoretically parsimonious since it is natural to accept the existence of evaluative vagueness and if it can effortlessly account for alleged examples of incomparability then there is no reason to accept the more mysterious notion of incomparability or to introduce more value relations beyond the standard trichotomous relations (Andersson 2017; Elson 2017).

2.2 “Roughly Equal” and “On a Par”

The second line of inquiry concerns the set of possible comparative relations that can obtain between two items. The small improvement argument for the incomparability of the musical career and the legal career in Raz’s example assumes what Chang calls the “trichotomy thesis.” The trichotomy thesis holds that if two items can be compared in terms of some value or set of values, then the two items are related by one of the standard trichotomy of comparative relations, “better than,” “worse than,” or “equally good” (2002b, 660). A number of authors have argued that these three comparative relations do not exhaust the space of comparative relations. If they are correct, the musical career and the legal career may, in fact, be comparable.

James Griffin and Derek Parfit argue that items may in fact be “roughly equal” and hence comparable (Griffin 1986, 80–81, 96–98, and 104; 1997, 38–39; 2000, 285–289; Parfit 1987, 431). As an illustration, Parfit imagines comparing two poets and a novelist for a literary prize (1987, 431). Neither the First Poet nor the Novelist is worse than the other and the Second Poet is slightly better than the First Poet. If the First Poet and the Novelist were equally good, it would follow that the Second Poet is better than the Novelist. This judgment, according to Parfit, need not follow. Instead, the First Poet and the Novelist may be roughly equal. The intuition is that even though three items display the respects in virtue of which the comparisons are made, some comparisons are inherently rough so that even though two alternatives are not worse than one other, they are not equally good. In turn, the musical and legal careers in Raz’s example may be roughly equal. Parfit later referred to this possibility as there being “evaluative imprecision” (Parfit 2016, 113).

“Roughly equal,” as used here, is to be distinguished from two other ways in which the term has been used: (1) to refer to a small difference in value between two items and (2) to refer to a choice of little significance (Raz 1986, 333). As used here, two items A and B are said to be roughly equal if neither is worse than the other and C’s being better than B does not imply that C is better than A when the comparisons are all in virtue of the same set of respects.

There is some debate as to whether “roughly equal” is in fact a fourth comparative relation to be considered in addition to the three standard relations, “better than,” “worse than,” and “equally good.” One way to conceive of “roughly equal” is as a “roughed up” version of “equally good.” On this interpretation, the trichotomy thesis basically holds; there are simply precise and rough versions (Chang 2002b, 661, fn. 5). Furthermore, “roughly equal” is a relation that can be defined only in virtue of three items, and as such, appears to be something distinct from a standard comparative relation. The standard comparative relations are binary; transitivity with respect to them is a separate condition (Hsieh 2005, 195).

A separate proposal for a genuine fourth relationship is Ruth Chang’s argument for “on a par” (Chang 1997; Chang 2002b). Two items are said to be on a par if neither is better than the other, their differences preclude their being equally good, and yet they are comparable. Whereas “roughly equal” is invoked to allow for comparability among alternatives that display the same respects (e.g., literary merit), “on a par” is invoked to allow for comparability between alternatives that are different in the respects that they display. Imagine comparing Mozart and Michelangelo in terms of creativity. According to Chang, neither Mozart nor Michelangelo is less creative than the other. Because the two artists display creativity in such different fields, however, it would be mistaken to judge them to be equally creative. Nevertheless, according to Chang, they are comparable with respect to creativity. Something can be said about their relative merits with respect to the same consideration. According to Chang, they are on a par.

Chang’s argument relies on invoking a continuum that resembles Broome’s standard configuration. Chang asks us to imagine a sequence of sculptors who are successively worse than Michelangelo until we arrive at a sculptor who is clearly worse than Mozart in terms of creativity. Chang then brings to bear the intuition that “between two evaluatively very different items, a small unidimensional difference cannot trigger incomparability where before there was comparability” (2002b, 673). In the light of this intuition, because Mozart is comparable to this bad sculptor, Mozart is also comparable to each of the sculptors in the sequence, including Michelangelo. The soundness of this so-called Chaining Argument has, however, been questioned (Boot 2009; Elson 2014a; Andersson 2016a).

Whether “roughly equal” or “on a par” imply comparability is a matter of some debate. “Roughly equal” and “on a par,” for example, are intransitive, so to recognize them as distinct comparative relations would require us to reconsider the transitivity of comparative relations (Hsieh 2007). Some authors suggest that one of the three standard comparative relations obtains between all items that are claimed to be incomparable, roughly equal, or on a par (Regan 1997). In the case of “on a par,” Joshua Gert and Erik Carlson have argued that it can be defined in terms of the three standard comparative relations (Gert 2004; 2015; Carlson 2010). Gert’s suggestion is developed further by Wlodek Rabinowicz who provides a Fitting Attitudes account of value relations (Rabinowicz 2008; 2012). The Fitting Attitudes account typically analyzes goodness in terms of a normative component and an attitudinal component. By acknowledging that there can be two levels of normativity, requirement and permissibility, the account leaves room for both parity and standard value relations. X is better than Y if and only if it is rationally required to prefer X to Y, and X and Y are on a par if and only if it is rationally permissible to prefer X to Y and also rationally permissible to prefer Y to X. Interestingly, preferences and the lack of preferences together with the two levels of normativity can be combined in 15 different ways. This means that the fitting attitudes analysis provides the conceptual space for 15 possible value relations.

Another view is that values can be “clumpy,” meaning that the values sort items into clumps. According to this view, once we recognize the way in which the relation “equally good” functions in the context of clumpy values, items that appear to require “roughly equal” or “on a par” can be judged equally good (Hsieh 2005).

3. Arguments for Value Incommensurability and Incomparability

While recent research has focused on value incomparability and how to interpret examples that have the structure described by the Small Improvement Argument, earlier research had less focus on the structure of value but focused more on substantial consideration that talks in favor of incomparability. In this section, such considerations will be discussed.

First, a note on terminology. Most of the arguments discuss something that is similar to the phenomenon of incomparability but refer to the phenomenon in terms of “incommensurability”. In this section, the terminology of the discussed authors will be respected, and thus “incommensurability” will sometimes be used, even though, the authors possibly refer to the phenomenon of incomparability.

It should be noted that value pluralism seems central for the possibility of incomparability. After all, the most direct argument against the possibility that values are incommensurable or incomparable is based on value monism (e.g., Mill 1861 [1979] and Sidgwick 1874 [1981]). Donald Regan, for example, argues that “given any two items (objects, experiences, states of affairs, whatever) sufficiently well specified so that it is apposite to inquire into their (intrinsic) value in the Moorean sense, then either one is better than the other, or the two are precisely equal in value” (Regan 1997, 129).

This argument has been questioned. As Ruth Chang points out, by referring to John Stuart Mill, that values may have both qualitative and quantitative aspects could in principle allow for value bearers to be incomparable due to a difference in their qualitative features. (Chang 1997b, 16–17).

For purposes of this entry, it will not be assumed that value monism rules out incomparability. In any case, many philosophers argue for some form of value pluralism (Berlin 1969, Finnis 1981, Nagel 1979, Raz 1986, Stocker 1990, Taylor 1982, Williams 1981). Although this entry will not assume value pluralism, most philosophers who argue for incommensurability or incomparability are value pluralists, so it will be simpler to present their views by talking of separate values.

3.1 Constitutive Incommensurability

It has been argued that value incomparability is constitutive of certain goods and values and consequently we should assume its existence. Two versions of this second argument will be discussed here.

One version of this argument comes from Joseph Raz. Consider being offered a significant amount of money to leave one’s spouse for a month. The indignation that is typically experienced in response to such an offer, according to Raz, is grounded in part in the symbolic significance of certain actions (1986, 349). In this case, “what has symbolic significance is the very judgment that companionship is incommensurable with money” (1986, 350). Although this form of value incommensurability looks like trumping, Raz does not see this as a case of trumping. He rejects the view that companionship is more valuable than money. If such a view were correct, then those who forgo companionship for money would be acting against reason (1986, 352). Instead, Raz takes the view that a “belief in incommensurability is itself a qualification for having certain relations” (1986, 351). Someone who does not regard companionship and money as incommensurable simply has chosen a kind of life that may be fulfilling in many ways, but being capable of having companionship is not one of them.

In Raz’s account, the symbolic significance of judging money to be incommensurable with companionship involves the existence of a social convention that determines participation in that convention (e.g., marriage) that requires a belief in value incommensurability. This conventional nature of belief in value incommensurability in Raz’s account raises a question for some authors about its robustness as an account of value incommensurability. For example, Chang objects that incommensurability appears to become relative to one’s participation in social conventions (2001, 48). It remains an open question how much of a problem this point raises. Raz’s account appears to illustrate a basic sense in which the values of money and companionship can be incommensurable. Insofar as it is not against reason to choose money over companionship, there is no general way to resolve a conflict of values between money and companionship. In Raz’s account, the resolution depends upon which social convention one has chosen to pursue.

Elizabeth Anderson advances a second argument for constitutive incommensurability. Her account is grounded in a pragmatic account of value. Anderson reduces “‘x is good’ roughly to ‘it is rational to value x,’ where to value something is to adopt toward it a favorable attitude susceptible to rational reflection” (1997, 95). She argues that in virtue of these attitudes there may be no good reason to compare the overall values of two goods. Pragmatism holds that if such a comparison serves no practical function, then the comparative value judgment has no truth value, meaning that the goods are incommensurable (1997, 99). Because the favorable attitudes one adopts toward goods help to make them good, Anderson’s account can be seen as an argument for constitutive incommensurability (Chang 2001, 49).

Anderson advances three ways in which there may be no good reason to compare the overall values of goods. First, it may be boring or pointless to engage in comparison. To illustrate, “the project of comprehensively ranking all works of art in terms of their intrinsic aesthetic value is foolish, boring, and stultifying” (1997, 100). Second, Anderson points to instances in which “it makes sense to leave room for the free play of nonrational motivations like whims and moods” as in the choice of what to do on a leisurely Sunday afternoon (1997, 91). Third, Anderson argues that the roles that goods play in deliberation can be so different that “attempts to compare them head to head are incoherent” (1997, 91). Imagine that the only way to save one’s dying mother is to give up a friendship. Rather than compare their overall values, argues Anderson, ordinary moral thinking focuses on what one owes to one’s mother and one’s friends (1997, 102). This focus on obligation recognizes mother and friend each to be intrinsically valuable and yet valuable in different ways (1997, 103). There is no good reason, according to Anderson, to compare their overall values with regard to some common measure.

Chang argues against each of the three points raised by Anderson (Chang 2001). In response to the first point, Chang notes there are occasions in which comparisons do need to be made between goods for which Anderson argues there is no good reason to make comparisons. In response to the second point, Chang argues that the range of instances for which the second argument applies is small. In response to the third point, Chang contends that Anderson’s argument assumes that if goods are comparable then they have some value or evaluative property in common. Chang points out that this need not be the case.

3.2 Moral Dilemmas

Both value incommensurability and incomparability have been invoked to make sense of a central feature of supposed moral dilemmas—namely, that no matter which alternative the agent chooses, she fails to do something she ought to do. The apparent value conflicts involved in these choices have led some philosophers to relate moral dilemmas to the incomparability or incommensurability of values. Henry Richardson, for example, takes the situation confronting Sophie in the novel Sophie’s Choice—that one of her two children will be spared death, but only if she chooses which one to save—to point to the incommensurability of values (1994, 115–117).

It has been argued that the mere fact of a moral dilemma does not imply incomparability. James Griffin, for example, argues that the feature of “irreplaceability” in moral dilemmas often may be mistaken as evidence for incomparability (1997, 37). Irreplaceability is the feature that what is lost in choosing one alternative over another cannot be replaced by what is gained in choosing another alternative. Although a conflict of values displays this feature, not all instances of irreplaceability need involve plural values. Some moral dilemmas, for example, may involve not a conflict of values, but a conflict of obligations that arises from the same consideration. Consider forced choices in saving lives. If there is a dilemma, it need not involve conflicting values, but rather conflicting obligations that arise from the same consideration. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong calls such dilemmas “symmetrical” (1988, 54–58). The dilemma encountering Sophie, it may be said, does not point to the incommensurability of values.

Richardson acknowledges that the moral considerations underlying Sophie’s dilemma are not incommensurable. Nonetheless, he takes value incommensurability to be essential to understanding the tragedy of the dilemma that Sophie encounters. “It is a distinguishing feature of love, including parental love,” he writes, “that it cherishes the particular and unique features of the beloved” (115). He concludes, “the fact that she cannot adequately represent each child’s value on a single scale is what makes the choosing tragic” (116). By locating the incommensurability of values at the level of what is valuable about each of her children, Richardson argues that the tragedy of the dilemma points to incomparability.

Another common approach to argue for value incommensurability is with reference to “non-symmetrical” dilemmas. As the name suggests, in non-symmetrical dilemmas, the alternatives are favored by different values (Sinnott-Armstrong 1988). If these values are incommensurable in the third sense as discussed in subsection 1.3, there is no systematic resolution of the value conflict. Consider Jean-Paul Sartre’s well-known example of his pupil who faced the choice between going to England to join the Free French Forces and staying at home to help his mother live (Sartre 1975, 295–296). No matter which alternative he chooses, certain values will remain unrealized. An idea along these lines is considered, for example, by Walter Sinnott-Armstrong (1988, 69–71) and Bernard Williams (1981, 74–78) in their discussions of moral dilemmas.

3.3 Akrasia

Value incommensurability also features in debates about akrasia (Nussbaum 2001, 113–117). David Wiggins, for example, invokes the idea of value incommensurability to suggest “the heterogeneity of the psychic sources of desire satisfaction and of evaluation” (1998, 266). This heterogeneity, according to Wiggins, allows for a coherent account of the agent’s attraction to what is not best. It allows for a divergence between desire and value such that the akratic individual can be attracted to a value that should not be sought at that point in time. Wiggins invokes value incommensurability to capture the idea that a gain in the value that should not be sought does not reduce the loss in choosing what is not best.

In contrast, Michael Stocker denies that value incommensurability is required for a coherent account of akrasia (1990, 214–240). For Stocker, coherent akrasia is possible with a single value in just the way that it is possible to be attracted to two objects that differ with respect to the same value (e.g., “a languorous lesser pleasure and a piquant better pleasure” (1990, 230)). Recall the discussion of quantitative and qualitative aspects of a single value at the outset of section 3.

4. Deliberation and Choice

As suggested above much of the inquiry into value incomparability is motivated more generally by theories of practical reason and rational choice. Even if a conception of justified choice can accommodate value incomparability, questions remain about how to justify choice on the basis of incomparability and how to reason about incomparability. This section considers these issues as they have been discussed in the contemporary philosophical literature.

It is worth noting the potential for drawing connections between the philosophical literature and the literature in psychology and the social sciences on decision-making. One area for such potential is the psychological literature on the difficulty of making decisions (Yates, Veinott, and Patalano 2003). Jane Beattie and Sema Barlas (2001), for example, advance the thesis that the observed variation in the difficulty of making trade-offs between alternatives can be explained in part by the category to which the alternatives belong. The authors consider three categories: commodities (“objects that are appropriately bought and sold in markets”), currencies (“objects that act as stand-ins for commodities”), and noncommodities (“objects that either cannot be transferred (e.g., pain) or that lose some of their value by being traded in markets (e.g., friendship)”) (Beattie and Barlas 2001, 30). The authors’ experimental findings are consistent with participants holding normative commitments about exchanging currencies and noncommodities similar to those considered in the discussion of constitutive incommensurability in subsection 3.2. For example, Beattie and Barlas report that participants “had a significant tendency to choose noncommodities over commodities and currencies” and that choices between noncommodities and currencies were the easiest for participants (2001, 50–51). The authors interpret these results to support the view that people choose noncommodities over currencies on the basis of a rule without engaging in a calculation of trade-offs (2001, 51–53). In the context of empirical research, it should also be noted that philosophers have contributed with empirical research on the characterization of hard choices (Messerli and Reuter 2017a, 2017b).

4.1 Optimization and Maximization

At a minimum, for the choice of an alternative to qualify as justified, there must not be an overriding reason against choosing it. Beyond that, conceptions of justified choice differ in what is required for the choice of an alternative to qualify as justified.

Ruth Chang defines “comparativism” as the view that “comparative facts are what make a choice objectively correct; they are that in virtue of which a choice is objectively rational or what one has most or sufficient normative reason to do. So, whether you are a consequentialist, deontologist, virtue theorist, perfectionist, contractualist, etc., about the grounds of rational choice, you should be, first and foremost, I suggest, a comparativist” (2016, 213). If alternatives are incomparable, then the lack of a comparative fact precludes the possibility of justified choice.

One response has been to argue that apparently incomparable alternatives are, in fact, comparable. As discussed in subsection 2.2, judgments of incomparability frequently involve comparisons that are difficult and it may be that judgments of incomparability are mistaken (Regan 1997) or that, due to vagueness, it is indeterminate which value relation holds. In addition, as discussed, alternatives that appear incomparable by way of “better than,” “worse than,” or “equally good” may be comparable by way of some fourth comparative relation, such as “roughly equal” or “on a par.” This means that there is a comparative fact that makes a choice objectively correct in cases of apparent incomparability. It does not, however, help us identify the objectively correct alternative.

A common form of comparativism is optimization. According to optimization, the fact that an alternative is at least as good as the other alternatives is what justifies its choice. Consequently, if two alternatives are incomparable no justified choice can be made between them. Another line of response, one from within the economics literature, has been to distinguish between “optimization” and “maximization” as theories of justified choice (Sen 1997, 746; Sen 2000, 486). The theory of maximization as justified choice only requires the choice of an alternative that is not worse than other alternatives. Because incomparable alternatives are not worse than one another, the choice of either is justified according to the theory of maximization as justified choice. Maximization is thus a rejection of comparativism. However, Hsieh (2007) argues that proponents of comparativism have no reason to reject maximization as an account of justified choice and consequently incomparability need not pose a problem for the possibility of justified choice.

4.2 Cyclical Choice

One objection voiced against accounts that permit justified choice between alternatives that are roughly equal or on a par or between incomparable alternatives is that such accounts may justify a series of choices that leaves a person worse off. Consider Raz’s example of career choice. Suppose the person chooses the musical career over the legal career. At a future time, she has the opportunity to pursue a legal career that is slightly worse than the initial legal career. Suppose this slightly worse legal career and the musical career are judged roughly equal or on a par. If justified choice permits her to choose either of two alternatives when they are roughly equal or on a par, then she would be justified in choosing the slightly worse legal career. Similarly, if justified choice does not require the comparability of alternatives, she could be justified in choosing the slightly worse legal career. Through a series of such apparently justified choices, she would be left significantly worse off in a manner analogous to a “money pump” (Chang 1997, 11).

One response is to question whether the problem posed by choices of this sort is serious. John Broome, for example, notes that after having chosen one kind of career, a person may change her mind and choose the kind of career she previously rejected. According to Broome, there would be a puzzle only if she did not repudiate her previous choice (2000, 34).

Another line of response is that the considerations that make some alternatives worthy of choice count against the constant switching among alternatives envisioned in this objection. First, the constant switching among alternatives is akin to not choosing an alternative. If the alternatives are such that choosing either is better than choosing neither, then the considerations that make the alternatives worthy of choice count against constantly switching among them. Second, to switch constantly among careers appears to misunderstand what makes the alternatives worthy of choice. Not only is pursuing a career the kind of activity that depends upon continued engagement for its success, but it is also the kind of activity that is unlikely to be judged truly successful unless one demonstrates some commitment to it. Third, for a career to be considered successful, it may require the chooser to adopt a favorable attitude toward the considerations that favor it over other careers. In turn, when subsequently presented with the choice of a legal career, the considerations favoring it may no longer apply to her in the same way as they did before (Hsieh 2007).

Ruth Chang advances a hybrid view on rational choice to meet the challenge of cyclical choice. She distinguishes “given reasons” from “will-based” reasons. Roughly put, given reasons could here be understood as those that are grounded in normative facts while will-based reasons are “reasons in virtue of some act of the will; they are a matter of our creation. They are voluntarist in their normative source. In short, we create will-based reasons and receive given ones.” (Chang 2013, 177). Will-based reasons come into play when the given reasons no longer can guide our actions. When two alternatives are on a par, given reasons fail to guide us and at this stage, will-based reasons can provide guidance and guarantee that the agent commits to her choice. Anders Herlitz (2019) argues that Chang’s approach and other “two-step models” violate an intuitively plausible constraint on rational choice called Basic Contraction Consistency. By violating this constraint two-step models also allow for money pumps. This could, however, possibly be avoided by introducing additional formal conditions for the second step in the model (Herlitz 2019, 299–307).

4.3 Rational Eligibility

The idea expressed in the distinction between optimization and maximization in subsection 4.1 can be expressed more generally in terms of the idea of rational eligibility. To say that an alternative is rationally eligible is to mean that choosing it would not be an unjustified choice. Which alternatives are judged rationally eligible may vary with the theory of justified choice. According to maximization as a theory of justified choice, an alternative is rationally eligible if and only if there is no better alternative.

Isaac Levi (1986; 2004) argues for “v-admissibility” as a criterion of justified choice. For v-admissibility, value incomparability does not pose a problem for the possibility of justified choice. An alternative is v-admissible if and only if it is optimal according to at least one of the relevant considerations at hand. In some conflicts of value, maximization and v-admissibility specify the same alternatives as rationally eligible. Suppose that alternative X is better than alternative Y with respect to consideration A and alternative Y is better than alternative X with respect to consideration B. According to maximization as a theory of justified choice, both X and Y are rationally eligible; neither alternative is better than the other with respect to A and B taken together. Both alternatives are also rationally eligible according to v-admissibility; X is optimal with respect to A and Y is optimal with respect to B.

In some conflicts of value, maximization and v-admissibility specify different sets of alternatives as rationally eligible. V-admissibility is more restrictive than maximization (Levi 2004). Add to the above example alternative Z. Suppose that X is better than Z, which is better than Y, all with respect to A. Suppose also that Y is better than Z, which is better than X, all with respect to B. According to maximization as a theory of justified choice, X, Y, and Z are rationally eligible; no alternative is better than the other with respect to A and B taken together. However, Z is not rationally eligible according to v-admissibility. Z is not optimal with respect to A. Nor is it optimal with respect to B. Only X and Y are rationally eligible according to v-admissibility. According to Levi, v-admissibility captures what he takes to be a plausible judgment—namely, that it would be unjustified to choose the alternative that is second worse on all relevant respects (Levi 2004). The plausibility of this judgment might be questioned. Suppose that Z is only slightly worse than X with respect to A and Z is only slightly worse than Y with respect to B. Does the judgment still hold?

For Joseph Raz, incomparability also does not pose a problem for the possibility of justified choice (1997). If incomparable options give us reasons to choose both alternatives, they are both rationally eligible from the perspective of justified choice. As such, the choice of either alternative is justified on the basis of reason.

One question that arises is this. If an agent has reason to choose either alternative and they are not equally good, what makes her choice of one alternative over another intelligible to her? For Raz, what explains the choice of one alternative over the other is the exercise of the will. By the will, Raz has in mind “the ability to choose and perform intentional actions” and “the most typical exercise or manifestation of the will is in choosing among options that reason merely renders eligible” (1997, 111).

John Finnis advances a similar view in response to the question of intelligibility. Finnis writes, “in free choice, one has reasons for each of the alternative options, but these reasons are not causally determinative.… No factor but the choosing itself settles which alternative is chosen” (1997, 220). In a choice between alternatives each favored by different, incomparable values, even though there are reasons to choose both alternatives, because reasons are not causally determinative, the lack of a reason to choose one alternative over another need not render the choice unintelligible.

Donald Regan challenges this view. According to Regan, unless grounded in an adequate reason, “a decision to go one way rather than another will be something that happened to the agent rather than something she did” and hence be unintelligible to the agent herself (1997, 144). Suppose the agent has no more reason to choose one alternative over another and the choice, as suggested above, is settled by her wants. On Regan’s view, if the agent’s choice is to be intelligible to her, her wants must be grounded in reasons. Because she has no more reason to choose one alternative over another initially, the reasons grounding her wants must be available to her only after the initially relevant reasons are exhausted. This strikes Regan as implausible (1997, 150). Regan concludes that no choice between incomparable bearers of value is intelligible in the ways suggested by Raz or Finnis.

4.4 External Resources

A number of authors have argued that practical reason has available to it the resources to accommodate incomparability in ways that would appear to address the concern raised by Regan.

Charles Taylor outlines two such sets of resources. First, we are able to appeal to “constitutive goods that lie behind the life goods” our sense of which is “fleshed out, and passed on, in a whole range of media: stories, legends, portraits of exemplary figures and their actions and passions, as well as in artistic works, music, dance, ritual, modes of worship, and so on” (1997, 179). Second, we cannot escape the need to live an integrated life or to have this, at a minimum, as an aspiration (1997, 180). Given that a life is finite, leading a life involves an articulation of how different goods fit into it relative to one another. More generally, our lives take on a certain “shape” and this shape provides guidance in making choices in the face of incomparability (1997, 183). Michael Stocker similarly points out that alternatives are rarely considered in the abstract (1997). Instead, they are usually considered in concrete ways in which they are valuable—for example, as part of one’s life. Once considered in such concrete contexts, there are considerations according to which alternatives can be evaluated for purposes of justified choice. In his analysis of incommensurability, Fred D’Agostino discusses the role of social institutions in resolving value conflicts (2003).

Another resource that has been invoked is morality. Recall Elizabeth Anderson’s discussion of the example of the choice between saving the life of one’s mother and maintaining a close friendship. Anderson regards the attempt to invoke a comparison of values as incoherent from the perspective of practical reason. Instead, ordinary moral thinking focuses on the obligations one has to one’s mother and one’s friends. In turn, Anderson suggests that the obligations themselves will provide guidance (1997, 106). The availability of such resources to reason is independent of her theories of value and rationality. John Finnis also points to principles of morality as guiding reason which avoids comparability problems (1997). It remains an open question as to how wide a range of cases it is in which morality can provide such guidance.

One worry that may arise in appealing to such external resources is that they address the problem of incomparability by simply denying it. The shape of one’s life or the “constitutive goods that lie behind the life goods,” for example, would appear to be sources of value. Insofar as they provide a value against which to resolve the initial value conflict, it might be said that there was no problem of incomparability in the first place.

Two responses to this worry can be given. First, even if these external resources can ground comparisons, it does not follow that they provide a systematic resolution to value conflicts. Insofar as the shapes of people’s lives differ, the way in which two individuals resolve the same value conflict may be different. The fact that it may be consistent with reason to resolve the same value conflict in different ways points to the possibility of incomparability.

Second, in the case of moral considerations, there may not be any denial of incomparability. Moral considerations may provide guidance without comparing alternative courses of action (Finnis 1997, 225–226). Furthermore, some philosophers argue that the moral wrongness of certain actions is intelligible only in virtue of incomparability. For example, Alan Strudler argues that to deliberate about the permissibility of lying in terms of comparable options is to misunderstand the wrong in lying (1998, 1561–1564).

4.5 Non-Maximizing Choice

It would appear that conceptions of justified choice that do not rely on comparisons avoid the problems posed by incomparability. Stocker aims to provide one such account of justified choice (1990; 1997). Two features help to distinguish his account. First, he argues for evaluating alternatives as “the best” in an absolute, rather than a relative, sense. Optimization and maximization rely on choosing “the best” in a relative sense: given the relevant comparison class, there is no better alternative. To be “the best” in an absolute sense, an alternative “must be, of its kind, excellent—satisfying, or coming close to, ideals and standards” (1997, 206). This is the sense, for example, in which a person can be the best of friends even if we may have even better friends. More generally, an alternative can be absolutely best even if there are better alternatives, and even if an alternative is relatively best, it may not be absolutely best. The second distinctive feature of Stocker’s account is his appeal to a good life, for example, or part of a good life or project. This appeal does not require the alternative to be the best for that life or project. Instead, the alternative need only be good enough for that life or project to qualify as a justified choice.

Stocker’s account of justified choice differs from the concept of “satisficing” as used in the economics and rational choice literature. Introduced into the economics literature by Herbert Simon (1955), satisficing is the process of choosing in which it is rational to stop seeking alternatives when the agent finds one that is “good enough” (Byron 2004). Where satisficing differs from Stocker’s account is that satisficing is instrumentally rational in virtue of a more general maximizing account of choice. In situations in which finding the best alternative is prohibitively costly or impossible, for example, satisficing becomes rational. In contrast, on Stocker’s account, choosing the alternative that is “good enough” is non-instrumentally rational (Stocker 2004).

Objections discussed in previous sections may be raised with respect to Stocker’s account. Suppose two alternatives are both good in an absolute sense and incomparable. According to Stocker’s account, insofar as both alternatives are good enough for an agent’s life, the choice of either alternative appears justified. As discussed in subsection 4.2, Regan and others may object that the choice of either alternative is not intelligible to the agent. Also, the appeal to a good life may raise the worry discussed in subsection 4.4 that Stocker’s account addresses the problem of incomparability by simply denying it.

4.6 Deliberation about Ends

The topics of value incommensurability and incomparability also arise in accounts that concern deliberation about ends. This section discusses two accounts.

The first account is by Henry Richardson (1994). Richardson argues for the possibility of rational deliberation about ends. According to Richardson, if comparability is a prerequisite for rational choice, choices involving conflicting values could be made rationally if each of the values were expressed in terms of their contribution to furthering some common end. This conception of choice treats this common end as the one final end relevant for the choice. According to Richardson, the idea that comparability is a prerequisite for rational choice seems to rule out rational deliberation about ends (1994, 15).

Richardson defends an account of rational deliberation about ends that does not depend upon comparability. In his account, rational deliberation involves achieving coherence among one’s ends. Briefly, coherence is “a matter of finding or constructing intelligible connections or links or mutual support among them and of removing relations of opposition or conflict” (Richardson 1994, 144). For Richardson, coherence among ends need not result in their being comparable (1994, 180).

The second account is by Elijah Millgram (1997). Like Richardson, Millgram argues that comparability is not a prerequisite for deliberation. However, in contrast to Richardson, Millgram argues that practical deliberation results in the comparability of ends (1997, 151). By this he means that through deliberation, one develops a coherent conception of what matters and a “background against which one can judge not only that one consideration is more important than another, but how much more important” (1997, 163). For Millgram, comparing one’s ends is a “central part of attaining unified agency” (1997, 162).

Millgram proposes two ways in which deliberation results in the comparability of ends. The first proposal is that one can learn what is important and how it is important through experience (1997, 161). The second proposal is that deliberation about ends is “something like the construction by the agent of a conception of what matters … out of raw materials such as desires, ends, preferences, and reflexes” (1997, 168). Millgram identifies an objection to each proposal and briefly responds to each.

The objection to the first proposal is this. If the incomparability of ends can be resolved by experience, this suggests that the judgment of incomparability reflects incomplete knowledge about the values expressed in these ends. In other words, experience seems to help only if the values expressed in these ends are themselves comparable (1997, 168). Millgram responds as follows. The agent who uses her experience to develop a coherent conception of what matters is like the painter who uses her experience to paint a picture that is not a copy of an existing image. Even if the ends are comparable in her conception of what matters, the values they reflect need not be comparable just as the painting need not be an exact copy of an existing image.

The objection to the second proposal is this. The second proposal suggests that deliberation is not driven by experience, which places it in tension with the first proposal. Millgram responds by continuing the analogy with the painter. Imagine a painter who paints a picture that is not a copy of an existing image. Just because the painting is not a copy of an existing image does not mean there is no source of correction and constraint on it. Similarly, deliberation may involve the construction by the agent of a conception of what matters, but this does not imply that it is not informed or constrained by experience (1997, 168–169).

4.7 Risky Actions

Caspar Hare (2010) introduces and discusses a problem relating to how rational choice theory can encompass risky actions involving outcomes that are on a par. If we assume that two outcomes, A and B, are on a par, it follows that a small improvement, or mild sweetening as Hare phrases it, to one of the outcomes would not break the parity relation. We can imagine two actions, X and Y. If we opt for X then we will either end up with a sweetened A in state 1 or a sweetened B in state 2, and the outcomes are equiprobable. If we opt for Y, we will end up with B in state 1 or A in state 2, and the outcomes are equiprobable. On the one hand, it seems as if we ought to opt for X since we will end up with a sweetened alternative, A+ or B+. On the other hand, it is difficult to say why X is better than Y. The outcome in state 1 is not better if we do X rather than Y since the outcomes, A+ and B, are on a par, and the outcome in state 2 is not better if we do Y rather than X since the outcomes, B+ and A, are on a par. The problem can be construed as a lottery where one lottery is deemed comparable with another, yet their outcomes are incomparable (see Rabinowicz, 2021b, for this axiological formulation of Hare’s problem). Hare argues that we should “take the sugar”, i.e., we ought to opt for X (see also Bader 2019). Inspired by a Fitting-Attitudes Analysis of value Wlodek Rabinowicz argues that even though outcomes may be on a par, it is possible for an action to be better than another (2021b). Others such as Schoenfield (2014), Bales, Cohen & Handfield (2014), and Doody (2019) reach the opposite conclusion.

5. Social Choices and Institutions

As discussed above, social practices and institutions play a role in the inquiry into value incommensurability and incomparability. They are claimed by some philosophers to ground the possibility of these phenomena as in the case of constitutive incommensurability (subsection 3.2), and to help resolve value conflicts, as in the case of providing external resources for practical reason (subsection 4.4). This section discusses additional areas in which considerations about social institutions intersect with the inquiry at hand.

To begin, some philosophers have pointed to a structural similarity between a single individual trying to choose in the face of incomparability and the process of incorporating the varied interests and preferences of the members of society into a single decision. The preferences of different individuals, for example, may be taken to reflect differing evaluative judgments about alternatives so that combining these different preferences into a single decision becomes analogous to resolving value conflicts in the individual case. Given this analogy, Fred D’Agostino has applied methods of decision-making at the social level from social choice theory and political theory to consider the resolution of value conflicts at the individual level (2003).

At the same time, Richard Pildes and Elizabeth Anderson caution against wholeheartedly adopting this analogy. The analogy, according to them, assumes that individuals already have rationally ordered preferences. Given incomparability, however, there is no reason to make such an assumption. In turn, Pildes and Anderson argue that “individuals need to participate actively in democratic institutions to enable them to achieve a rational ordering of their preferences for collective choices” (1990, 2177).

Value incommensurability and incomparability also have been considered with respect to the law. Matthew Adler discusses the variety of ways in which legal scholars have engaged the topic of value incommensurability (1998). One question is whether the possibility of value incommensurability poses a problem for evaluating government policy options and laws, more generally. Some authors respond that it does not. Cass Sunstein, for example, argues that recognition of value incommensurability helps “to reveal what is at stake in many areas of the law” (1994, 780). According to Sunstein, important commitments of a well-functioning legal system are reflected in recognizing value incommensurability.

More generally, a number of scholars have focused on the relation between incomparability and the structure of social and political institutions. John Finnis, for example, takes the open-endedness of social life to render it impossible to treat legal or policy choices as involving comparable alternatives (1997, 221–222). Michael Walzer’s account of distributive justice also relates incomparability to the structure of social and political institutions. According to Walzer (1983), different social goods occupy different “spheres,” each one governed by a distinct set of distributive norms. What is unjust is to convert the accumulation of goods in one sphere into the accumulation of goods in another sphere without regard for that second sphere’s distributive norms. Underlying Walzer’s account, it seems, is a commitment to a kind of constitutive incommensurability. Given its connection to the possibility of plural and incompatible ways of life, the concepts of value incommensurability and incomparability also play a role in many accounts of political liberalism, including Joseph Raz’s account (1986) and Isaiah Berlin’s account (1969). The latter’s inquiry into the relation between incommensurable values and political institutions motivated much of the further inquiry into the topic.

Bibliography

  • Adler, M., 1998, “Law and Incommensurability: Introduction,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 146: 1169–1184.
  • Anderson, E., 1993, Value in Ethics and Economics, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1997, “Practical Reason and Incommensurable Goods,” in Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, R. Chang (ed.), Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Andersson, H., 2015, “Propping Up the Collapsing Principle,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18 (3): 475–486.
  • –––, 2016a, “Parity and Comparability, a Concern Regarding Chang’s Chaining Argument,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 19 (1): 245–253.
  • –––, 2016b, “Vagueness and Goodness Simpliciter,” Ratio, 29 (4): 378–394.
  • –––, 2017, How it all relates: Exploring the space of value comparisons, Ph.D. dissertation, Lund University.
  • Andersson, H., & Herlitz, A., 2018, “A More Plausible Collapsing Principle,” Theoria, 84 (4): 325–336.
  • Andreou, C., 2015, “Parity, Comparability, and Choice,” Journal of Philosophy, 112 (1): 5–22.
  • Aristotle, 1984, Nicomachean Ethics, in The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, J. Barnes (ed.), Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Baumann, P. and M. Betzler (eds.), 2004, Practical Conflicts, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Bader, R. M., 2018, “Stochastic Dominance and Opaque Sweetening,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 96 (3): 498–507.
  • Bales, A., Cohen, D., & Handfield, T., 2014, “Decision Theory for Agents with Incomplete Preferences,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92 (3): 453–470.
  • Beattie, J. and S. Barlas, 2001, “Predicting Perceived Differences in Tradeoff Difficulty,” Conflict and Tradeoffs in Decision Making, E. Weber, J. Baron, and G. Loomes (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Berlin, I., 1969, “Two Concepts of Liberty,” in Four Essays on Liberty, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Boot, M., 2009, “Parity, Incomparability and Rationally Justified Choice,” Philosophical Studies, 146 (1): 75–92.
  • Broome, J., 1997, “Is Incommensurability Vagueness?” in Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, R. Chang (ed.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2000, “Incommensurable Values”, in Well-Being and Morality: Essays in Honour of James Griffin, R. Crisp and B. Hooker (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Burkert, W., 1972, Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism, translated by E. Minar, Jr., Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Byron, M., (ed.), 2004, Satisficing and Maximizing: Moral Theorists on Practical Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Carlson, E., 2004, “Broome’s Argument against Value Incomparability,” Utilitas, 16: 220–224.
  • –––, 2010, “Parity Demystified,” Theoria, 76 (2): 119–128.
  • –––, 2013, “Vagueness, Incomparability, and the Collapsing Principle,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 16 (3): 449–463.
  • Chan, D., 2010, “Reasoning Without Comparing,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 47 (2): 153–164.
  • Chang, R. (ed.), 1997a, Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1997b, “Introduction”, in Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, R. Chang (ed.), Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2001, “Against Constitutive Incommensurability or Buying and Selling Friends,” Philosophical Issues, 11: 33–60.
  • –––, 2002a, Making Comparisons Count, New York: Routledge.
  • –––, 2002b, “The Possibility of Parity,” Ethics, 112: 659–688.
  • –––, 2004, “Putting Together Morality and Well-Being,” in Practical Conflicts, P. Baumann and M. Betzler (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2005, “Parity, Interval Value, and Choice,” Ethics, 115: 331–350.
  • –––, 2012, “Are Hard Choices Cases of Incomparability?,” Philosophical Issues, 22 (1): 106–126.
  • –––, 2013, “Grounding Practical Normativity: Going Hybrid,” Philosophical Studies, 164 (1): 163–187.
  • –––, 2016, “Comparativism: The Ground of Rational Choice,” in Weighing Reasons, E. Lord and B. McGuire (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Constantinescu, C., 2012, “Value Incomparability and Indeterminacy,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 15 (1): 57–70.
  • Crisp, R. and B. Hooker, (eds.), 2000, Well-Being and Morality: Essays in Honour of James Griffin, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • D’Agostino, F., 2003, Incommensurability and Commensuration: The Common Denominator, Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing.
  • De Sousa, R., 1974, “The Good and the True,” Mind, 83: 534–551.
  • Doody, R., 2019, “Parity, Prospects, and Predominance,” Philosophical Studies, 176 (4): 1077–1095.
  • Dos Santos, M. F., 2020, “Superhard Choices,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 98 (2):248–265.
  • Ellis, S., 2008, “The Main Argument for Value Incommensurability (and Why It Fails),” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 46 (1): 27–43.
  • Elson, L., 2014a, “Heaps and Chains: Is the Chaining Argument for Parity a Sorites?,” Ethics, 124 (3): 557–571.
  • –––, 2014b, “Borderline Cases and the Collapsing Principle,” Utilitas, 26 (1): 51–60
  • –––, 2017, “Incommensurability as Vagueness: A Burden-Shifting Argument,” Theoria, 83 (4): 341–363.
  • Espinoza, N., 2008, “The Small Improvement Argument,” Synthese, 165 (1): 127–139.
  • Feyerabend, P., 1978, Science in a Free Society, London: New Left Books.
  • –––, 1981, Philosophical Papers (Volume 1), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1993, Against Method: Outline of an Anarchist Theory of Knowledge, third edition, London: Verso.
  • Finnis, J., 1980, Natural Law and Natural Rights, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 1997, “Commensuration and Public Reason,” in Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, R. Chang (ed.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Gert, J., 2004, “Value and Parity,” Ethics, 114: 492–510.
  • –––, 2015, “Parity, Preference and Puzzlement,” Theoria, 81 (3): 249–271.
  • Griffin, J., 1986, Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement and Importance, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 1991, “Mixing Values”, The Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary), 65: 101–118.
  • –––, 1997, “Incommensurability: What’s the Problem?” in Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, R. Chang (ed.), Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2000, “Replies”, in Well-Being and Morality: Essays in Honour of James Griffin, R. Crisp and B. Hooker (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Gustafsson, J., 2013, “Indeterminacy and the Small-Improvement Argument,” Utilitas, 25 (4): 433–445.
  • –––, 2018, “Does the Collapsing Principle Rule Out Borderline Cases?” Utilitas, 30 (4): 483–492.
  • Gustafsson, J. and Espinoza, N., 2010, “Conflicting Reasons in the Small-Improvement Argument,” Philosophical Quarterly, 60 (241): 754–763.
  • Halstead, J., 2015, “The Impotence of the Value Pump,” Utilitas, 27 (2): 195–216.
  • Hare, C., 2010, “Take the Sugar,” Analysis, 70 (2): 237–247.
  • Heath, T., 1921, A History of Greek Mathematics, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Herlitz, A., 2019, “Nondeterminacy, two-step models, and justified choice,” Ethics, 129 (2): 284–308.
  • Hsieh, N., 2005, “Equality, Clumpiness, and Incomparability,” Utilitas, 17: 180–204.
  • –––, 2007, “Is Incomparability a Problem for Anyone?” Economics and Philosophy, 23: 65–80.
  • Kelly, C. 2008, “The Impossibility of Incommensurable Values,” Philosophical Studies, 137 (3): 369–382.
  • Klocksiem, J., 2010, “In Defense of the Trichotomy Thesis,” Acta Analytica, 25 (3): 317–327.
  • Kuhn, T., 1977, The Essential Tension, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, 1983, “Commensurability, Comparability, Communicability,” in PSA 198: Proceedings of the 1982 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, P. Asquith and T. Nickles (eds.), East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.
  • –––, 1996, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, third edition, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Levi, I., 1986, Hard Choices: Decision Making Under Unresolved Conflict, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2004, “The Second Worst in Practical Conflict,” in Practical Conflicts, P. Baumann and M. Betzler (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Luce, R. D., 1958,“ A probabilistic theory of utility,” Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, 26 (2): 193–224.
  • Messerli, M., & Reuter, K., 2017, “Hard Cases of Comparison,” Philosophical Studies, 174 (9): 2227–2250.
  • Mill, J.S., 1861 [1979], Utilitarianism, George Sher (ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1979.
  • Millgram, E., 1997, “Incommensurability and Practical Reasoning,” in Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, R. Chang (ed.), Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Moore, G.E., 1902, Principia Ethica, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Nagel, T., 1979, “The Fragmentation of Value”, in Mortal Questions, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Nussbaum, M., 2001, The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy, revised edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Parfit, D., 1987, Reasons and Persons, paperback edition with corrections, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Pildes, R. and E. Anderson, 1990, “Slinging Arrows at Democracy: Social Choice Theory, Value Pluralism, and Democratic Politics,” Columbia University Law Review, 90: 2121–2214.
  • Pinkowski, D., 2013, “Practically Equal: An Analysis of the Practical Nature of Equality and Incomparability,” Acta Analytica, 28 (4): 457–470.
  • Qizilbash, M., 2012, “Incommensurability or Vagueness? A Comment on Rabinowicz and Sugden”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 112 (3): 333–338.
  • –––, 2014, “Incommensurability and Vagueness: Is the Vagueness View Defensible?, ” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 17 (1): 141–153.
  • Rabinowicz, W., 2009, “Incommensurability and Vagueness,” Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 83 (1): 71–94.
  • –––, 2008, “Value Relations,” Theoria, 74 (1): 18–49.
  • –––, 2012, “Value Relations Revisited,” Economics and Philosophy, 28 (2): 133–164.
  • –––, 2021a, “Can Parfit′s Appeal to Incommensurabilities in Value Block the Continuum Argument for the Repugnant Conclusion?” in Ethics and Existence: The Legacy of Derek Parfit, J. McMahan, T. Campbell, J. Goodrich, and K. Ramakrishnan (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2021b, “Incommensurability Meets Risk” in Value Incommensurability: Ethics, Risk, and Decision-Making, H. Andersson and A. Herlitz (eds.), Routledge.
  • Rawls, J., 1982, “Social Unity and Primary Goods,” in Utilitarianism and Beyond, A. Sen and B. Williams (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Raz, J., 1986, The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 1989, “Facing Up,” Southern California Law Review, 62: 1153–1235.
  • –––, 1991, “Mixing Values,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplement), 65: 83–100.
  • –––, 1997, “Incommensurability and Agency,” in Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, R. Chang (ed.), Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Regan, D., 1997, “Value, Comparability, and Choice,” in Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, R. Chang (ed.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Reiff, M., 2014, “Incommensurability and Moral Value,” Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 13 (3): 237–268.
  • Reuter, K., & Messerli, M., 2017, “How Not to Characterise a Hard Choice,” Ratio, 30 (4), 494–521.
  • Richardson, H., 1994, Practical Reasoning about Final Ends, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Sartre, J.-P., 1975, “Existentialism is a Humanism,” in Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre, W. Kaufman, New York: Meridian-New American.
  • Savage, L. J., 1954, The Foundations of Statistics, New York: Wiley.
  • Schoenfield, M,. 2014, “Decision Making in the Face of Parity,” Philosophical Perspectives, 28: 263–277.
  • Schneider, S. and J. Shanteau, (eds.), 2003, Emerging Perspectives on Judgment and Decision Research, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Sen, A., 1997, “Maximization and the Act of Choice,” Econometrica, 65: 745–779.
  • –––, 2000, “Consequential Evaluation and Practical Reason,” Journal of Philosophy, 98: 477–502.
  • Sen, A. and B. Williams, (eds.), 1982, Utilitarianism and Beyond, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Sidgwick, H., 1874 [1981], The Methods of Ethics, seventh edition, Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Company, 1981.
  • Simon, H., 1955, “A Behavioral Model of Rational Choice,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69: 99–118.
  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W., 1985, “Moral Dilemmas and Incomparability,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 22: 321–329.
  • –––, 1988, Moral Dilemmas, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
  • Stocker, M., 1990, Plural and Conflicting Values, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 1997, “Abstract and Concrete Value: Plurality, Conflict, and Maximization,” in Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, R. Chang (ed.), Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2004, “Two Views of Satisficing,” in Satisficing and Maximizing: Moral Theorists on Practical Reason, M. Byron (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Strudler, A., 1998, “Incommensurable Goods, Rightful Lies, and the Wrongness of Fraud,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 146: 1529–1567.
  • Sugden, R., 2009, “On Modelling Vagueness, and on Not Modelling Incommensurability,” Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 83 (1): 95–113.
  • Sunstein, C., 1994, “Incommensurability and Valuation in Law,” Michigan Law Review, 92: 779–861.
  • Taylor, C., 1982, “The Diversity of Goods,” in Utilitarianism and Beyond, A. Sen and B. Williams (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1997, “Leading a Life,” in Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, R. Chang (ed.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Thomson, J. J., 1997, “The Right and the Good,” The Journal of Philosophy, 94 (6): 273–298.
  • Von Fritz, K., 1970, “The Discovery of Incommensurability by Hippasus of Metapontum,” in Studies in Presocratic Philosophy, D. Furley and R.E. Allen (eds.), London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
  • Walzer, M., 1983, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality, New York: Basic Books.
  • Wasserman, R., 2004, “Indeterminacy, Ignorance and the Possibility of Parity,” Philosophical Perspectives, 18: 391–403.
  • Weber, E., J. Baron, and G. Loomes, (eds.), 2001, Conflict and Tradeoffs in Decision Making, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Wiggins, D., 1998, “Weakness of Will, Commensurability, and the Objects of Deliberation and Desire,” in D. Wiggins, Needs, Values, Truth: Essays in the Philosophy of Value, third edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 1997, “Incommensurability: Four Proposals,” in Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, R. Chang (ed.), Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Williams, B., 1981, “Conflicts of Values,” in Moral Luck, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Yates, J. F., E. Veinott, and A. Patalano, 2003, “Hard Decisions, Bad Decisions: On Decision Quality and Decision Aiding,” in Emerging Perspectives on Judgment and Decision Research, S. Schneider and J. Shanteau (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Other Internet Resources

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Acknowledgments

For helpful discussions and comments, Nien-hê Hsieh would like to thank Rahul Kumar, Martin Sandbu, Alan Strudler, Kok-Chor Tan, and Sara Toomey. A special debt of gratitude is given to Walter Sinnott-Armstrong for his support and for his extremely detailed comments and suggestions. Hsieh also would like to thank Jennifer Woo for research assistance.

Copyright © 2021 by
Nien-hê Hsieh
Henrik Andersson <Henrik.Andersson@fil.lu.se>

This is a file in the archives of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Please note that some links may no longer be functional.