version history
|
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
A |
B |
C |
D |
E |
F |
G |
H |
I |
J |
K |
L |
M |
N |
O |
P |
Q |
R |
S |
T |
U |
V |
W |
X |
Y |
Z
This document uses XHTML/Unicode to format the display. If you think special symbols are not displaying correctly, see our guide Displaying Special Characters. |
|
last substantive content change
|
Teleological Notions in Biology
Teleological terms such as "function" and "design" appear frequently in
the biological sciences. Examples of teleological claims include:
- A (biological) function of stotting by antelopes is to communicate
to predators that they have been detected.
- Eagles' wings are (naturally) designed for soaring.
Teleological notions were commonly associated with the pre-Darwinian
view that the biological realm provides evidence of conscious design by
a supernatural creator. Even after creationist viewpoints were rejected
by most biologists there remained various grounds for concern about the
role of teleology in biology, including whether such terms are:
- vitalistic (positing some special "life-force");
- requiring backwards causation (because future outcomes explain
present traits);
- incompatible with mechanistic explanation (because of 1 and
2);
- mentalistic (attributing the action of mind where there is
none);
- empirically untestable (for all the above reasons).
Opinions divide over whether Darwin's theory of evolution provides a
means of eliminating teleology from biology, or whether it provides a
naturalistic account of the role of teleological notions in the
science. Many contemporary biologists and philosophers of biology
believe that teleological notions are a distinctive and ineliminable
feature of biological explanations but that it is possible to provide a
naturalistic account of their role that avoids the concerns above.
Terminological issues sometimes serve to obscure some widely-accepted
distinctions.
Teleomentalists regard the teleology of psychological
intentions, goals, and purposes as the primary model for understanding
teleology in biology. Aside from creationism, the most common form of
teleomentalist view is that teleological claims in biology are mere
metaphor — describing and explaining biological phenomena on the
basis of more or less loose comparisons to psychological teleology.
Those who hold teleology in biology to be metaphorical in nature
typically regard it as eliminable; i.e., they believe that the science
of biology would not be essentially altered if all references to
teleology were eschewed.
Those who reject teleomentalism typically seek naturalistic truth
conditions for teleological claims in biology that do not refer to the
intentions, goals, or purposes of psychological agents. Some
teleonaturalists seek to reduce teleological language to forms
of description and explanation that are found in other parts of
science. One class of such views defines teleological notions
cybernetically and maintains that teleology in biology is appropriate
insofar as biological systems are cybernetic systems. Another, more
widely-accepted approach treats functional claims in biology as part of
the analysis of the capacities of a complex system into various
component capacities.
Other forms of teleonaturalism regard the teleological aspects of
biology as unique and ineliminable. One class of such views maintains
that teleological claims in biology depend on natural values that apply
to biological entities (such as what is good for an organism or
species). A different approach, that avoids normative notions, is to
define biological teleology explicitly in terms of natural selection
and the theory of evolution.
Several theorists have argued for the pluralistic idea that biology
may incorporate two notions of function, one to explain the presence of
traits and the other to explain how those traits contribute to the
complex capacities of organisms. Others have argued that these two
apparently distinct notions of function can be unified by regarding the
target of explanation as the biological fitness of a whole organism.
Nonetheless, the mainstream view among philosophers of biology is that
natural selection accounts best explain the majority of uses of
teleological notions in biology.
Accounts of biological function which refer to natural selection
typically have the form that a trait's function or functions
causally explain the existence or maintenance of that trait in a given
population via the mechanism of natural selection. Three
components of this view can be usefully separated:
- Functional claims in biology are intended to explain the existence
or maintenance of a trait in a given population;
- Biological functions are causally relevant to the existence or
maintenance of traits via the mechanism of natural selection;
- Functional claims in biology are fully grounded in natural
selection and are not derivative of psychological uses of notions such
as design, intention, and purpose.
Variations on this account mostly center on the first two points.
- Some theorists maintain a distinction between the initial spread of
a new phenotypic trait in a population from the maintenance of traits
in populations.
- Some theorists adopt an etiological or backward-looking
approach that analyzes the function of a trait only in terms of those
effects of the trait which have in the past contributed to the
selection of organisms with that trait. Others adopt a
dispositional or forward-looking approach that analyzes
function in terms of those effects it is disposed to produce that tend
to contribute to the present or future maintenance of the trait in a
population of organisms.
In the debate about biological teleology, relatively little attention
has been paid to the notion of natural design. It is common for authors
to slide between claims about function and design as if they accept
this principle:
A trait T is naturally designed for X if
and only if X is a biological function of
T.
Collapsing the notions of design and function in this manner has the
advantage that if the notion of biological function is successfully
naturalized then so is the notion of natural design.
The biological notion of design seems, however, to imply more than
mere usefulness. Female turtles use their flippers to dig nests in
sand, and doing so surely accounts for the maintenance of the trait in
the population. So, on an etiological account, digging in sand is a
function of the flippers. Yet it seems wrong to say that they are
designed for that purpose. This suggests that function and design
should be analyzed separately. One way to do this is as follows:
Trait T is naturally designed to do X
means that
- X is a biological function of T and
- T is the result of a process of change of (anatomical or
behavioral) structure due to natural selection that has resulted in
T being more optimal (or better adapted) for X than
ancestral versions of T.
With respect to this analysis, to say that an eagle's wings are
designed for soaring is to claim, first, that the ability to soar (as
opposed to other kinds of flying) explains why some ancestral eagles
had higher reproductive fitness than others and, second, that eagles'
wings are better adapted for soaring than were ancestral versions of
the wings. This second part is an historical claim that might be
checked against the fossil record.
The notion of adaptation is controversial among biologists because it
suggests the Panglossian belief that this is the best of all possible
worlds. However comparative judgments about traits of organisms, e.g.,
that the traits of present organisms are better at producing some
effect than the corresponding traits of ancestral organisms, do not
require the Panglossian assumption. This is because the claim that A is
more optimal or better adapted than B with respect to some function
does not entail that A is optimal or even good with respect to that
function.
Gould & Vrba (1982) would deny that sand-digging is a function
of turtle flippers and prefer instead to label it an "exaptation". They
recommend the use of "function" only when natural selection has
"shaped" a trait for some use — i.e. the trait has undergone some
modification in form that makes it more suited to the use. This
recommendation, however, seeks to change ordinary biological usage
rather than to elucidate it. Because it conflates the notions of design
and function, it becomes necessary to mark the distinction between
cases of selection with modification (function/design) and cases where
a trait of an organism is coopted for a use for which it is not
modified (exaptation). Even if the flippers of turtles are not
specially modified for burying eggs in sand, the fact that they were so
used helps to explain why turtles with flippers were selected over
those without. Whether one prefers to call this a function or an
exaptation is a terminological issue perhaps to be settled by one's
taste for neologisms.
Works cited
- Gould, S.J. and Vrba, E.S. "Exaptation - a missing term in the
science of form," Paleobiology 8 (1982):
4-15.
Anthologies
- Allen, C., Bekoff, M., & Lauder, G. (eds.) (1998) Nature's
Purposes Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Ariew, A., Cummins, R., & Perlman, M. (eds.) (2002)
Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology and
Biology
- Baerends, G., Beer, C. and Manning, A. (eds.) (1975). Function
and Evolution in Behaviour: Essays in Honor of Niko Tinbergen.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Buller, D. (ed.) (1999) Function, Selection, and Design
Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
- Rescher, N. (ed.) (1986) Current Issues in Teleology.
Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
Review Papers
- Allen, C. and Bekoff, M. (1995) "Function, natural design, and
animal behavior: philosophical and ethological considerations," in N.S.
Thompson (ed.) Perspectives in Ethology, Volume 11: Behavioral
Design. NY: Plenum Press, pp.1-47.
- Bekoff, M. & Allen, C. (1995) "Teleology, function, design, and
the evolution of animal behavior." Trends in Ecology and
Evolution 10(6): 253-255.
- Buller, D. (1998). "Etiological theories of function: a
geographical survey. Biology and Philosophy 505-527. Reprinted
in Buller (1999).
Primary Sources
- Achinstein, P. (1977). "Function statements." Philosophy of
Science 44: 360-376.
- Adams, F. (1979). "A goal-state theory of function attributions."
Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9: 493-518.
- Allen, C. &: Bekoff, M. (1995). "Biological function,
adaptation, and natural design." Philosophy of Science 62:
609-622. Reprinted in Allen, Bekoff & Lauder (1998) and in Buller
(1999).
- Amundson, R., & Lauder, G. (1994). "Function without purpose:
the uses of causal role function in evolutionary biology." Biology
and Philosophy 9: 443-469. Reprinted in Allen, Bekoff & Lauder
(1998).
- Ayala, F.J. (1977). "Teleological explanations." In T. Dobzhansky
(ed.) Evolution, San Francisco: W.H. Freeman and Co.,
pp.497-504. Reprinted in Allen, Bekoff & Lauder (1998).
- Bechtel, W. (1986). "Teleological functional analyses and the
hierarchichal organization of nature." In N. Rescher ed. Current
Issues in Teleology. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
- Beckner, M. (1969). "Function and teleology." Journal of
History of Biology 2: 151-164.
- Bedau, M. (1990). "Against mentalism in teleology." American
Philosophical Quarterly 27(1): 61-70.
- Bedau, M. (1991). "Can biological teleology be naturalized?"
Journal of Philosophy 88: 647-57.
- Bedau, M. (1992). "Where's the good in teleology?" Philosophy
and Phenomenolical Research 52(4): 781-805.
- Bedau, M.A. and Packard, N.H. (1991). "Measurement of evolutionary
activity, teleology, and life." In C. G. Langton, C. E. Taylor, J. D.
Farmer, and S. Rasmussen (eds.) Artificial Life II, SFI Studies in
the Sciences of Complexity Vol. X. Redwood City, CA:
Addison-Wesley, pp.431-483.
- Beer, C.G. (1975). "Multiple functions and gull displays." In
Baerends, G., Beer, C. and Manning, A. eds. (1975). Function and
Evolution in Behaviour: Essays in Honor of Niko Tinbergen. Oxford:
Clarendon Press, pp. 16-54.
- Bigelow, J. and Pargetter, R. (1987). Functions. Journal of
Philosophy 86(4): 181-196. Reprinted in Allen, Bekoff, &
Lauder (1998) and in Buller (1999).
- Bock, W., and von Wahlert, G. (1965). "Adaptation and the
form-function complex." Evolution 19: 269-299. Reprinted in
Allen, Bekoff, & Lauder (1998).
- Boorse, C. (1976). "Wright on functions." Philosophical
Review 82: 139-168.
- Brandon, R.N. (1981). "Biological teleology: questions and
explanations." Studies in the History and Philosophy of
Science 12: 91-105. Reprinted in Allen, Bekoff, & Lauder
(1998).
- Cummins, R. (1975). "Functional Analysis." Journal of
Philosophy 72: 741.765. Reprinted with minor alterations in Allen,
Bekoff, & Lauder (1998) and in Buller (1999).
- Dawkins, R. (1986). The Blind Watchmaker New York:
Norton.
- Enç, B. and Adams, F. (1992). "Functions and goal
directedness." Philosophy of Science 59(4): 635-654.
- Gans, C. (1988). "Adaptation and the form-function relation."
American Zoologist 28: 681-697. Reprinted in Allen, Bekoff
& Lauder (1998).
- Godfrey-Smith, P. (1993). "Functions: consensus without unity."
Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 74: 196-208. Reprinted in
Buller (1999).
- Godfrey-Smith, P. (1994). "A modern history theory of functions."
Nous 28: 344-362. Reprinted in Allen, Bekoff, & Lauder
(1998) and in Buller (1999).
- Goode, R. and Griffiths, P.E. (1995) "The misuses of Sober's
selection for/selection of distinction." Biology and
Philosophy 10: 99-108. Reprinted in Buller (1999).
- Gould, S.J. and Vrba, E.S. (1982). "Exaptation--a missing term in
the science of form." Paleobiology 8: 4-15. Reprinted in
Allen, Bekoff, & Lauder (1998).
- Griffiths, P.E. (1993). Functional analysis and proper functions.
British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44: 409-422.
Reprinted in Buller (1999).
- Hempel, C.G. (1965). "The logic of functional analysis," in
Aspects of Scientific Explanation New York: Free Press.
- Hinde, R.A. (1975). "The concept of function." In Baerends, G.,
Beer, C. and Manning, A. eds. (1975). Function and Evolution in
Behaviour: Essays in Honor of Niko Tinbergen. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, pp. 3-15.
- Kitcher, P. (1994). "Function and Design." Midwest Studies in
Philosophy 18: 379-397. Reprinted in Allen, Bekoff & Lauder
(1998) and in Buller (1999).
- Lauder, G. (1982). "Historical biology and the problem of design."
Journal of Theoretical Biology 97:57-67. Reprinted in Allen,
Bekoff & Lauder (1998).
- Lipton, P. and Thompson, N.S. (1988a). Comparative Psychology and
the Recursive Structure of Filter Explanations. International
Journal of Comparative Psychology 1(4): 215-229.
- Lipton, P. and Thompson, N.S. (1988b). Response: Why Dr. Tinbergen
is more sound than Dr. Pangloss. International Journal of
Comparative Psychology 1(4): 238-244.
- Lorenz, K.Z. (1981). The Foundations of Ethology, New
York: Springer-Verlag.
- Mace, C.A. (1935). "Mechanical and teleological causation."
Proc. Arist. Soc., Supp. 14; reprinted in H. Feigl and W.
Sellars (eds.) (1949). Readings in Philosophical Analysis, New
York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, pp.534-539.
- Mayr, E. "The multiple meanings of teleological," in Towards a
New Philosophy of Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
(1988), pp. 38-66.
- Millikan, R.G. (1984). Language Thought and Other Biological
Categories. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
- Millikan, R.G. (1989a). "In defense of proper functions."
Philosophy of Science 56: 288-302. Reprinted in Allen, Bekoff,
& Lauder (1998).
- Millikan, R.G. (1989b). "An ambiguity in the notion of function."
Biology and Philosophy 4: 172-176. Reprinted in Buller
(1999).
- Millikan, R.G. (1993). White Queen Psychology and other essays
for Alice. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
- Mitchell, S. (1993). "Dispositions or etiologies? A comment on
Bigelow and Pargetter." Journal of Philosophy 90:
249-259.
- Mitchell, S. (1995). "Function, fitness, and disposition."
Biology & Philosophy 10: 39-54. Reprinted in Allen, Bekoff
& Lauder 1998.
- Mitchell, W.A. (1990). "The optimization research program: studying
adaptations by their function." Quarterly Review of Biology
65(1): 43-52.
- Nagel, E. (1961). "The structure of teleological explanations," in
The Structure of Science, pp.401-427, Hackett.
- Nagel, E. (1977). "Teleology revisited: goal-directed processes in
biology." Journal of Philosophy 74: 261-301. Reprinted in
Allen, Bekoff & Lauder (1998).
- Neander, K. (1991a). "The teleological notion of ‘function’."
Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69(4): 454-468.
- Neander, K. (1991b). "Functions as selected effects: the conceptual
analyst's defence." Philosophy of Science 58: 168-184.
- Nissen, L. (1993). "Four ways of eliminating mind from teleology."
Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 24(1):
27-48.
- Pittendrigh, C.S. (1958). "Adaptation, natural selection and
behavior." In Roe, A. and Simpson, G.G. (eds.) Behavior and
Evolution. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT, pp.390-419.
- Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and proper function. New
York: Oxford University Press.
- Reeve, H.K. and Sherman, P.W. (1993). "Adaptation and the goals of
evolutionary research." Quarterly Review of Biology 68(1):
1-32.
- Rudwick, M.J.S. (1964). "The inference of function form structure
in fossils." British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 12:
91-105. Reprinted in Allen, Bekoff, & Lauder (1998).
- Sober, E. (1984). The Nature of Selection. MIT Press,
Cambridge, MA.
- Sober, E. (1993). Philosophy of biology. Boulder, CO :
Westview Press.
- Thompson, N.S. (1987). "The Misappropriation of Teleonomy." In,
P.P.G.B. Bateson and P. Klopfer (eds.) Perspectives in
Ethology 7: 259-274.
- Tinbergen, N. (1952). "Derived" activities, their causation,
biological significance and emancipation during evolution.
Quarterly Review of Biology 27: 1-32.
- Tinbergen, N. (1963). "On aims and methods of ethology."
Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie 20: 410-429.
- Van Parijs, P. (1982). Evolutionary Explanation in the Social
Sciences: an emerging paradigm. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and
Littlefield.
- Walsh, D. and Ariew, A. (1996). "A taxonomy of functions."
Canadian Journal of Philosophy 493-514. Reprinted in Buller
(1999).
- West-Eberhard, M. J. 1992. "Adaptation: current usages." In E.F.
Keller and E.A. Lloyd (eds.) Keywords in Evolutionary Biology,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp.13-18.
- Williams, G.C. (1966). Adaptation and Natural Selection,
Princeton, NJ.: Princeton University Press.
- Wimsatt, W.C. (1972). "Teleology and the logical structure of
function statements." Studies in the History and Philosophy of
Science 3(1),1-80.
- Wouters, A. (1999). "Explanation Without a Cause." Utrecht, The
Netherlands: Zeno Institute of Philosophy.
- Wright, L. (1973). "Functions." Philosophical Review 82:
139-168. Reprinted in Allen, Bekoff & Lauder (1998) and in Buller
(1999).
- Wright, L. (1976). Teleological Explanations. Berkeley,
CA: University of California Press.
- Please contact the author with suggestions.
biology, philosophy of |
function |
mental content: teleologicaltheories of |
natural selection
A |
B |
C |
D |
E |
F |
G |
H |
I |
J |
K |
L |
M |
N |
O |
P |
Q |
R |
S |
T |
U |
V |
W |
X |
Y |
Z
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy