This is a file in the archives of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. |
version history
|
Stanford Encyclopedia of PhilosophyA | B | C | D | E | F | G | H | I | J | K | L | M | N | O | P | Q | R | S | T | U | V | W | X | Y | Z
|
last substantive content change
|
Sense data are the (alleged) mind-dependent objects that we are directly aware of in perception, and that have exactly the properties they appear to have. For instance, sense data theorists say that, upon viewing a tomato in normal conditions, one forms an image of the tomato in one’s mind. This image is red and round. The mental image is an example of a ‘sense datum’. Many philosophers have rejected the notion of sense data, either because they believe that perception gives us direct awareness of physical phenomena, rather than mere mental images, or because they believe that the mental phenomena involved in perception do not have the properties that appear to us (for instance, I might have a visual experience representing a red, round tomato, but my experience is not itself red or round). Defenders of sense data have presented a variety of arguments for their view, appealing to such phenomena as perspectival variation, illusion, and hallucination. Critics of sense data have objected to the theory’s commitment to mind-body dualism, its difficulty in locating sense data in physical space, and its apparent commitment in some cases to sense data that have indeterminate properties.
Each of those conditions calls for clarification.
First, condition (i): Everyone in the philosophy of perception agrees that perception makes us aware of something. Most hold that there is a distinction between the things perception makes us directly aware of, and the things it makes us indirectly aware of, where to be indirectly aware of something is, roughly, to be aware of it in a way that depends on the awareness of something else. There are at least two ways of further explicating this notion. One way, adopted by Jackson (1977, pp. 15-20), is to say that we perceive something indirectly if we perceive it by virtue of perceiving something else. For example, consider my perception of the table in front of me. I do not perceive all of the table; I can only see its outer surface, and indeed only the portion of that surface facing me. Yet we still say that I see the table. I count as seeing the table by virtue of seeing something else, namely, the facing surface of the table. Therefore, Jackson would say that I see (or perceive) the table only indirectly. Sense data, on this view, are things that one may perceive not by virtue of perceiving anything else.
Another way of distinguishing direct and indirect awareness is to say, roughly, that one has indirect awareness of x when one's awareness of x is caused by one's awareness of something else. For instance, I might wish to determine the temperature of a pot of water indirectly, by means of a thermometer, rather than sticking my hand in the water. In such a case, I would first become aware of the reading on the thermometer, and this would cause me to be aware of the temperature of the water. Thus, my awareness of the water's temperature would be indirect. On this view, sense data would be things our awareness of which is not causally dependent on any other awareness.
Second, condition (ii): Sense data theorists believe that the things we are directly aware of in perception are dependent on the mind of the perceiver — they cannot exist unperceived. Such things have also sometimes been called "mental images," "ideas," "impressions," "appearances," or "percepts."
Third, condition (iii): "The properties that perceptually appear to us" refers to the qualities we seem to perceive things around us to have. For instance, if I perceive a tomato, and it looks red and round to me, then redness and roundness are properties that perceptually appear to me. According to those who believe in sense data, there is in this case a thing that I am directly aware of, which is both red and round, and which depends on my mind for its existence. Condition (iii) holds true even if I am subject to a sensory illusion or hallucination. Thus, if the tomato is really green, but, due to some sort of color illusion, it looks red to me, then my sense datum is red (not green). Furthermore, if there is no tomato present in reality, but I am hallucinating a tomato, then I will be having a tomato-like sense datum.
Those who accept sense data believe that sense data exist whenever a person perceives anything, by any of the senses, and also whenever a person has an experience qualitatively like perceiving (such as a hallucination).
The sense data theory contrasts with two competing schools of thought in the philosophy of perception. First, direct realism holds that in perception, we are directly aware (only) of things in the physical world--for example, a table, or a portion of a table's surface. Direct realists thus deny that there is anything satisfying both conditions (i) and (ii) above, and therefore deny that there are sense data. Second, the adverbial theory (in one version) holds that in perception, we are directly aware of a certain kind of mental state or occurrence, but that this mental state does not actually possess the properties that appear to us. Adverbialists have been known to characterize this mental state in such terms as "being appeared to redly." When a person is in the mental state of being appeared to redly, say the adverbialists, it does not follow that anything is actually red. Thus, adverbialists deny that there is anything satisfying all of conditions (i), (ii), and (iii), and therefore deny that there are sense data.
Some have argued that the phenomenon of perspectival variation shows that what we are immediately aware of in perception cannot be the real, external objects, but must instead be only images in the mind (sense data). Here is one way of making out that argument:
Here is an alternate way of making the argument:
Modifications might be made to this argument to make it more plausible (the first premise might be phrased in terms of counterfactual relations, rather than actual changes; "direct awareness" might replace "awareness"; and one might specify more carefully in what respects the properties of experience must covary with those of the object of awareness). Something like this argument may be what Hume had in mind, if only implicitly.
Once we have agreed that the immediate object of awareness is not the real, external object, we are then meant to infer that it must be some sort of image of the physical object in our minds, which we perhaps confused with the physical object.
Some philosophers have argued that the possibility of sensory illusions shows that what we are directly aware of in perception is never the real, physical object. Using the bent-stick illusion as an example, one might argue:
A background assumption is that there is only one stick-like thing that one sees in the example, and that thing is either an actual, physical stick, or a mental image of a stick (a sense datum). The argument concludes that it is not the physical stick, so it must be a sense datum.
Step (4) seems plausible, since one can imagine first perceiving the stick normally, and then moving it into the water. It would seem absurd to maintain that one is seeing the physical stick up to the moment when it touches the water, at which point the object of one's awareness suddenly changes to a sense datum.
Some believe that the possibility of hallucinations shows that even normal perception always involves sense data. Imagine two people, Sally and Sam, each of whom is having an experience of seeming to see a table. Sally is simply perceiving a table in the normal way. Sam, however, is having an incredibly realistic hallucination of a table, induced by futuristic brain scientists who have sophisticated technology for electrically stimulating Sam's brain. And suppose, as is theoretically possible, that Sally and Sam are in the same brain state, which I will call brain state B (where this is the state that is relevant to the character of their visual experience). Sam would be unable to distinguish his experience from a normal perception of a table.
In this scenario, what is Sam directly aware of? Surely not a physical table, since no physical table is present. It seems, then, that he must be aware of a mere mental image of a table. This mental image is caused by brain state B.
Now, what about Sally? Sally's brain state was caused in a different way from Sam's — Sally's was caused by a real table, whereas Sam's was caused by the brain scientists. But that does not change the fact that Sally is now in the same brain state as Sam. We have already said that in Sam, brain state B caused a mental image of a table. Therefore, it seems that if someone else were to have state B, it would also cause a mental image of a table for them. Therefore, it seems that Sally must also be having a mental image of a table, since she is in state B. Therefore, normal perception involves sense data, just as hallucination does. This argument relies on the principle that, if a causal chain of events leads to some effect, E, then any series of events that duplicates the last member of the causal chain will also produce E, regardless of whether the earlier members of the chain are duplicated. As long as Sally and Sam get into the same brain state, regardless of how they got there, both should experience whatever effects result from that brain state.
It would be implausible to maintain that one of the two things is a sense datum while the other is a real object. One reason this would be implausible is that there seems to be nothing relevantly different between the two images that could make one of them the ‘real’ object. Therefore, one should conclude that both of the things one sees are sense data, rather than physical objects.
Imagine two individuals, Sally and Sam, who are each looking up at the night sky and ‘seeing’ (or seeming to see) qualitatively similar stars. The star responsible for Sally's experience still exists. But the star ultimately responsible for Sam's experience ceased to exist 1000 years ago. Sam still ‘sees' it because the star was over 1000 light years away.
What is Sam directly aware of? Surely not an actual star, since no star presently exists in the place where he is looking. It must be a mere mental image of a star that he is directly aware of. Just as in the case of the argument from hallucination, we can now argue that since Sally is in the same brain state as Sam, she must also be having a mental image of a star. Therefore, sense data are involved in normal perception, even when the physical object responsible for the perception still exists.
One might be tempted to say that what Sam sees is light rays, rather than a sense datum. But if the time gap shows that Sam does not directly perceive the star, it must also show that Sam does not directly perceive anything else outside of him either, since there is some time gap, however small, between any external event and Sam's corresponding sensory experience. Sam's visual experience as of a star will occur at least slightly later than the light rays strike his retina.
The first premise seems obvious on its face. The second premise may seem unbelievable, but there are several arguments for it. One of these arguments appeals to differences of color perception among people. Not only color blind people, but even people with normal vision differ among themselves slightly in how they perceive the colors of things. If colors are really out there, then there would have to be an answer to the question, Whose color perceptions are right? But not only is there no way of determining the answer to that; it seems hard to think of what facts might make one person's color perceptions more right than another's. A related argument appeals to the differences of color perception among different species of animals. Again, there seems no answer to the question of which species is right.
Another argument appeals to the fact that our experiences of color are caused (mostly) by the wavelengths of light that physical objects reflect. Therefore, it seems that if colors belong to physical objects, they must be reducible to spectral reflectance distributions. However, there is in general no single spectral reflectance distribution, or even a single (continuous) range of spectral reflectance distributions, corresponding to each of the colors we see. Two objects with very different spectral reflectance distributions may both appear orange to us in normal lighting conditions, for example. (This phenomenon is known as ‘metamerism.’) Some believe that this fact precludes our reducing colors to spectral reflectance properties.
Some philosophers hold that colors are dispositions to cause certain kinds of sensory experiences in us, rather than dispositions to reflect light in certain ways. But others object that this is not so, because (among other reasons) colors ought to be properties that we directly perceive things to have, whereas we do not perceive things as having dispositions to cause experiences in us.
There is much more to be said about color. But if the sense data theorist can succeed in refuting the alternative views of color, we will have to say that colors are properties only of our mental images of objects, and not of the physical objects themselves. Once we admit that, we would surely have to admit that what we are directly aware of in perception is the mental images.
If, to take a rather different case, a church were cunningly camouflaged so that it looked like a barn, how could any serious question be raised about what we see when we look at it? We see, of course, a church that now looks like a barn. We do not see an immaterial barn, an immaterial church, or an immaterial anything else. And what in this case could seriously tempt us to say that we do? (p. 30; emphasis Austin's)
A similar response might be made to the argument from perspectival variation. For this sort of reason, some sense data theorists have abandoned the argument from illusion, resting their case on other arguments. (Jackson 1977, pp. 107-11)
For various reasons, most contemporary thinkers in philosophy of mind embrace some form of physicalism and reject dualism. If they are right to do so, then there is a reason for rejecting sense data: namely, that sense data do not seem to fit into the physicalist picture. Sense data are supposed to have the properties that perceptually appear to us. But, in cases of normal perception, the only physical things that have the properties that perceptually appear to us are the external objects (tables, trees, and so on) that the direct realists say we are perceiving; and in cases of illusions and hallucinations, there are no physical things that have the properties that perceptually appear to us. In particular, our brain states manifestly do not ordinarily have the properties that perceptually appear to us (except in the odd case that we happen to be looking at a brain!). So sense data, if they exist, must be non-physical things. Of course, those prepared to embrace mind-body dualism need not worry about this objection.
A further objection to both answers (2) and (3) is that they conflict with the special theory of relativity, since in some cases, they would require one's brain state to cause a sense datum to appear outside one's forward light cone, and the theory of relativity precludes causal relations with events so situated.
A problem with this is raised by the observation that it is sometimes indeterminate what properties objects appear to us to have. To say that it is indeterminate what properties an object appears to have is to say that the object appears to instantiate some determinable (for example, it appears to be in a certain range of colors), but there is no specific determinate falling under that determinable that it appears to instantiate (for instance, there is no exact shade of color that it appears to have). Chisholm (1942) discusses a case in which one sees a speckled hen for a moment, but one is unable to say how many speckles one saw. Ayer (1963, pp. 124-5) implies that in such a case, there is no definite number of speckles that the sense datum had. Other, perhaps more convincing pieces of evidence for indeterminate appearances include our inability to say exactly how far away certain objects are, our inability in some cases to say whether two objects are the same color, and our inability to read blurred or far-away words.
If the apparent properties of objects of perception are sometimes indeterminate, then the sense data involved would have to be metaphysically indeterminate — that is, they would have to actually lack definite characteristics. This, however, is logically impossible — an object cannot be speckled but have no particular number of spots; an object cannot be colored but have no particular shade of color; and so on. This sort of problem only arises when we analyze appearance in such a way that there must always be an actual object that has all and only the properties that appear to the subject.
Sense data theorists may wish to respond to this problem by denying (pace Ayer) that the properties of one's sense data are always transparent to one.
Michael Huemer slztu9y02@sneakemail.com |
A | B | C | D | E | F | G | H | I | J | K | L | M | N | O | P | Q | R | S | T | U | V | W | X | Y | Z