Intention

First published Mon Aug 31, 2009; substantive revision Mon Aug 13, 2018

Philosophical perplexity about intention begins with its appearance in three guises: intention for the future, as when I intend to complete this entry by the end of the month; the intention with which someone acts, as I am typing with the further intention of writing an introductory sentence; and intentional action, as in the fact that I am typing these words intentionally. As Elizabeth Anscombe wrote in a similar context, ‘it is implausible to say that the word is equivocal as it occurs in these different cases’ and from the fact that ‘we are tempted to speak of “different senses” of a word which is clearly not equivocal, we may infer that we are pretty much in the dark about the character of the concept which it represents’ (Anscombe 1963, p. 1).

The principal task of the philosophy of intention is to uncover and describe the unity of these three forms. This project matters for questions in the philosophy of mind, but also for ethics, where it is involved in the doctrine of double effect, for epistemology, and most obviously, for the nature of practical reason.

We can classify theories of intention roughly but usefully on two axes. First, how do they find unity in the guises of intention? Do they explain one in terms of another? Which, if any, do they treat as primary? There is a deep opposition here between accounts that take intention to be a mental state in terms of which we can explain intentional action, and those that do not. Second, how do they understand the relation between intention and evaluative thought, which bears on the possibility of akrasia, and the relation between intention and belief, which bears on the nature and scope of self-knowledge? These questions arise whatever the relation between intending and doing. Sections 1 and 2 address the first axis of disagreement, while sections 3 to 5 primarily address the second.

1. Intending as Doing

In ‘Actions, Reasons and Causes,’ Donald Davidson gave a reductive theory of ‘intention with which’ as ‘syncategorematic’: the phrase does not refer to an event or state of the agent, but is a way of redescribing what she is doing in terms of a ‘primary reason,’ where this is understood as a pro-attitude towards actions having some feature, F, along with the belief that the original action has that feature (Davidson 1963, pp. 5–8). It is in virtue of its relation to a primary reason that the action counts as intentional, and this reason gives the intention with which the action is done. Davidson thereby unified, or took himself to have unified, intentional action and intention-with-which.

As he came to see, however, this story neglects and cannot easily incorporate prospective intention or intention for the future (Davidson 1978). There are apparent cases of ‘pure intending’ in which no steps of any kind are taken. Suppose that I intend to write a book review but have yet to open the book. On the face of it, such pure intending cannot be reduced to intentional action. What is more, once we recognize the existence of pure intending, ‘there is no reason not to allow that intention of exactly the same kind is also present when the intended action eventuates’ (Davidson 1978, p. 89). If what I am doing intentionally takes time, as almost everything does, there will be early phases in which I stand to the completion of the deed just as I stand to future actions I intend to perform but have yet to begin.

The majority of work since Davidson’s conversion has followed him in acknowledging the state of prospective intention as irreducible to action, and has been led to seek unity in the forms of intention by explaining the others—intentional action and intention-with-which—in terms of intending as a mental state. Recently, however, philosophers inspired by Anscombe’s Intention have offered resistance to this move. Anscombe denies that there is a sharp distinction between ‘I am doing A’ and ‘I am going to do A’ offered as answers to the question ‘Why are you doing B?’ (Anscombe 1963, pp. 39–40). Nor does she regard intention for the future as needing further explanation once intentional action and intention-with-which have been understood (Anscombe 1963, pp. 90–4). Thus, Anscombe appears to solve the problem of unity without acknowledging intention as a mental state.

The simplest version of this approach would emphasize the ‘openness’ of the progressive, that ‘He is doing A’ does not imply that he will succeed in doing A, or that he has or will get very far with it. (That I am crossing the road is consistent with being hit by a car the moment I step off the curb.) It then identifies the fact that S intends to do A with the fact that S is doing A intentionally, though perhaps he has barely begun. If I intend to visit the zoo next Thursday, I am already on the way to doing so. Here it is striking that we sometimes employ the present progressive in anticipation: ‘Kieran is visiting the zoo next Thursday’ sounds perfectly fine when said today, before I have taken any overt steps (see Falvey 2000 pp. 25–6; Thompson 2008, pp. 140–1; Moran and Stone 2009, pp. 145–6).

A more subtle line would concede that we do not always use the progressive quite so liberally, but insist that doing so carves nature at its joints. According to Michael Thompson (2008, pp. 91–2, 133–46), intending to do A is not a mental state because it is not static; instead it is a form of imperfectivity or being in progress towards the intentional completion of an act, where the progress may be so vestigial or ineffectual or interrupted that it would be odd to remark, ‘He is doing A.’ (See Thompson 2008, pp. 91–2, 133–45; Moran and Stone 2009, pp. 146–8; Ferrero 2017.) The unity of prospective intention and ‘doing A intentionally’ is that the latter, too, consists of being in progress, though perhaps with the implication of some success.

Along with this unity, and the hint supplied by the use of the progressive in anticipation, there are two main arguments for the theory of intending as being embarked on intentional action. First, it readily explains why intending is always intending to do something. (For this argument, see Thompson 2008, pp. 120–3, 127–8, 130–1, drawing on Baier 1970; Moran and Stone 2009, pp. 143, 147.) Although we sometimes report intention as a propositional attitude—‘I intend that p’—such reports can always be recast as ‘intending to…’ as when I intend to bring about that p. By contrast, it is difficult to rephrase such mundane expressions as ‘I intend to walk home’ in propositional terms. ‘I intend that I am (will be) walking home’ suggests indifference to getting there. ‘I intend that I (will) have walked home’ suggests indifference to my present agency. ‘I intend that I walk home’ can only be read as an intention with a habitual object, describing a general practice of getting home on foot; it is not directed at a particular action. If intending is being on the way to intentional action, it is no surprise that its proper object—what one is on the way to doing—is not a mere proposition or state of affairs, but something one might do.

Second, the theory of intending as being embarked on intentional action explains the unity of what Thompson calls ‘naïve’ and ‘sophisticated’ rationalization. (For this argument, see Thompson 2008, pp. 97–9, 118–9, 132–4.) As well as explaining action by intention—‘He is doing A because he intends to do B’—we explain action by action—‘He is doing A because he is doing B’—intention by intention—‘He intends to do A because he intends to do B’—and intention by action—‘He intends to do A because he is doing B.’ On the face of it, moreover, ‘naïve’ explanations in terms of what someone is doing entail ‘sophisticated’ explanations that appeal to intention. At least when we are using the ‘because’ of rationalization, ‘He is doing A because he is doing B’ arguably entails ‘He is doing A because he intends to do B.’ The same point holds for what is explained: ‘He is doing A because…’ entails ‘He intends to do A because…’ If intending is being on the way to intentional action, these are all forms of explanation by, and of, such progress. So, again, it is no surprise that they are bound together in just the way that they appear to be.

If we help ourselves to the ‘because’ of rationalization, we can further exploit the unity of its ‘naïve’ and ‘sophisticated’ forms to give a simple theory of intention-with-which. An intention with which one is doing A is an intentional-action-in-progress that explains one’s doing it. We thus complete the task of unification that was set by the threefold division of intention for the future, intention-with-which, and intentional action, all of which are modes of, or modes of explanation by, being embarked on intentional action.

A final virtue of this account is that it captures the element of commitment in intention, emphasized by Michael Bratman, among others (Bratman 1987, pp. 18–20). Intention is not merely predominant desire. When I decide to do something, and so intend to do it, I am embarked upon doing it. This vindicates the Aristotelian view that action itself is the conclusion of practical thought.

Because of its relatively recent recovery, and the prevalent acceptance of intention as a mental state, there has been little examination of the present alternative. But some initial observations can be made. First, it is in fact controversial that intending to do A is necessary for doing A intentionally, as the present theory predicts. This raises complications best considered later on, in sections 2 and 4. (They are briefly discussed at Thompson 2008, pp. 102–3.)

Second, and more obviously, there is room to doubt whether intending to do A is sufficient for me to count as doing it intentionally, even when we admit that I can be doing what I will never successfully do. Isn’t there a distinction between taking preparatory steps towards doing A and beginning to do it, as in the contrast between buying flour and eggs with the intention of baking, and turning on the oven the following week? This distinction may be significant in ethics and the criminal law (Paul 2014). There is also the prospect of plans that require no preparatory steps, as for instance, to blink tomorrow at 3:00pm. Isn’t some intending utterly pure, as Davidson thought? Once we move away from the simple theory of intending as doing, however, and introduce the abstract notion of imperfectivity or being in progress, it is more difficult to say what such examples show. That the theory is false? Or just how liminal being in progress can be?

More telling, perhaps, is the possibility of making a mistake, as when I intend to walk home by the shortest possible route, but have taken a wrong turn. Do I count as being embarked on walking home by the shortest route? If not, the theory stands refuted. If so, I can be on the way not only to doing something I will never do, because I will be interrupted at the earliest moment, but something it is now impossible for me to do. Can we explain how my doings are directed at that impossible outcome except by appeal to the intention with which they are performed?

The arguments that motivate the theory of intending as being embarked on intentional action are in any case inconclusive. As to the second, while it is a constraint on any theory of intention to show the unity of ‘naïve’ and ‘sophisticated’ rationalization, insofar as they are really unified, it would take much further argument to show that this cannot be done while thinking of intention as a mental state (cf. Setiya 2007a, pp. 51–2). Further demands for unity push towards that view. So, for instance, if we hope to bring out what is common to the explanations ‘He is doing A because he is doing B’ and ‘He is doing A because p’ where these entail, respectively, ‘He is doing A because he intends to do B’ and ‘He is doing A because he believes that p,’ we will have to relate intention to the mental state of belief. If intention is not itself a mental state, but a way of being in progress, such relations are more puzzling. They are taken up again in section 5.

As to the first, those who think of intention as a mental state could explain why its objects are restricted to actions by saying more about the kind of state it is. For instance, if intention is a representation that is such as to guide and control what it represents, its object must be as such as to be guided: it must be the sort of thing that can be in progress and move towards completion, something that can be done, not a mere proposition or state of affairs. Alternatively, the restriction could be denied (as it is by Davis 1984, pp. 131–2; Ferrero 2013). Intending that p is fundamental, and intending to walk home can be explained in terms of it: I intend that I will have walked home by walking home.

Finally, whatever view we take about the basic objects of intention—actions or propositions—it is a problem for the theory of intending as being embarked on intentional action that these objects can be logically complex. I intend not to be hit by a car as I walk home. I intend to drink with dinner or have dessert, but not both. I intend to read a book tonight if there’s nothing on the radio. In none of these cases can we say, without contrivance, what action I am now on the way to performing. Until it is supplied with an account of these cases, and of the relation between intention and the mental states with which it interacts, the theory of intending as being embarked on intentional action remains incomplete.

2. Intention in Action

If prospective intention cannot be explained in terms of intentional action, or both in terms of being in progress, how can we preserve the unity of our three divisions? In particular, how does intentional action relate to prospective intention and intention-with-which? There are two obvious thoughts. The first is that doing A intentionally is doing it with some further intention, or doing something with the intention of thereby doing A. The second is that both phenomena are to be explained in terms of intention as a mental state. Let us take these possibilities in turn.

The idea of explaining intentional action through intention-with-which is associated with resistance to causal accounts of acting for a reason. It begins instead with intentional teleology—doing A in order to do B, or with the intention of doing B—treating this as primitive and not involving intention as efficient cause. If we assume that every intentional action is done for a reason, and that this reason can be cast in teleological form, we can identify doing A intentionally with doing A in order to do something else. We thereby unify two guises of intention. Difficulties arise, however, from the case of idle behaviour, in which I am doing A intentionally for no particular reason (Anscombe 1963, p. 25), and from the possibility—or necessity—that teleological series come to an end. I am doing A in order to do B in order to do C … in order to do Z, which I am doing for its own sake. Not all intentional actions are performed with a further end. The purported unity fades. In order to solve this problem, George Wilson (1989) and Carl Ginet (1990, Ch. 6) appeal to intention de re. One need not intend one’s doing A to promote some further end in order to count as doing A intentionally. It is sufficient to intend, of something one is doing, that it promote or constitute one’s doing A.

This way of putting things prompts the objection that merely having that intention is not enough. If the intention is idle or ineffective, one will not, despite one’s wishes, count as doing A intentionally, or as acting in order to do A (Mele 1992, pp. 248–55). We need to add a causal relation, after all. But this objection misunderstands the teleological view. It is not that the mere presence of a mental state—intending of … that it …—constitutes acting with an intention, or acting intentionally, but that intention-with-which is a basic form of teleology, distinct from causation, out of which we can construct the unity of intention.

A deeper problem for the teleological approach is how to complete this construction with an account of prospective intention in terms of intention-with-which. In cases of pure intending, there is no intention with which I am doing anything yet. It is thus no accident that Wilson (1989, pp. 222–30) is led to deny the possibility of pure intention. When I intend to do A in the future, I am doing something now with the intention of doing A, in that I intend, of what I am doing, that it promote or constitute my doing A. The action in question may be overt, but it may be as minimal as keeping track of opportunities for doing A, or biding my time.

Finally, the teleological theorist must account for the connection between intentions with which one acts and psychological states of belief and desire. Why does it follow from the fact that one intends, of what one is doing, that it promote or constitute one’s doing A that one wants to do A and that one believes, of what one is doing, that it is a means to that end? These implications make sense if intention is a species of desire that interacts with means-end belief when one does A with the intention of doing B. They are more difficult to explain if intention-with-which is the basic material from which intention and intentional action are built. (This argument is developed at greater length in Setiya 2011, pp. 146–9.)

Pressures of this kind push us towards the second approach, now orthodox in action theory, which aims to explain both intentional action and intention-with-which in terms of intention as a mental state. According to the simplest possible view, an intentional action of doing A is the execution of a prior intention to do A, and doing A with the intention of doing B is intending, of one’s doing A, that it promote or constitute one’s doing B.

There are two immediate difficulties. First, although we sometimes form an intention prior to acting, this is not essential. I can wave my arm intentionally without planning in advance. This fact elicits a refinement often credited to Searle (1983, pp. 84–5): the distinction between prospective intention and intention in action. In the former case, one intends to do A, perhaps at some point in the future. In the latter, one intends to be doing it now. When S is doing A intentionally, she is doing it in execution of an intention in action, though except in very unusual cases she also intends to do A: to complete the action she is in the midst of performing.

This refinement preserves the idea that doing A intentionally requires an intention whose object is doing A. This is what Bratman (1987, p. 112) has dubbed ‘the Simple View.’ It is open to serious objections, the more subtle of which will be examined in section 4. For now, it is sufficient to note that I sometimes count as doing A intentionally when it is a merely foreseen and unintended consequence of what I intend to do. (See Harman 1976, pp. 151–2; Bratman 1987, pp. 123–5.) Thus if I am paid to pump water into the cistern of a house, and I continue to do so even when I realize that the water is poisoned, I poison the inhabitants of the house intentionally, despite the fact that I did not intend or desire such harm (cf. Anscombe 1963, pp. 41–2). Even here, however, an intention is executed: I intend to pump water into the house. In general, when it is not the execution of a directly corresponding intention, doing A intentionally is a foreseen or desired consequence of an action that is. Admittedly, this condition is necessary, not sufficient, for intentional action, a concept whose vagaries are hard to map. But the execution of intention remains the core phenomenon from which all instances of intentional action are derived.

Along with such matters of detail, two problems of principle can be raised against the present approach. The first contends that it is tacitly circular, because the content of intention always includes the concept of intentionality (Wilson 1989, pp. 274–5; Ginet 1990, pp. 34–5). In prospective intention, I intend not only to do A, but to do A intentionally, and the same point holds for the object of intention in action. This prevents us from explaining what it is to act intentionally in terms of intention as a mental state.

The force of this objection is unclear. While there is something wrong with an account of what it is to φ that appeals to being or doing φ, it is not so obviously problematic to appeal to mental states that represent something as being or doing φ. Our task is not to introduce the concept of intentional action to someone who lacks that concept, but to spell out the metaphysics of doing A intentionally. It is an open question whether ‘metaphysical definition’—saying what it is to φ—can be permissibly circular, so long as the circularity is contained in the scope of an attitude. Such circularity is characteristic of ‘response-dependent’ accounts of evaluative and other properties. (This response may fail if the attitude in question is knowledge; see Ford 2011, §4.)

A more direct response to the challenge would deny its premise. While it is true that the execution of intention is intentional action, it does not follow that the object of intention is doing A intentionally (cf. Searle 1983, pp. 85–6.) If I intend to be smiling and am doing so involuntarily, I am doing what I intend, though not intentionally. Likewise, if I intend to skip breakfast and do so because I forget about it, my intention was fulfilled, though not by intentional action. (These claims are consistent with the view that, when I act for reasons, those reasons figure in my intention as a Kantian ‘maxim’. In that case, my intention is fulfilled, in its entirety, only if I act on them and thereby act intentionally. See Wallace 1999, pp. 60–2; Setiya 2007a, pp. 39–49; Korsgaard 2008; Schapiro 2011; and, for resistance, Sinhababu 2013, §3. On the content of intention, more generally, see Harman 1976, pp. 156–8; Velleman 1989, pp. 94–7; Mele 1992, Ch. 11; and Ross, pp. 255–7, Appendix B.)

The second problem is more a question: whether ‘the relation of being done in execution of a certain intention, or being done intentionally, is a causal relation between act and intention.’ (Anscombe 1983, p. 95) Anscombe denies that it is. When she writes of ‘practical knowledge’ as ‘the cause of what it understands’ she means formal not efficient cause, and then only when ‘the description of the action is of a type to be formally the description of an executed intention.’ (See Anscombe 1963, pp. 87–8, and for conflicting interpretations: Hursthouse 2000; Vogler 2002; Moran 2004; Newstead 2006; Velleman 2007; Paul 2011; Ford 2015; Schwenkler 2015; Lavin 2016; Setiya 2016a; Campbell 2018a; Campbell 2018b.)

One source of concern about intention as efficient cause is that intention need not precede intentional action, while causes must precede their effects. But causal theorists may deny that claim about the temporality of causes, conceiving intention as the simultaneous, sustaining cause of what one is doing (Thalberg 1984, pp. 257–8). They can also accommodate the case in which intention is essential to, and thus not fully distinct from, the action it causes: for things that cannot be done except intentionally, as perhaps greeting and promising (Anscombe 1963, pp. 84–5). Even here, intention could play an efficient-causal role in its own execution (Setiya 2007a, pp 56–9).

A more familiar anxiety turns on ‘causal deviance’ (Davidson 1973, p. 79). If we are trying to say what it is to act intentionally, the condition of doing A because one so intends looks insufficient. For it says nothing about the causal path from intention to action. If I intend to be shaking in order to signal my confederate, and this intention makes me nervous, so that I shake, I am shaking because I intend to do so—though not intentionally. My intention did not cause me to shake ‘in the right way.’ Nor is the ‘right way’ obviously a matter of ‘proximate’ causation or the absence of causal intermediaries, since a causal theorist may well allow for neural intermediaries, and further intentions, in the causal path from intention to action. There is a failure of intentional action only when intermediaries are of the wrong kind.

Reactions to causal deviance vary widely. Some are convinced that the problem is hopeless (Anscombe 1989, pp. 110–1; Wilson 1989, Ch. 9; O’Brien 2007, Ch. 8); others that it can be solved by appeal to such phenomena as causal direction and guidance, which are found outside the province of intentional action and therefore introduce no circularity. (See Thalberg 1984; Mele 1992, Ch. 11; Setiya 2007a, pp. 31–2; and, for objections, Lavin 2013.) A recent development finds a problem of causal deviance in the manifestation of dispositions, even when they are dispositions of inanimate objects. Suppose I attach a fragile glass to an explosive device that detects whether it is attached to something fragile and if it is, shatters the object when it is struck. When the glass is struck, it will break in part because it is fragile without manifesting its fragility: the causal connection is wrong. Because the phenomenon deviance is in this way general, there is reason to hope we can solve it for intentional action by appeal to resources we need elsewhere. (See Hyman 2014 on dispositions and desires.)

It is in any case unclear how the dispute about causal deviance bears on the project of explaining intentional action through intention as a mental state. Would that project survive if the relation of execution and the corresponding ‘because’ were taken as primitive? Or in a ‘disjunctive’ theory according to which intention in action has two distinct forms: doing A intentionally and ‘mere’ intending, frustrated by the world? Like the theory of intending as being embarked upon intentional action, the disjunctive conception agrees with Aristotle that action is, or can be, the conclusion of practical thought.

Corresponding issues have been pursued in the philosophy of perception, where causal and disjunctive theories are often opposed (as by Snowdon 1980–1), and in epistemology more broadly. Instead of explaining knowledge as belief that meets further conditions, some epistemologists treat knowledge as basic, explaining mere belief as its defective form (McDowell 1995; Williamson 2000). The parallel view of intentional action treats mere intending as a defective form of intentional action (O’Brien 2007; Rödl 2007, Ch. 2; McDowell 2010, §7; Marcus 2012, Ch. 2). A question for this view is how the state of intending can be a form of something dynamic: the event or process of acting. To answer this question, we need to say more about the kind of state intention is.

3. Intention and the Good

If intention is a mental state in relation to which doing A amounts to doing A intentionally, or with the further intention of doing B, that fact would unify the modes of intention with which we began. It would, however, tell us little about intending itself. Does this state involve desire? Belief about what one is doing or what one is going to do? Evaluative judgement? Similar questions arise for those who deny that intention is a mental state and explain it as being on the way to intentional action. Must I want to perform an action I am thus embarked upon? Believe that I am engaged in it? Hold it to be in some way good?

It is a matter of consensus in the philosophy of intention that intending to do A entails wanting to do A, in the motivational sense for which the ‘primitive sign of wanting is trying to get’ (Anscombe 1963, p. 68). Doubts about this entailment are attributed to ambiguities in ‘desire.’ When I intend to do A reluctantly, from the motive of duty, I may deny that I want to do it, but what I lack is ‘appetite’ not ‘volition’ (Davis 1984, pp. 135–40; Thompson 2008, pp. 103–5).

Intending is thus a ‘pro-attitude’ of some kind—assuming, for simplicity, that intention is a mental state. In his later work, Davidson specified this pro-attitude as ‘an all-out, unconditional judgement that the action is desirable’ (Davidson 1978, p. 99). He made two further refinements. First, when one is doing A intentionally, ‘at least when the action is of brief duration, nothing seems to stand in the way of an Aristotelian identification of the action with [all-out evaluative judgement]’ (Davidson 1978, p. 99). Second, one counts as intending an action only if one’s beliefs are consistent with one’s performing it; one cannot intend to do what one believes to be impossible (Davidson 1978, pp. 100–1).

In an influential critique, Bratman objects that choice is possible even when one knows that neither option is more desirable than the other; one can decide between options that are equivalent or on a par (Bratman 1985, §V). If unconditional judgement presents its object as more desirable than any alternative, Davidson’s theory wrongly prohibits such choice. If the judgement is merely that a given action is no less desirable than others, it permits me to intend A and intend B, even if I know that they are incompatible. Against this, Bratman claims that it is irrational to intend A and intend B if one cannot rationally intend A-and-B, as when doing both is inconsistent with one’s beliefs.

A related objection is that we can fail to act, or intend, in accordance with our evaluations. In a typical case of akrasia, I conclude that I ought to quit, but decide to continue smoking instead. Davidson (1970) replied to this by distinguishing ‘all things considered’ from ‘unconditional’ evaluative judgement. In ‘conditional’ or ‘prima facie’ judgement one takes some body of considerations, r, to support A over B. All things considered judgement is the special case of this in which r includes all the considerations one holds relevant. There is no inconsistency in judging that the sum of these particular considerations favours A over B while judging that B is better than A, perhaps in light of other considerations one has not specifically considered. Since it is the latter judgement that constitutes intention, one can act intentionally against the former. This is how Davidson makes sense of my continuing to smoke.

Few have been convinced by Davidson’s account. (A recent critic is McDowell 2010.) Can’t we act—intentionally and without self-contradiction—against an unconditional evaluative judgement? Or fail to intend in accordance with one? Davidson himself concedes that ‘A is better than B, all things considered’ entails ‘A is better than B’ if ‘all things considered’ means ‘all truths, moral and otherwise’ (Davidson 1970, p. 40). He may intend this to be trivial, counting that fact that A is better than B among the relevant truths. But it is both plausible and non-trivial to claim that A is better than B, in the relevant sense, if and only if the balance of reasons favours A over B, where the reasons are distinct from that evaluative fact. Since it is possible to grasp this connection, to hold that the balance of reasons favours quitting, and still not intend to quit, Davidson’s theory must be false. (A consequence of this fact is the need to distinguish weakness as akrasia from weakness as failure of will; see Holton 2009, Ch. 4.)

If we hope to defend an evaluative theory of intention, despite this possibility, we will have to equate intending with judgement of some other evaluative proposition, not entailed by claims about the balance of reasons (as in Rödl 2007, Ch. 2), distinguish kinds of judgement or ways of representing an action as to be done, one of which constitutes intending, the other of which we act against in akrasia (as in Tenenbaum 2007, Ch. 7), or otherwise weaken the relationship between intention and the good (as in Shah 2008). Whichever way we go, we will need to motivate the evaluative theory. What is it about the role of intention in intentional action, or in practical reasoning, that requires it to take an evaluative shape? What is missing from theories of intention on which it does not?

4. Intentions as Plans

Having criticized Davidson’s theory, Bratman offers a diagnosis of his mistake that appeals to the functional role of intention as a mental state. According to Bratman (1985, §VI), Davidson neglects the place of prospective intentions in cross-temporal and inter-personal coordination, and as inputs to further practical thought. There is room for doubt about this verdict, since all-out evaluative judgement may well appear as a premise of practical syllogism (‘I ought to do A; doing B is a means to that; so I ought to do B’) and since it may sustain ‘diachronic autonomy,’ at least to some extent, just through the working of memory (a point emphasized by Ferrero 2006). But Bratman is right to indicate a gap in Davidson’s story, which he has done more than anyone to fill.

For Bratman (1987), intention is a distinctive practical attitude marked by its pivotal role in planning for the future. Intention involves desire, but even predominant desire is insufficient for intention, since it need not involve a commitment to act: intentions are ‘conduct-controlling pro-attitudes, ones which we are disposed to retain without reconsideration, and which play a significant role as inputs to [means-end] reasoning’ (Bratman 1987, p. 20). The plans for action contained in our intentions are typically partial and must be filled out in accordance with changing circumstances as the future comes.

Among the advantages of being able to commit ourselves to action in advance, albeit defeasibly, are: (i) the capacity to make rational decisions in circumstances that leave no time to deliberate, or lend themselves to deliberative distortion; (ii) the capacity to engage in complex, temporally extended projects that require coordination with our future selves; and (iii) the capacity for similar coordination with others.

Bratman (1987, Ch. 3) argues that these advantages are best secured if our intentions are consistent with one another and with our beliefs, and if they conform to principles of means-end coherence—for instance, that when we intend E and believe that intending M is necessary to achieve E, we also intend M. There is, he claims, a ‘pragmatic rationale’ for such requirements, ‘one grounded in [their] long-run contribution to getting what we (rationally) want’ (Bratman 1987, p. 35).

Responses to Bratman’s theory have focused largely on the nature of these alleged requirements. Bratman (1987, §2.5) argues that intentions do not provide inputs to practical reasoning by providing additional reasons. This conception is, on the one hand, too weak, since it treats the fact that I have settled on doing A as just one consideration among many in favour of doing it, whereas means-end coherence is a strict or peremptory demand. And it is, on the other hand, too strong, since it permits a form of illicit bootstrapping in which an irrational decision can generate a reason that tips the balance in favour of acting on it. (Do intentions ever provide reasons? Many deny this; see, for instance, Broome 2001; Brunero 2007; Cullity 2008; Kolodny 2011. But Bratman’s argument leaves room for such reasons, so long as the actions they support would be rational without them. For versions of this point, see Chang 2009; Ferrero 2010; Smith 2016.)

Bratman’s pragmatic theory gives intentions a substantive role in practical thought without treating them as reasons. But it faces problems of its own. In structure, Bratman’s theory is akin to the variety of rule-utilitarianism on which we have utilitarian grounds for adopting a practice of punishment or promising that sometimes goes against considerations of utility. This structure prompts a serious dilemma. If reasons for adopting a practice or pattern of reasoning transmit to the actions or inferences that fall under it, as Rawls (1955) once argued, the problems of bootstrapping and peremptoriness return. All we have is a theory of why intentions provide reasons. But if reasons do not transmit in this way, the picture appears to be one of ‘rational irrationality’: having reason to adopt or sustain an irrational pattern of reasoning, on the ground that the results of doing so are mostly for the best. Neither option is appealing.

In his 1987 book, Bratman in effect pursued the second path, hoping to soften its peculiarity by distinguishing ‘internal’ and ‘external’ perspectives on rationality and deliberation (Bratman 1987, §3.5). More recently, he has argued that the benefits of consistency and coherence are more than pragmatic, since they allow for a form of self-governance that is of non-instrumental value (Bratman 2009b), and that they are closely tied to the functional role of intentions as plans (Bratman 2009c, §§VIII–IX). He also adopts John Broome’s (2004) idea that the relevant norms take ‘wide scope.’ For instance, it is irrational to [intend E, believe that intending M is necessary to achieve E, and not intend M]. It does not follow from this that, if one intends E, one is under rational pressure to intend the necessary means, since one can just as well avoid the forbidden combination of attitudes by giving up one’s intention for the end. By the same token, there is no need to admit that intentions provide reasons for acting. We thus avoid both horns of the dilemma sketched above. How far this strategy succeeds is a matter of ongoing dispute (Setiya 2007b; Bratman 2009b; Brunero 2010; Way 2010). There is also a question how far Bratman’s functional explanation of means-end rationality commits him to a wider form of rationalism or ‘constitutivism’ about practical reason (Setiya 2014; Bratman 2018).

A further objection to the demands for consistency and coherence in intention turns on an implication that Bratman (1987, Ch. 8) himself draws out. According to the Simple View, doing A intentionally involves an intention whose object is A. As Bratman argues, however, it is sometimes rational to attempt both A and B, hoping to achieve one or the other, when I know that I cannot do both. If I succeed in doing A, I will have done so intentionally, and thus, on the Simple View, I must have intended to do A. Considerations of symmetry imply that I also intended to do B. But then my intentions are not jointly consistent with my beliefs. Bratman concludes that the Simple View is false, since it would be irrational to have such intentions. Instead, I intend to try doing A and to try doing B, knowing that I can make both attempts, though both cannot succeed. Bratman admits that, when I try to do A, I take the relevant means ‘with the intention’ of doing it. But he finds this phrase ambiguous. On one reading, it ascribes the intention to do A, but in the present case it does not. Instead, I merely ‘endeavour’ to do A, where this is a matter of ‘guiding desire’ (Bratman 1987, Ch. 9).

The main objection to this view, pressed forcefully by Hugh McCann (1991), is that it generates an unhappy proliferation of intention-like states, and that, by finding ambiguity in ‘intention with which,’ it fails to unify the guises of intention. What is more, there are natural alternatives. One equates intention with guiding desire, defends the Simple View, and finds the requirement of consistency defeasible. There is rational pressure to conform to it, in general, but this pressure can be outweighed, as when it makes sense to intend both A and B, despite their manifest inconsistency, hoping to achieve just one. Another alternative appeals to partial intention, by analogy with partial belief (see Holton 2009; Goldstein 2016; Shpall 2016; Archer 2017; Muñoz 2018). There is also room for a more radical view, on which the reasons for being consistent in one’s intentions, or conforming to means-end coherence, reduce to the reasons for acting in one way or another: Bratman’s alleged requirements are a ‘myth.’ (See Raz 2005; Kolodny 2008; and for a qualified view that speaks to the persistence of intention, Tenenbaum 2014; Tenenbaum 2018).

A final objection to Bratman’s theory is more general, and would apply as well to the theory of intention as guiding desire. The question is whether such accounts reveal the unity of intentional action, intention for the future, and intention-with-which. McCann’s objection concerned the latter. The more basic objection is about the role of intention in intentional action. Bratman (1987, Ch. 8) does not ignore this connection: he proposes necessary and sufficient conditions for doing A intentionally that rely on the state of intending, though not always the intention of doing A itself. But it is open to question how deep the envisaged unity goes. Why must there be intention in intentional action, if intentions are plans? (See Velleman 2007, §3.)

A partial answer cites the need for direction and guidance in doing anything that takes time or requires the selection of means. But it is not clear that such guidance requires intention (see Bratman 1987, pp. 126–7 on spontaneous action). Nor would this forge a general connection between the state of intending and the phenomenon of acting for reasons or the application of Anscombe’s (1963, p. 9) question ‘Why?’ If S is doing A on the ground that p, she is doing it intentionally. Bratman’s conditions do not explain why intention must be involved in the antecedent of this conditional. Why must reasons attach to what I am doing by way of plans or guiding desires? One response is to admit that they may not: there can be intentional action without intention (see Bratman 2000, pp. 51–2). But if we hope to unify intention with intentional action, we cannot accept this. Intention must figure in the correct account of acting for a reason, and thus intentionally. In order to avoid disunity, the theory of intentions as plans (or as guiding desires) needs such an account.

5. Intention and Belief

Acknowledging these problems, some philosophers turn back to Davidson and the project of reducing intention to desire and means-end belief (see, especially, Ridge 1998; Sinhababu 2013; and, for discussion, Mulder 2018). But others see a promise of unity in the idea—influentially proposed by Elizabeth Anscombe (1963, pp. 11–15) and Stuart Hampshire (1959, pp. 95, 102)—that when S is doing A intentionally, S knows that she is doing A. What is more, acting for a reason, in a sense that contrasts with mere purposive behavior (of the sort characteristic of other animals), essentially involves such knowledge: in acting for a reason, I know an explanation of what I am doing that cites that reason, and therefore know that I am doing it. That is why, for Anscombe, the question ‘Why?’ is ‘given application’ by the agent. Intentional action turns on knowing the answer to that question.

This picture raises many difficulties, and needs considerable refinement and defence. (For variations, see Velleman 1989; Velleman 2000; Setiya 2007a, Part One; Rödl 2007, Ch. 2; Setiya 2016b.) Some will resist the claim that acting for a reason is acting with self-knowledge—though it is important to stress that the knowledge attributed here need not involve conscious belief. There is also disagreement about the kind of explanation involved in giving the reasons for which one acts (Wilson 1989, Ch. 7; Ginet 1990, Ch. 6; Dancy 2000; Davis 2005; Alvarez 2010; Setiya 2011). But if the picture is basically right, it suggests that the unity of intention can be found in knowledge or belief about action. Assuming that knowledge entails belief, the basic thought is that intention in action involves the belief that one is doing A. Doing something for a reason involves a belief about one’s reason for doing it that constitutes intention in action. And prospective intention, or intention for the future, involves a belief about what one is going to do and why. The idea that intention involves belief is what unifies intentional action, prospective intention, and intention-with-which. (On an alternative view, which may be Anscombe’s, intention contrasts with belief: they correspond to radically different kinds of knowledge. See the treatment of mistakes below.)

The claim that intention entails belief—most commonly, that if one intends to do A, one believes that one is going to do it—is widespread among those who draw no particular inspiration from Anscombe. (See Audi 1973; Harman 1976; Davis 1984; Ross 2009.) As Grice (1971, pp. 264–6) observed, there is peculiarity of some sort in asserting ‘I intend to do A, but I might not do it,’ a peculiarity readily explained if intention is a species of belief. It is equally striking that the ordinary expression of intention for the future is ‘I am going to do A’ (Anscombe 1963, p. 1), which looks like the assertoric expression of belief. The same point holds for intention in action: ‘What are you up to?’; ‘I am doing A.’ Although such evidence is suggestive, however, it might be explained in other ways. (See Davidson 1978, pp. 91, 100; for criticism, Pears 1985; and for more recent discussion, Levy 2018.)

So far, we have only the fragment of a theory, an alleged condition of intending, not an adequate account of what intention is. Here there are several possibilities. On the simplest proposal, to intend an action is to believe that one will perform it and to have an appropriate guiding desire (Audi 1973, p. 395). But a mere conjunction seems insufficient: the desire and belief could be utterly unrelated (Davis 1984, pp. 141–2). This prompts the suggestion that, when S intends to do A, his belief rests on his desire: to intend an action is to believe that one will perform it on the ground that one wants to do so (Davis 1984, p. 147; see also Grice 1971, pp. 278–9). The principal defect of this account is that it makes the belief component of intention epiphenomenal. This belief merely registers one’s activity: the motivational work is done by a prior desire. (Something similar is true on more subtle theories that divorce the motivational role of intention from belief; as, for instance, Ross 2009, pp. 250–1.) If the claim that intention involves belief is to capture the essence of the will, not a superficial fact about the word ‘intend,’ the belief must be implicated in the functions of intending and the explanation of action. (For objections of this kind, see Bratman 1987, pp. 19–20 and Mele 1992, Ch. 8 on ‘intention*’; on the role of beliefs in planning for the future, see Velleman 1989, Ch. 8; Velleman 2007.)

There is variation even among those accounts that give a motivational role to belief. On Velleman’s early view, intentions are ‘self-fulfilling expectations that are motivated by a desire for their fulfillment and that represent themselves as such’ (Velleman 1989, p. 109). Such expectations interact with a general desire for self-knowledge to motivate action by which they are confirmed. More recently, Velleman has replaced the desire for self-knowledge with a sub-personal aim or disposition (Velleman 2000: 19–21). Either way, his view threatens to generate what Bratman (1991, pp. 261–2) calls ‘the problem of promiscuity’: in attributing a general desire for self-knowledge that motivates us to conform to our own expectations, it predicts that we will be just as strongly motivated by beliefs that do not constitute intentions, like the belief that I am going to trip over the step, or mispronounce a word.

A different proposal, due to Harman (1976, p. 168) is that intentions are ‘conclusion[s] of practical reasoning’ (see also Ross 2009, pp. 270–2). But it seems possible to intend an action spontaneously, for no particular reason. In later work, Harman looks downstream of intention, rather than upstream: an intention is a belief about what one is doing or what one is going to do that has the power to guide and motivate action through practical thought (Harman 1986, pp. 375–6; Setiya 2007a, pp. 48–53). This claim interacts with the question about ‘disjunctive’ theories left unanswered at the end of section 2. If intention involves belief, those who treat knowledge as basic, with mere belief its defective form, will take a similar view of ‘knowledge in intention’ (Rödl 2007; Ch. 2; McDowell 2010, §7; Marcus 2012, Ch. 2). In the good case, one’s intention in action involves knowledge of what one is doing: it entails, so cannot cause or motivate, one’s action. In the bad case, one merely intends to act. If not its causal role, however, what distinguishes knowledge in intention from knowledge of other kinds?

Finally, there is Anscombe’s own view, on which there is a normative contrast between intention and ordinary belief. If one fails to act as one intends, and not through a mistaken belief about the means or possibilities for action, ‘the mistake is not one of judgment but of performance’ (Anscombe 1963, pp. 56–7). Intention sets a standard of success for what does. (For discussions of this point, see Frost 2014; Setiya 2016a; Campbell 2018a; Campbell 2018b.) What is more, there is ‘a difference of form between reasoning leading to action and reasoning for the truth of a conclusion’ (Anscombe 1963, p. 60). Intention is justified by the former, not the latter: by practical not theoretical reasoning (Anscombe 1963, pp. 57–62).

In this respect, Anscombe’s doctrine differs most sharply from Velleman’s. As well as thinking of intention as a kind of belief, Velleman holds that ‘practical reasoning is a kind of theoretical reasoning’ (Velleman 1989, p. 15; see also Ross 2009). In a review of Velleman’s book, Bratman (1991, pp. 250–1) dubbed the conjunction of these claims ‘cognitivism about practical reason.’ It prompts what Davidson (1978, p. 95) called ‘the strongest argument against identifying [intention] with [belief],’ that ‘reasons for intending to do something are in general quite different from reasons for believing one will do it.’ Though Velleman (1989, pp. 122–5) defends that identification, one need not do so in order to accept the theory of intention as belief or the idea of ‘practical knowledge’ as ‘knowledge in intention.’

A more modest ‘cognitivism’ would hold that intention entails belief, that practical reasoning does not reduce to theoretical, but that some requirements that govern intention are best understood as requirements of theoretical reason. It is often regarded as a virtue of such cognitivism that it explains why there should be an indefeasible requirement of consistency among intentions and beliefs (Ross 2009, pp. 244–7). It has also been argued that the requirement of means-end coherence follows from requirements of theoretical reason on the beliefs that figure in our intentions (Harman 1976, p. 153; Wallace 2001; Setiya 2007b; Ross 2009, pp. 261–5). If I intend to do E and thus believe that I will do it, and I believe that doing M is a necessary means to doing E, but do not intend or believe that I am going to do M, I fail to believe a practically salient logical consequence of what I believe. The principal challenge for a cognitivist account of means-end coherence is to explain why one must avoid such theoretical failures by forming the relevant intention, not just the corresponding belief (Bratman 2009a). But once again, one need not defend cognitivism, even in its less ambitious form, in conceiving intention as a kind of belief.

There are two main arguments against this conception. The first turns on apparent cases of intention without belief. According to Davidson, ‘[a] man may be making ten carbon copies as he writes, and this may be intentional; yet he may not know that he is; all he knows is that he is trying’ (Davidson 1971, p. 50; see also Davidson 1978, pp. 91–4). Or imagine I am recovering from paralysis, and movement slowly returns to my hand. At a certain point, I am not sure that I can clench my fist. As it happens, I can. But if I try to do so behind my back, under anesthesia, I may not believe that I am clenching my fist, even though—on the face of it—I am doing so intentionally, and that is just what I intend (Setiya 2008, pp. 390–1). Something similar crops up in planning for the future. I intend to mail the bills on the way to work, but I know that I am forgetful, and don’t believe that I will do it (see Bratman 1987, pp. 37–8).

Such examples can be dealt with in various ways. One strategy insists that, when I do not believe that I am clenching my fist, or that I will mail the bills, I do not intend the corresponding actions, I merely intend to try (Harman 1986, pp. 364–5; Velleman 1989, pp. 115–6). But do I really act as I intended if I try and fail? (See Pears 1985, p. 86; McCann 1991, p. 212.) And when I know that I am forgetful, do I even believe that I will try to mail the bills? A more radical theory points to the simplifying assumption, often made in epistemology, that belief is binary and does not come by degree. On that assumption, it may be harmless to claim that intention involves belief. But the truth is bound to be more complex: that in forming an intention one becomes more confident than one would otherwise be (Setiya 2008, pp. 391–2); or that the will is a capacity to know what one is doing, or what one is going to do, whose exercise may be impeded, yielding mere belief or partial belief instead of knowledge (Pears 1985, pp. 78–81; Setiya 2009, pp. 129–31; Setiya 2012, pp. 300–303).

A final response casts doubt on the examples. When we recall the ‘openness’ of the progressive, we can insist that Davidson’s carbon-copier knows that he is making ten copies, even if he is not sure the copies are going through first time (see Thompson 2011). It is not a condition of being embarked on intentional action that one will in fact succeed. The same might be said when I am clenching my first, if what I know is merely that I am in progress towards doing so, in some liminal way. (This points back to the theory of intending as doing, discussed in section 1.) This strategy struggles with prospective intention and the belief that I am going to act. But its advocates may insist that the content of prospective intention is also imperfective (Thompson 2008, pp. 142–5). We have practical knowledge only of what is in progress, not what has happened, or what will.

The second objection is epistemic. If forming an intention is, among other things, coming to believe that one is doing A, or that one is going to do A, what entitles us to form such beliefs? Not, or not ordinarily, that we have sufficient evidence of their truth. Forming an intention is not predicting the future on the basis of what one takes to be, or what ought to be, adequate grounds. That is why Anscombe calls practical knowledge ‘knowledge without observation,’ meaning to exclude not only observation in the narrow sense but knowledge by inference (Anscombe 1963, p. 50). And it is why Velleman (1989) writes about ‘spontaneous’ knowledge of action. Even though he hopes to reduce practical to theoretical reasoning, and holds that intention involves belief, he denies that intentions are formed on the basis of sufficient prior evidence. Anscombe and Velleman concede that knowledge in intention often rests in part on observation; the claim is that it goes beyond what observation, or inference from prior evidence, can support. (For differing views of the role of perception in practical knowledge, see Pickard 2004; Gibbons 2010; Schwenkler 2011; Ford 2016.)

The postulation of beliefs formed without sufficient prior evidence is sometimes taken as a fatal flaw. In a memorable formulation, Grice (1971, p. 268) wrote that it makes decision ‘a case of licensed wishful thinking.’ According to Grice, we are not epistemically permitted to form beliefs about what we are doing, or what we are going to do, without sufficient prior evidence. Instead, we know what we are doing, or what we are going to do, by inference from the condition of our will, along with premises about our own abilities (Grice 1971, pp. 275–9; Paul 2009). The condition of the will cannot itself involve belief.

Reactions to this problem vary widely. Those who restrict the content of intention to what is in progress and emphasize how little is involved in being embarked on intentional action may suggest that the beliefs in question verify themselves. It is sufficient for doing A intentionally, in the relevant sense, that one intends to do it. As we saw in section 1, however, there are reasons to doubt this sufficiency. And the view seems to deflate the interest of practical knowledge. Anscombe warns against the ‘false avenue of escape’ on which ‘I really “do” in the intentional sense whatever I think I am doing’ (Anscombe 1963, p. 52), and seems to allow for practical knowledge of what I will actually do (Moran 2004: 146; Setiya 2016a).

Other views account for knowledge in intention in reliabilist terms: where one’s intention to do A reliably issues in doing A, it may amount to knowledge of what one is doing, or what one is going to do (Newstead 2006, §2; Velleman 2007, §5). Non-reliabilists may dismiss the need for prior evidence, holding that we are entitled to form a belief if we know that it will be true, and that we will have sufficient evidence for its truth, once formed; this condition can be met when we form an intention to act (Harman 1976, p. 164, n. 8; Velleman 1989, pp. 56–64). So long as I know what I intend, and that my intention will be effective, I have sufficient evidence for what I am doing, or what am I going to do, even though this evidence did not precede the forming of my intention.

Critics may object to the necessity of these conditions. According to Berislav Marušić (2015), I can form the ‘practical belief’ that I will do A without knowing that my intention will be effective, so long as I know that its execution is up to me. A more common objection is that the conditions are not sufficient. They assimilate intention to faith, as when I form the belief that I can leap a great chasm even though I have no evidence of my ability to do so, knowing that the belief itself will ensure success. It is not clear that such acts of faith are possible, that they are epistemically rational, or that they provide a plausible model for intention (Langton 2004; Setiya 2008, §III). On an alternative view, there is a general demand for prior evidence in forming beliefs, but our intentions are sometimes exempt from it, as perhaps when we know how to perform the relevant acts (Setiya 2008; Setiya 2009; Setiya 2012). It is know-how that explains why the execution of our intentions, and thus the truth of the beliefs that they involve, can be credited to us.

Anscombe’s position on the matter is elusive, and may have to do with her normative claims about intention and belief. Is practical knowledge exempt from ordinary requirements of evidence because there is a mistake of performance, not of judgement, when its object is false? (See Anscombe 1963, pp. 4–5, 56–7; Campbell 2018a.) Would it then amount to knowledge of what is not the case? Anscombe may seem to suggest as much (Anscombe 1963, p. 82), but it is unclear whether she accepts or merely entertains this prospect.

Implicit these debates is a question about the scope of groundless (non-perceptual, non-inferential) self-knowledge. A blanket objection to beliefs formed without sufficient prior evidence cannot be sustained: I often know what I believe without having come to know on the basis of perception or inference. Is groundless knowledge of this kind restricted to our mental states? Or can it extend to what we are doing and what we are going to do? Compare externalism about content: at least typically, believing that p has implications for the constitution of the world outside one’s skin; but it remains accessible to self-knowledge (Burge 1988). Why should that not be true of intentional action? On any reading, part of the aim of Anscombe’s Intention was to break the Cartesian prejudice against self-knowledge of what is happening in the world. If she failed in that endeavour, she at least prescribed a task for future work: to say whether it is indeed a prejudice or a decisive obstacle to the possibility of practical knowledge and the theory that intention involves belief.

Bibliography

  • Alvarez, M., 2010, Kinds of Reasons, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Anscombe, G. E. M., 1963, Intention, second edition, Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 1983, ‘The Causation of Action,’ reprinted in Human Life, Action, and Ethics, M. Geach and L. Gormally (eds.), Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2005, pp. 89–108.
  • –––, 1989, ‘Practical Inference,’ reprinted in Human Life, Action, and Ethics, M. Geach and L. Gormally (eds.), Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2005, pp. 109–147.
  • Archer, A., 2017, ‘Do We Need Partial Intentions?’ Philosophia, 45: 995–1005.
  • Audi, R., 1973, ‘Intending,’ Journal of Philosophy, 70: 387–403.
  • Baier, A., 1970, ‘Act and Intent,’ Journal of Philosophy, 67: 648–658.
  • Bratman, M., 1985, ‘Davidson’s Theory of Intention,’ reprinted in Faces of Intention, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1999, pp. 209–224.
  • –––, 1987, Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1991, ‘Cognitivism about Practical Reason,’ reprinted in Faces of Intention, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999, pp. 250–264.
  • –––, 2000, ‘Valuing and the Will,’ reprinted in Structures of Agency, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007, pp. 47–67.
  • –––, 2009a, ‘Intention, Belief, and Practical Rationality,’ in Reasons for Action, D. Sobel and S. Wall (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 13–36.
  • –––, 2009b, ‘Intention, Practical Rationality, and Self-Governance,’ Ethics, 119: 411–443.
  • –––, 2009c, ‘Intention, Belief, Practical, Theoretical,’ in Spheres of Reason, S. Robertson (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 29–61.
  • –––, 2018, Planning, Time, and Self-Governance, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Broome, J., 2001, ‘Are Intentions Reasons? And How Should We Cope With Incommensurable Values?’ in Practical Rationality and Preference: Essays for David Gauthier, C. W. Morris and A. Ripstein (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 98–120.
  • –––, 2004, ‘Reasons,’ in Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz, R. J. Wallace, et al. (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 28–55.
  • Brunero, J., 2007, ‘Are Intentions Reasons?’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 88: 424–444.
  • –––, 2010, ‘Self-Governance, Means-End Coherence, and Unalterable Ends,’ Ethics, 120: 579–591.
  • Burge, T., 1988, ‘Individualism and Self-Knowledge,’ Journal of Philosophy, 85: 649–663.
  • Campbell, L., 2018a, ‘An Epistemology for Practical Knowledge,’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 48: 159–177.
  • –––, 2018b, ‘Two Notions of Intentional Action? Solving a Puzzle in Anscombe’s Intention,’ British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 26: 578–602.
  • Chang, R., 2009, ‘Voluntarist Reasons and the Sources of Normativity,’ in Reasons for Action, D. Sobel and S. Wall (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 243–271.
  • Cullity, G., 2008, ‘Decisions, Reasons, and Rationality,’ Ethics, 119: 57–95.
  • Dancy, J., 2000, Practical Reality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Davidson, D., 1963, ‘Actions, Reasons, and Causes,’ reprinted in Essays on Actions and Events, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980, pp. 3–20.
  • –––, 1970, ‘How is Weakness of the Will Possible?’ Reprinted in Essays on Actions and Events, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980, pp. 21–42.
  • –––, 1971, ‘Agency,’ reprinted in Essays on Actions and Events, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980, pp. 43–61.
  • –––, 1973, ‘Freedom to Act,’ reprinted in Essays on Actions and Events, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980, pp. 63–81.
  • –––, 1978, ‘Intending,’ reprinted in Essays on Actions and Events, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980, pp. 83–102.
  • Davis, W., 1984, ‘A Causal Theory of Intending,’ reprinted in The Philosophy of Action, A. Mele (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997, pp. 131–148.
  • –––, 2005, ‘Reasons and Psychological Causes,’ Philosophical Studies, 122: 51–101.
  • Falvey, K., 2000, ‘Knowledge in Intention,’ Philosophical Studies, 99: 21–44.
  • Ferrero, L., 2006, ‘Three Ways of Spilling Ink Tomorrow,’ in Rationality in Belief and Action, E. Baccarini and S. Prijic-Samarzija (eds.), Rijeka: Filozofski Facultet, pp. 95–127.
  • –––, 2010, ‘Decisions, Diachronic Autonomy, and the Division of Deliberative Labor,’ Philosophers’ Imprint, 10, available online.
  • –––, 2013, ‘Can I Only Intend My Own Actions?’ Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility, 1: 70–94.
  • –––, 2017, ‘Intending, Acting, and Doing,’ Philosophical Explorations, 20 (Supplement 2): 13–39.
  • Ford, A., 2011, ‘Action and Generality,’ in Essays on Anscombe’s Intention, A. Ford, J. Hornsby, and F. Stoutland (eds.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 76–104.
  • –––, 2015, ‘The Arithmetic of Intention,’ American Philosophical Quarterly, 52: 129–143.
  • –––, 2016, ‘On What is in Front of Your Nose,’ Philosophical Topics, 44: 141–161.
  • Frost, K., 2014, ‘On the Very Idea of Direction of Fit,’ Philosophical Review, 123: 429–484.
  • Gibbons, J., 2010, ‘Seeing What You’re Doing,’ Oxford Studies in Epistemology, 3: 63–85.
  • Ginet, C., 1990, On Action, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Goldstein, S., 2016, ‘A Preface Paradox for Intention,’ Philosophers’ Imprint, 16, available online.
  • Grice, H. P., 1971, ‘Intention and Uncertainty,’ Proceedings of the British Academy, 5: 263–279.
  • Hampshire, S., 1959, Thought and Action, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
  • Harman, G., 1976, ‘Practical Reasoning,’ reprinted in The Philosophy of Action, A. Mele (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997, pp. 149–177.
  • –––, 1986, ‘Willing and Intending,’ in Philosophical Grounds of Rationality, R. E. Grandy and R. Warner (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 363–380.
  • Holton, R., 2008, ‘Partial Belief, Partial Intention,’ Mind, 117: 27–58.
  • –––, 2009, Willing, Wanting, Waiting, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Hursthouse, R., 2000, ‘Intention,’ in Logic, Cause and Action, R. Teichmann (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 83–105.
  • Hyman, J., 2014, ‘Desires, Dispositions and Deviant Causal Chains,’ Philosophy, 89: 83–112.
  • Kolodny, N., 2008, ‘The Myth of Practical Consistency,’ European Journal of Philosophy, 16: 366–402.
  • –––, 2011, ‘Aims as Reasons,’ in Reasons and Recognition: Essays on the Philosophy of T. M. Scanlon, S. Freeman, R. Kumar, and and R. J. Wallace (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 43–78.
  • Korsgaard, C., 2008, ‘Acting for a Reason,’ in The Constitution of Agency, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 207–229.
  • Langton, R., 2004, ‘Intention as Faith,’ in Agency and Action, J. Hyman and H. Steward (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 243–258.
  • Lavin, D., 2013, ‘Must There Be Basic Action?’ Noûs, 47: 273–301.
  • –––, 2016, ‘Action as a Form of Temporal Unity: On Anscombe’s Intention,’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 45: 609–629.
  • Levy, Y., 2018, ‘Why Cognitivism?’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 48: 223–244.
  • Marcus, E., 2012, Rational Causation, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Marušić, B., 2015, Evidence and Agency, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • McCann, H., 1991, ‘Settled Objectives and Rational Constraints,’ reprinted in The Philosophy of Action, A. Mele (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997, pp. 204–222.
  • McDowell, J., 1995, ‘Knowledge and the Internal,’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55: 877–893.
  • –––, 2010, ‘What is the Content of an Intention in Action?’ Ratio, 23: 415–432.
  • Mele, A., 1992, Springs of Action, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Moran, R., 2004, ‘Anscombe on “Practical Knowledge,”’ in Agency and Action, J. Hyman and H. Steward (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 43–68.
  • Moran, R. and Stone, M., 2009, ‘Anscombe on Expression of Intention,’ in New Essays on the Explanation of Action, C. Sandis (ed.), Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 132–168.
  • Mulder, J., 2018, ‘Why Intentions?’ Ratio, 31: 51–64.
  • Muñoz, D., 2018, ‘Thinking, Acting, Considering’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 96: 255–270.
  • Newstead, A., 2006, ‘Knowledge by Intention? On the Possibility of Agent’s Knowledge,’ in Aspects of Knowing: Epistemological Essays, S. Hetherington (ed.), Amsterdam: Elsevier, pp. 183–202.
  • O’Brien, L., 2007, Self-Knowing Agents, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Paul, S., 2009, ‘How We Know What We’re Doing,’ Philosophers’ Imprint, 9, available online.
  • –––, 2011, ‘Deviant Formal Causation,’ Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 5: 1–23.
  • –––, 2014, ‘Embarking on a Crime,’ in Law and the Philosophy of Action, E. Villanueva (ed.), Amsterdam: Rodopi, pp. 101–124.
  • Pears, D. F., 1985, ‘Intention and Belief,’ in Essays on Davidson: Actions and Events, B. Vermazen and M. Hintikka (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 75–88.
  • Pickard, H., 2004, ‘Knowledge of Action without Observation,’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104: 203–228.
  • Rawls, J., 1955, ‘Two Concepts of Rules,’ Philosophical Review, 64: 3–32.
  • Raz, J., 2005, ‘The Myth of Instrumental Rationality,’ Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 1: 1–28.
  • Ridge, M., 1998, ‘Humean Intentions,’ American Philosophical Quarterly, 35: 157–178.
  • Rödl, S., 2007, Self-Consciousness, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Ross, J., 2009, ‘How to be a Cognitivist about Practical Reason,’ Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 4: 243–281.
  • Schapiro, T., 2011, ‘Foregrounding Desire: A Defense of Kant’s Incorporation Thesis,’ Journal of Ethics, 15: 147–167.
  • Schwenkler, J., 2011, ‘Perception and Practical Knowledge,’ Philosophical Explorations, 14: 137–152.
  • –––, 2015, ‘Understanding “Practical Knowledge,”’ Philosophers’ Imprint, 15, available online.
  • Searle, J., 1983, Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Setiya, K., 2007a, Reasons without Rationalism, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 2007b, ‘Cognitivism about Instrumental Reason,’ Ethics, 117: 647–673.
  • –––, 2008, ‘Practical Knowledge,’ Ethics, 118: 388–409.
  • –––, 2009, ‘Practical Knowledge Revisited,’ Ethics, 120: 128–137.
  • –––, 2011, ‘Reasons and Causes,’European Journal of Philosophy, 19: 129–157.
  • –––, 2012, ‘Knowing How,’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 112: 285–307.
  • –––, 2014, ‘Intention, Plans, and Ethical Rationalism,’ in Rational and Social Agency: The Philosophy of Michael Bratman, M. Vargas and G. Yaffe (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 56–82.
  • –––, 2016a, ‘Anscombe on Practical Knowledge,’ in Practical Knowledge: Selected Essays, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 156–168.
  • –––, 2016b, Practical Knowledge: Selected Essays, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Shah, N., 2009, ‘How Action Governs Intention,’ Philosophers’ Imprint, 8, available online.
  • Shpall, S., 2016, ‘The Calendar Paradox,’ Philosophical Studies, 173: 293–307.
  • Sinhababu, N., 2013, ‘The Desire-Belief Account of Intention Explains Everything,’ Noûs, 47: 680–696.
  • Smith, M. N., 2016, ‘One Dogma of Philosophy of Action,’ Philosophical Studies, 173: 2249–2266.
  • Snowdon, P., 1980–1, ‘Perception, Vision, and Causation,’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 81: 175–192.
  • Tenenbaum, S., 2007, Appearances of the Good: An Essay on the Nature of Practical Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2014, ‘Minimalism about Intention: A Modest Defense,’ Inquiry, 57: 384–411.
  • –––, 2018, ‘Reconsidering Intentions,’ Noûs, 52: 443–472.
  • Thalberg, I., 1984, ‘Do Our Intentions Cause Our Intentional Actions?’ American Philosophical Quarterly, 21: 249–260.
  • Thompson, M., 2008, Life and Action, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2011, ‘Anscombe’s Intention and Practical Knowledge,’ in Essays on Anscombe’s Intention, A. Ford, J. Hornsby, and F. Stoutland (eds.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 198–210.
  • Velleman, J. D., 1989, Practical Reflection, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 2000, ‘Introduction,’ in The Possibility of Practical Reason, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1–31.
  • –––, 2007, ‘What Good is a Will?’ In Action in Context, A. Leist (ed.), Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, pp. 193–215.
  • Vogler, C., 2002, Reasonably Vicious, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Wallace, R. J., 1999, ‘Three Conceptions of Rational Agency,’ reprinted in Normativity and the Will, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006, pp. 43–62.
  • –––, 2001, ‘Normativity, Commitment, and Instrumental Reason,’ reprinted in Normativity and the Will, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006, pp. 82–120.
  • Way, J., 2010, ‘Defending the Wide-Scope Approach to Instrumental Reason,’ Philosophical Studies, 147: 213–233.
  • Williamson, T., 2000, Knowledge and its Limits, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Wilson, G., 1989, The Intentionality of Human Action, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Other Internet Resources

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Michael Bratman, Luca Ferrero, and Niko Kolodny for valuable comments on an earlier draft.

Copyright © 2018 by
Kieran Setiya <ksetiya@mit.edu>

This is a file in the archives of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Please note that some links may no longer be functional.
[an error occurred while processing the directive]