Events
Smiles, walks, dances, weddings, explosions, hiccups, hand-waves, arrivals and departures, births and deaths, thunder and lightning: the variety of the world seems to lie not only in the assortment of its ordinary citizens—animals and physical objects, and perhaps minds, sets, abstract particulars—but also in the sort of things that happen to or are performed by them. In the last few decades, this view has been a focus of considerable debate in philosophy, with implications reaching far into the concern of other disciplines as well, above all linguistics and the cognitive sciences. Indeed, there is little question that human perception, action, language, and thought manifest at least a prima facie commitment to entities of this sort:
- Pre-linguistic infants appear to be able to discriminate and “count” events, and the content of adult perception, especially in the auditory realm, endorses the discrimination and recognition as events of some aspects of the perceived scene.
- Humans (and, presumably, other animals) appear to form intentions to plan and execute actions, and to bring about changes in the world.
- Dedicated linguistic devices (such as verb tenses and aspects, nominalization of some verbs, certain proper names) are tuned to events and event structures, as opposed to entities and structures of other sorts.
- Thinking about the temporal and causal aspects of the world seems to require parsing those aspects in terms of events and their descriptions.
It is, however, unclear to what extent such prima facie commitments add up to an integrated phenomenon, as opposed to separate, independent dispositions. Moreover, even among those who favor a realist attitude towards the ontological status of events, there is significant disagreement concerning the precise nature of such entities. (Their broad characterization as ‘things that happen’, though commonly found in dictionaries, merely shifts the burden to the task of clarifying the meaning of ‘happen’.) One useful approach is to set them against entities belonging to other, philosophically more familiar, metaphysical categories. In the following we review the main contrasts between events and those categories that have in the literature been put forward explicitly as their ontological competitors, or at least as categories exhibiting significant differences with the category of events. Along the way, we shall also review the main conceptual tools that metaphysicians and other philosophers have adopted in their attempts to deal with events, either from a realist or from a non-realist perspective.
- 1. Events and Other Categories
- 2. Types of Events
- 3. Existence, Identity, and Indeterminacy
- Bibliography
- Academic Tools
- Other Internet Resources
- Related Entries
1. Events and Other Categories
1.1 Events vs. Objects
Although not undisputed, some standard differences between events and physical objects are commonplace in the philosophical literature. First, there would seem to be a difference in mode of being: material objects such as stones and chairs are said to exist; events are said to occur or happen or take place (Hacker 1982a; Cresswell 1986). Second, there would seem to be differences in the way objects and events relate to space and time. Ordinary objects are supposed to have relatively crisp spatial boundaries and vague temporal boundaries; events, by contrast, would have relatively vague spatial boundaries and crisp temporal boundaries. Objects are said to be invidiously located in space—they occupy their spatial location; events tolerate co-location much more easily (Quinton 1979; Hacker 1982b). Objects can move; events cannot (Dretske 1967). Finally, objects are standardly construed as enduring continuants—they are in time and persist through time by being wholly present at every time at which they exist; events are perduring occurrents—they take up time and persist by having different parts or “stages” at different times (Johnson 1921; Mellor 1980; Simons 2000).
The last distinction is especially controversial, as there are philosophers—from Whitehead (1919), Broad (1923), and Russell (1927) to Quine (1950), Lewis (1986c), Heller (1990), Sider (2001) and many others—who conceive of objects as four-dimensional entities that extend across time just as they extend across space. Some such philosophers would accordingly draw no metaphysically significant distinction between objects and events, treating both as entities of the same kind: an object would simply be a “monotonous” event; an event would be an “unstable” object (Goodman 1951). More generally, the relevant distinction would be one of degree, and while ‘event’ is standardly applied to things that develop and change fast in time, ‘object’ would apply to those things that strike us as “firm and internally coherent” (Quine 1970). On the other hand, there are also philosophers who reject the distinction on the side of events, by construing at least some such entities—e.g., processes—as continuants: what is happening at any moment when an apple is decaying or a person is walking down the street is the whole process, not just part of it (Stout 1997, 2003, 2016; Galton 2006, 2008; Galton & Mizoguchi 2009). This view, in turn, admits of several variants and alternatives, e.g. based on different ways of understanding the notion of a continuant (Steward 2013, 2015) or its relation to the stuff of which a continuant is composed (Crowther 2011, 2018).
If a metaphysical distinction between objects and events is granted, then a question arises as to the relation between the entities in the two categories. Objects are prime actors in events; objectless events are uncommon. But so are eventless objects; events make up the lives of objects. In a radical mood, however, one can think of the entities in one category as being metaphysically dependent on entities in the other. For instance, it has been claimed that events supervene on their participants (Lombard 1986; Bennett 1988), or that objects depend on the events in which they partake (Parsons 1991). In a more moderate way, one can grant objects and events an equal ontological status but maintain that either objects or events are primary in the order of thought. Thus, it has been argued that a pure event-based ontology would not be sufficient for the success of our re-identifying practices, which require a stable frame of reference of the sort that is adequately provided only by objects (Strawson 1959). A similar asymmetry between objects and events seems to be endorsed by natural language, which has expressions such as ‘the fall of the apple’ but not ‘the pomification of the fall’. However, these asymmetries may be attenuated to the extent that objects, too, may and sometimes must be identified via reference to events. For example, if we track down the father of Sebastian or the author of Waverley, it is by identifying certain events in the first place—of fathering and of writing, respectively (Moravcsik 1965; Davidson 1969; Lycan 1970; Tiles 1981).
1.2 Events vs. Facts
No matter what their relationships, events are naturally contrasted with objects insofar as both are conceived of as individuals. Both appear to be concrete, temporally and spatially located entities organized into part-whole hierarchies. Both can be counted, compared, quantified over, referred to, and variously described and re-described. (It has been argued that our conceptions of these two categories are so closely tied as to be structurally complementary, in that any characterization of the concept event that only mentions spatial and temporal features yields a characterization of the concept object by a simple replacement of temporal with spatial predicates, and vice versa (Mayo 1961).) From this point of view, events are to be distinguished from facts, which are characterized by features of abstractness and a-temporality: the event of Caesar’s death took place in Rome in 44 BCE, but that Caesar died is a fact here as in Rome, today as in 44 BCE. One could indeed speculate that for every event there is a companion fact, viz. the fact that the event took place (Bennett 1988), but the two would still be categorially distinct. The death of Caesar must no more be confused with the fact that Caesar died than the Queen of England should be confused with the fact that England has a Queen (Ramsey 1927).
According to some authors, this categorial distinction is actually reflected in the different sorts of expressions through which facts and events are referred to in ordinary language. In the terminology of Vendler (1967), ‘Caesar’s death’ is a perfect nominal: the process of nominalization is complete and the expression can only be modified by adjectival phrases (‘Caesar’s violent death’). By contrast, a that-clause such as ‘that Caesar died’, or a gerundive such as ‘Ceasar’s dying’, are imperfect nominals that still have “a verb alive and kicking inside them”: they can therefore tolerate auxiliaries and tenses (‘That Caesar would die’, ‘Caesar’s having died’), adverbs (‘Ceasar’s dying violently’), negation (‘Ceasar’s not dying’), etc. With some qualifications (McCann 1979), the metaphysical hypothesis would be that, as a norm, perfect nominals stand for events, whereas facts or states of affairs are the referents of imperfect nominals.
Some philosophers, however, conceive of the link between events and facts as being much closer than this—close enough to justify assimilating the two categories (Wilson 1974; Tegtmeier 2000) or at least treating both as species of the same “state of affairs” genus (Chisholm 1970). This has two main consequences. On the one hand, because facts corresponding to non-equivalent propositions are distinct, events conceived of as facts or fact-like particulars are fine-grained entities that cannot be freely re-described or re-identified under different conceptualizations: the fact that Caesar died violently is different from the fact that he died, hence the death of Caesar and his violent death would be two different events (Chisholm 1970, 1971), as opposed to one and the same event under different descriptions (Davidson 1969; Anscombe 1979). On the other hand, because linguistic expressions of facts are semantically transparent, a Fregean line of argument could be concocted to show instead that events construed as facts are too coarse-grained, to the point of melting into a single “big” entity (Davidson 1967a). (The argument is known as the “slingshot argument” (Barwise & Perry 1981).)
Other philosophers have insisted on distinguishing events from facts but have given accounts that effectively amount to an assimilation. This is true especially of those theories that construe events as property exemplifications, i.e., exemplifications of properties by objects at times (Kim 1966; Martin 1969; Goldman 1970; Taylor 1985; Hendrickson 2006). On such theories, events are individual entities. But because they have a structure, a difference in any constituent is sufficient to yield a different event. In particular, a difference in the relevant constitutive property is sufficient to distinguish events such as Caesar’s death, construed as Caesar’s exemplification of the property of dying, and Caesar’s violent death, construed as his exemplification of the property of dying violently (Kim 1976). Again, this makes events virtually as fine-grained as facts. It bears emphasis, however, that this consequence is not intrinsic to the theory of events as property exemplifications. Both Caesar’s death and his violent death could be construed as Caesar’s exemplification of one and the same property P, describable both as a dying and—with greater accuracy—as a dying violently. Thus, even if construed as a structured complex, an event can be coarsely referred to insofar as its names need not be sensitive to this structure (Bennett 1988). In this way the distinction between events and facts can be reinstated in terms of a firm distinction between semantic and metaphysical aspects (respectively) of the theory of event-descriptions.
Similar considerations apply to those theories that treat events as situations, in the sense familiar from situation semantics (Barwise & Perry 1983). On such theories, events are construed as sets of functions from spatiotemporal locations to “situation types” defined as sequences of objects standing or failing to stand in a certain relation. But while the formal machinery delivers a fine-grained account, the algorithm for applying the machinery to natural language sentences leaves room for flexibility.
1.3 Events vs. Properties
A third metaphysical category with which events have sometimes been contrasted is that of properties. If events are individuals, then they are not properties, at least insofar as properties are construed as universals. Individuals exist or occur whereas universals recur. However, some philosophers have taken very seriously the intuition that in some cases events may be said to recur, as when we say that the sun rises every morning (Chisholm 1970; Johnson 1975; Brandl 1997, 2000). If so, then it is natural to think of events as being more similar to properties than to individuals, similar enough to justify treating them as a kind of property—e.g., as properties of moments or intervals of time (Montague 1969), properties of cross-world classes of individuals (Lewis 1986a), or properties of sets of world segments (von Kutschera 1993). For instance, on the first of these accounts, the event of the sun’s rising is the property of being an interval during which the sun rises. As a characterization of event types, this would be uncontroversial and would allow one to construe particular events as tokens of the corresponding type. (One such construal would correspond to the above-mentioned conception of events as property exemplifications.) But to conceive of events as universal properties is to go beyond this uncontroversial fact and to reject the existence of event tokens altogether, even when it comes to “particular” events such as the unique rising of the sun that we witnessed this morning. Rather than an instance of the universal sun rising, such an event would be a universal in its own right, albeit a universal of such a restricted sort and of such a degree of singularity as to be instantiated only once.
One possible view about properties is that they are not universals but rather particulars of a special sort—viz. abstract particulars (Stout 1923) or tropes (Williams 1953). According to this view, the redness of this apple is different from the redness of anything else, not because of its extreme singularity (other things could agree with the apple colorwise) but because it is the redness of this apple. It exists here and now, where and while the apple exists. Likewise, this morning’s rising of the sun would be numerically different from (though qualitatively similar to) any other morning’s rising of the sun. If so, then the view that events are properties becomes compatible with the view that they are spatiotemporally located. An event would just be a particularized property located at some region of space-time (Bennett 1996). (Once again, this conception is closely related to the conception of events as property exemplifications, although the term ‘exemplification’ suggests a construal of properties as universals. Some authors actually identify the two conceptions (Bennett 1988); others reject the identification on account of the difference between property instances and property exemplifications (Macdonald 1989).)
A variant of the trope conception construes events as trope sequences (Campbell 1981). However, since tropes are particulars, a sequence of tropes at a place may itself be viewed as a trope, hence this variant is best regarded as a specification of what sort of tropes events are. Similar remarks apply to those theories that construe events as relational tropes (Mertz 1996), or even as higher-order tropes (Moltmann 2013).
1.4 Events vs. Times
The intuition that events are properties of times can also be fleshed out in terms of thinner metaphysical commitments, by construing events simply as times cum description, i.e., as temporal instants or intervals during which certain statements hold (van Benthem 1983). On this view, for example, this morning’s rising of the sun is identified by an ordered pair <i,φ> where i is the relevant time interval (corresponding to the descriptor ‘this morning’) and φ is the sentence ‘The sun rises’. Of course, this treatment does not do justice to some of the intuitions underlying the prima facie commitments to events mentioned at the beginning—for instance, events can be perceived but times cannot (Gibson 1975). But because of the availability of fully developed theories of intervals along with fully developed interval-based semantics (Cresswell 1979; Dowty 1979), and because of equally well worked-out traditional theories of instants and instant-based semantics (Prior 1967), such accounts are especially attractive from a reductionist perspective. One might even want to construe events as spatiotemporal regions cum description, distinguishing e.g between this morning’s rising of the sun in London and its rising in Paris.
The link between events and times has, however, been explored also in the opposite direction. If events are assumed as a primitive ontological category, then one may dispense with temporal instants or intervals and construe them as derived entities. The most classical treatment of this sort proceeds by construing temporal instants as maximal sets of pairwise simultaneous (or partially simultaneous) events (Russell 1914; Whitehead 1929; Walker 1947), but other treatments are possible. For example, it has been suggested that the mathematical connection between the way events are perceived to be ordered and the underlying temporal dimension is essentially that of a free construction (in the category-theoretic sense) of linear orderings from event orderings, induced by the binary relation x wholly precedes y (Thomason 1989). Treatments such as these provide a reduction of time in terms of relations among events and are therefore especially germane to a relational conception of time (and, more generally, of space-time). Modal variants (Forbes 1993) as well as mereological variants (Pianesi & Varzi 1996) of such views are also available.
2. Types of Events
2.1 Activities, Accomplishments, Achievements, and States
Philosophers who agree with a conception of events as particulars typically distinguish different sorts of such particulars. A classic typology distinguishes four sorts: activities, accomplishments, achievements, and states (Ryle 1949; Vendler 1957). An activity, such as John’s walking uphill, is a homogeneous event: its sub-events satisfy the same description as the activity itself, which has no natural finishing point or culmination. An accomplishment, such as John’s climbing the mountain, may have a culmination, but is never homogeneous. An achievement, such as John’s reaching the top, is a culminating event (and is therefore always instantaneous). And a state, such as John’s knowing the shortest way, is homogeneous and may extend over time, but it makes no sense to ask how long it took or whether it culminated. Sometimes accomplishments and achievements are grouped together into a single category of performances (Kenny 1963). Sometimes achievements have also been called events tout court and all other events have been grouped together into a broadly understood category of temporally extended entities, called processes (Ingarden 1935); the word ‘eventuality’ may then be used as a label covering both categories (Bach 1986).
Some authors introduce aspectual considerations into the taxonomy, drawing on Aristotle’s distinction between Energeia and Kinêsis (Ackrill 1965). The idea is that different verbs describe different types of events: verbs with no continuous form (‘know’) correspond to states; verbs with continuous form for which the present continuous entails the past perfect (‘John is walking uphill’ entails ‘John walked uphill’) correspond to activities; and verbs for which the present continuous entails the negation of the past perfect (‘John is climbing the mountain’ entails ‘John has not (yet) climbed the mountain’, at least in the relevant context) correspond to performances (Mourelatos 1978). Several authors have followed in these footsteps to develop linguistically sophisticated theories (Taylor 1977; Dowty 1979; Freed 1979; Roberts 1979; Bach 1981; Galton 1984; Verkuyl 1989; Smith 1991; Kühl 2008), but the legitimacy of drawing ontological categorizations from such linguistic distinctions has been questioned (Gill 1993).
2.2 Static and Dynamic Events
One may also want to distinguish between dynamic events, such as John’s walking, and static events, such as John’s resting under a tree. According to some authors, the latter are not events proper because they do not involve any change (Ducasse 1926). In the most abstract construal, a change is an ordered pair of states of affairs: an initial state and an end state (von Wright 1963). More substantial accounts of events as changes describe them as exemplifications of dynamic properties, i.e., properties that an object has by virtue of a “movement” in some quality space (Quinton 1979; Lombard 1979, 1986). However, the question of whether all events should be or involve changes of some sort is controversial (Montmarquet 1980; Steward 1997; Mellor 1998; Simons 2003) and it may be argued that it is ultimately a matter of stipulation—hence of little metaphysical import (Casati & Varzi 2008).
If static events are admitted, the question arises of whether they should be kept distinct from states (Parsons 1989). One plausible assumption is that the distinction between the static and the dynamic aspects of the world is skew to the distinction between states and activities. As there may be static activities, so there may be dynamic states. Walking is a state of John’s that is dynamic, as opposed to his state of resting, which is static. The walk itself is an activity of John’s that is dynamic, as opposed to the rest he took under a tree, which may be considered a static activity.
2.3 Actions and Bodily Movements
Prima facie, actions are naturally categorized as a subclass of events, namely, animate events. Like all events, actions are said to occur or take place, not to exist, and their relation to time and space is event-like as well: they have relatively clear beginnings and endings but unclear spatial boundaries, they appear to tolerate co-location, and they cannot be said to move from one place to another or to endure from one time to another, but rather extend in space and time by having spatial as well as temporal parts (Thomson 1977). Actions and events appear to be on a par in causal explanations, too: actions can be causes of which events are effects (Davidson 1967b). Some authors, however, prefer to draw a distinction here and to treat actions as relations between agents and events, namely as instances of the relation of ‘bringing about’ that may hold between an agent and an event (von Wright 1963; Chisholm 1964; Bach 1980; Bishop 1983; Segerberg 1989), or perhaps the relation ‘seeing to it that’ (Belnap and Perloff 1988; Tuomela and Sandu 1994; Horty 2001). On such views, actions are not individuals unless relations are themselves construed as tropes.
Whether or not actions are treated as events, one might be tempted to distinguish between actions proper (such as John’s raising of his arm) and bodily movements (such as John’s arm rising), or between intentional actions (John’s walk) and unintentional ones (John’s falling into a hole). For some authors, this is necessary in order to explain important facts of human behavior (Montmarquet 1978; Hornsby 1980a,b; Searle 1983; Brand 1984; Mele 1997). However, it has also been argued that such distinctions do not pertain to metaphysics but rather to the conceptual apparatus by means of which we describe the realm of things that happen. On this view, an arm raising is just an arm’s rising under a mentalistic description (Anscombe 1957, 1979; Sher 1973).
2.4 Mental and Physical Events
A similar story applies to the distinction between mental events (John’s decision to wear boots) and physical or physiological events (such and such neurons firing). One may think that this distinction is real insofar as the latter events are expected to fall naturally into the nomological net of physical theories whereas the former seem to escape it. But one may also want to resist this line of thought and maintain that the distinction between the mental and the physical concerns exclusively the vocabulary with which we describe what goes on. These options have important ramifications for various issues in the philosophy of mind—e.g., issues of mental causation (Heil & Mele 1993; Walter & Heckmann 2003; Gibb et al. 2013). If the distinction between mental and physical events is ontologically significant, then the question arises of how these two sorts of event causally interact with each other, leading to various forms of anomalous or nomological dualism (Foster 1991). By contrast, the claim that the distinction is purely semantic is congenial to a monist position, whether nomological or anomalous (Macdonald 1989). Anomalous monism has been popular especially among philosophers who accept a particularist conception of events as widely redescribable entities, for such a conception allows one to accept the materialist claim that all events are physical (regardless of whether one describes them in mentalistic terms) while rejecting the seeming consequence that mental goings-on can be given purely physical explanations (precisely because only a physicalistic vocabulary is suited to such explanations) (Nagel 1965; Davidson 1970, 1993). Some authors, however, have argued that this line of argument falls prey to the charge of epiphenomenalism, to the effect that mental events would lack causal or explanatory powers altogether (Honderich 1982; Robinson 1982; Kim 1993; Campbell 1998, 2005) and on such matters the debate is still open.
2.5 Negative Events
Events are things that happen. In some cases, however, the same sort of prima facie evidence that suggests a realist attitude towards such things might suggest a similar attitude towards things that do not actually happen, including “negative actions” of various sorts (Danto 1966; Ryle 1973). We speak of John’s walk with the same easiness with which we speak of the talk he did not deliver, the nap he did not take, the party he failed to organize; we seem to quantify over such things, and we normally engage in causal talk that seems to refer explicitly to negative causes, as when we reason that John’s failure to turn off the gas caused an explosion, or that his omitting the cutlery from the wedding list made Mary angry. Some authors take such evidence at face value, drawing a distinction at the ontological level: a good inventory of the world ought to include “negative” events and actions along with ordinary, “positive” ones (Lee 1978; Vermazen 1985; De Swart 1996; Przepiórkowski 1999; Higginbotham 2000; Mossel 2009; Silver 2018; Bernard & Champollion 2018). Others dissent: we often speak as though there were such things, but deep down we want our words to be interpreted in such a way as to avoid ontological commitment. Thus, either we are just engaging in mere counterfactual speculations, or else the putative negative events are just ordinary, positive events under a negative description: ‘John’s omitting the cutlery from the wedding list’, for example, would refer to his drawing up a wedding list that contains no cutlery, ‘Mary’s not moving’ would describe Mary’s working hard to master urges to move, etc. (Mele 2005; Varzi 2008). The latter view can also be construed in metaphysical (as opposed to semantic) terms, at least in some cases: for x to omit to φ (refrain from φ-ing, etc.) at t would be for x to ensure, through their actual behavior, that they do not φ at t (Payton 2018).
The case of negative causation is especially challenging, not last because of the link between causation and such ethical and legal matters as passive killing (Bennett 1966; Green 1980; Foot 1984), good Samaritanism (Kleinig 1976) and, more generally, moral responsibility (Weinryb 1980; Walton 1980; Williams 1995; Fischer 1997; Clarke 2014). Here it is also customary to introduce finer-grained discriminations, distinguishing e.g. several ways in which an agent may fail to do something, e.g. (trying and) not succeeding, refraining, omitting, and allowing (Brand 1971; Milanich 1984; Hall 1984; Bach 2010). At least with regard to some such ways, it is very tempting to endorse a realist ontology. If so, the difficulty naturally arises of how and where to draw the line. For example, the realist about omissions will have to find a principled way of refraining from treating all omissions, including non-salient ones, as causes (Gorr 1979; Lewis 1986b, 2004; Thomson 2003; Menzies 2004; McGrath 2005; Sartorio 2009; Bernstein 2014). On the other hand, the antirealist will have to explain how one can account for such causal talk while holding on to the view that every causal situation develops from “positive factors alone” (Armstrong 1999). Some would insist that every alleged case of negative causation can be described in terms of positive causation (Laliberté 2013). Others—the majority—would resist ontological commitment by recasting the logical structure of the relevant causal claims in suitable ways, e.g. as causal statements about events that are counterfactually described (Hunt 2005), or as “quasi-causal” claims about what would have been a cause if the omitted event had happened (Dowe 2001), or as mere causal explanations in which the explanans does not stand to the explanandum as cause to effect (Beebee 2004; Varzi 2007; Lombard & Hudson, in press).
3. Existence, Identity, and Indeterminacy
As mentioned in the Introduction, one finds a prima facie commitment to events in various aspects of human perception, action, language, and thought. The main line of argument offered to back up this commitment, however, comes from considerations of logical form. Not only does ordinary talk involve explicit reference to and quantification over events, as when one says that John’s walk was pleasant or that two explosions were heard last night. Ordinary talk also seems to involve several ways of adverting to events implicitly. Adverbial modification is a standard example (Reichenbach 1947). We say that Brutus stabbed Caesar with a knife. If this statement is taken to assert that a certain three-place relation obtains among Brutus, Caesar, and a knife, then it is hard to explain why the statement entails that Brutus stabbed Caesar (a statement that involves a different, two-place relation) (Kenny 1963). By contrast, if we take our statement to assert that a certain event occurred (namely, a stabbing of Caesar by Brutus) and that it had a certain property (namely, of being done with a knife), then the entailment is straightforward (Davidson 1967a). These reasons do not constitute a proof that there are such entities as events. But they are telling insofar as one is interested in an account of how it is that certain statements mean what they mean, where the meaning of a statement is at least in part determined by its logical relations to other statements. For another example, it has been argued that singular causal statements cannot be analyzed in terms of a causal connective (essentially for reasons having to do with the above-mentioned slingshot argument) but rather require that causation be treated as a binary relation holding between individual events (Davidson 1967b). A third example involves the semantics of perceptual reports with naked infinitive complements, as in ‘John saw Mary cry’, which is analyzed as ‘John saw an event which was a crying by Mary’ (Higginbotham 1983; Vlach 1983; Gisborne 2010). Still a fourth example involves the logical form of statements with plural subjects, such as ‘John and Mary lifted the piano (together)’, which is analyzed as reporting, not the exploits of a “plural object”, but rather an event involving more than one agent (Higginbotham & Schein 1986; Schein 1993; Lasersohn 1995; Landman 1996, 2000). Many more such arguments have been offered, also by authors working within different programs in linguistics (Parsons 1990; Peterson 1997; Rothstein 1998; Link 1998; Higginbotham et al. 2000; Tenny & Pustejovsky 2000; Pietroski 2005; van Lambalgen & Hamm 2005; Robering 2014).
On the other hand, some philosophers have been dissatisfied with this sort of “existential proof” and have argued instead that all talk that seems to involve explicit or implicit reference to or quantification over events can be paraphrased so as to avoid the commitment. For example, it has been argued that a term such as ‘John’s walk’ goes proxy for the corresponding statement ‘John walked’ (Geach 1965), so to say that John’s walk was pleasant is just to say that John walked pleasantly. Similar paraphrases have been offered to deal with the case of explicit quantifier-phrases such as ‘two explosions’ as well as with the implicit event quantification that lies behind adverb-dropping inferences (Clark 1970; Fulton 1979), singular causal statements (Horgan 1978, 1982; Wilson 1985, Needham 1988, 1994, Mellor 1991, 1995), and so on. On the face of it, it appears that questions of logical form leave the existential issue undecided, at least insofar as an event-committing analysis automatically turns into an eliminativist paraphrase when read in the opposite direction (and vice versa).
Another issue that appears to be undecided concerns so-called identity criteria for events, which has been the focus of an intense debate (Bradie 1983; Pfeifer 1989; Mackie 1997). Is John’s walk the same event as his pleasant walk? Was Brutus’s stabbing of Caesar the same event as his killing of Caesar? Was it the same as the violent assassination of Caesar? Some philosophers take these to be metaphysical questions—questions whose answers call for adequate identity criteria, which must be provided before we are allowed to take our event talk seriously. In this sense, different conceptions of events tend to suggest different answers, and widely varying ones. At one extreme we find the radical “unifiers”, who take events to be as coarse-grained as ordinary objects (Quine 1985; Lemmon 1967); at the other the radical “multipliers”, who take events to be as fine-grained as facts (Kim 1966; Goldman 1971); and in between several moderate variants (Davidson 1969; Davis 1970; Thalberg 1971; Thomson 1971; Brand 1977; Cleland 1991; Engel 1994; Jones 2013). Other philosophers, however, regard questions of identity to be first and foremost semantic questions—questions about the way we talk and about what we say. No metaphysical theory, it is said, can settle the semantics of ordinary event talk, hence there is no way of determining the truth or falsity of an event identity statement exclusively on the basis of one’s metaphysical views. Which events a statement speaks of depends heavily (more heavily than with ordinary material objects) on local context and unprincipled intuitions (Bennett 1988). If so, then the whole identity issue is undecidable, since one is demanding metaphysical answers to questions that are in large part semantical.
Bibliography
Surveys
- Casati, R., and Varzi, A. C. (eds.), 1996, Events, Dartmouth, Aldershot (referred to below as Events)
- –––, 1997, Fifty Years of Events. An Annotated Bibliography 1947 to 1997, Bowling Green (OH), Philosophy Documentation Center.
Cited Works
- Ackrill, J. L.,1965, ‘Aristotle’s Distinction Between Energeia and Kinêsis’, in R. Bambrough (ed.), New Essays on Plato and Aristotle, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, pp. 121–141.
- Anscombe, G. E. M, 1957, Intention, Oxford: Blackwell (second edition 1963).
- –––, 1979, ‘Under a Description’, Noûs, 13: 219–233; reprinted in Events, pp. 303–317.
- Armstrong, D. M., 1999, ‘The Open Door’, in H. Sankey (ed.), Causation and Laws of Nature, Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 175–185.
- Bach, K., 1980, ‘Actions Are Not Events’, Mind, 89: 114–120; reprinted in Events, pp. 343–349.
- –––, 2010, ‘Refraining, Omitting, and Negative Acts’, in T. O’Connor and C. Sandis (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 50–57.
- Bach, E., 1981, ‘On Time, Tense and Aspect: An Essay in English Metaphysics’ , in P. Cole (ed.), Radical Pragmatics, New York: Academic Press, 63–81.
- –––, 1986, ‘The Algebra of Events’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 9: 5–16; reprinted Events, pp. 497–508.
- Barwise, K. J., and Perry, J., 1981, ‘Semantic Innocence and Uncompromising Situations’, in P. A. French et al. (eds.), Foundations of Analytic Philosophy (Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 6), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 387–403.
- –––, 1983, Situations and Attitudes, Cambridge (MA): MIT Press.
- Beebee, H., 2004, ‘Causing and Nothingness’, in J. Collins et al. (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals, Cambridge (MA): MIT Press, pp. 291–308.
- Belnap, N., and Perloff, M., 1988, ‘Seeing to It that: A Canonical Form for Agentives’, Theoria, 54: 175–199.
- Bennett, J., 1966, ‘Whatever the Consequences’, Analysis, 26: 83–102.
- –––, 1988, Events and Their Names, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- –––, 1996, ‘What Events Are’, in Events, pp. 137–151.
- Bernard, T., and Champollion, L., 2018, ‘Negative Events in Compositional Semantics’, in S. Maspong, B. Stefánsdóttir, K. Blake, and F. Davis (eds.), Proceedings of the 28th Semantics and Linguistic Theory Conference, Washington, DC: Linguistic Society of America, pp. 512–532.
- Bernstein, S., 2014, ‘Omissions as Possibilities’, Philosophical Studies, 167: 1–23.
- Bishop, J., 1983, ‘Agent-Causation’, Mind, 92: 61–79.
- Bradie, M., 1983, ‘Recent Work on Criteria for Event Identity, 1967–1979’, Philosophy Research Archives, 9: 29–77.
- Brand, M., 1971, ‘The Language of Not Doing’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 8: 45–53.
- –––, 1977, ‘Identity Conditions for Events’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 14: 329–337; reprinted in Events, pp. 363–371.
- –––, 1984, Intending and Acting. Toward a Naturalized Action Theory, Cambridge (MA): MIT Press.
- Brandl, J., 1997, ‘Recurrent Problems. On Chisholm’s Two Theories of Events’, in L. E. Hahn (ed.), The Philosophy of R. M. Chisholm, La Salle (IL): Open Court, pp. 457–477.
- –––, 2000, ‘Do Events Recur?’, in J. Higginbotham et al. (eds.), 2000, pp. 95–104.
- Broad, C. D., 1923, Scientific Thought, New York: Harcourt.
- Campbell, K., 1981, ‘The Metaphysic of Abstract Particulars’, in P. A. French et al. (eds.), Foundations of Analytic Philosophy (Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 6), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 477–488.
- Campbell, N., 1998, ‘Anomalous Monism and the Charge of Epiphenomenalism’, Dialectica, 52: 23–39.
- –––, 2005, ‘Explanatory Epiphenomenalism’, Philosophical Quarterly, 55: 437–451.
- Casati, R., and Varzi, A. C., 2008, ‘Event Concepts’, in T. F. Shipley and J. Zacks (eds.), Understanding Events: From Perception to Action, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 31–54.
- Chisholm, R. M., 1964, ‘The Descriptive Element in the Concept of Action’, Journal of Philosophy, 61: 613–24.
- –––, 1970, ‘Events and Propositions’, Noûs, 4: 15–24; reprinted in Events, pp. 89–98.
- –––, 1971, ‘States of Affairs Again’, Noûs, 5: 179–189.
- Clark, R., 1970, ‘Concerning the Logic of Predicate Modifiers’, Noûs, 4: 311–335.
- Clarke, R., 2014, Omissions: Agency, Metaphysics, and Responsibility, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Cleland, C., 1991, ‘On the Individuation of Events’, Synthese, 86: 229–154; reprinted in Events, pp. 373–398.
- Cresswell, M. J., 1979, ‘Interval Semantics for Some Event Expressions’, in R. Bäuerle et al. (eds.), Semantics from Different Points of View, Berlin: Springer, pp. 90–116.
- –––, 1986, ‘Why Objects Exist but Events Occur’, Studia Logica, 45: 371–375; reprinted in Events, pp. 449–453.
- Crowther, T., 2011, ‘The Matter of Events’, Review of Metaphysics, 65: 3–39.
- –––, 2018, ‘Processes as Continuants and Process as Stuff’, in R. Stout (ed.), Process, Action, and Experience, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 58–81.
- Danto, A., 1966, ‘Freedom and Forbearance’, in K. Lehrer (ed.), Freedom and Determinism, New York: Random House, pp. 45–63.
- Davidson, D., 1967a, ‘The Logical Form of Action Sentences’, in N. Rescher (ed.), The Logic of Decision and Action, Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 81–95; reprinted in Events, pp. 3–17, and in Davidson 1980, pp. 105–122.
- –––, 1967b, ‘Causal Relations’, Journal of Philosophy, 64: 691–703; reprinted in Events, pp. 401–413, and in Davidson 1980, pp. 149–162.
- –––, 1969, ‘The Individuation of Events’, in N. Rescher (ed.), Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel, Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 216–34; reprinted in Events, pp. 265–283, and in Davidson 1980, pp. 163–180.
- –––, 1970, ‘Mental Events’, in L. Foster and J. W. Swanson (eds.), Experience and Theory, Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, pp. 79–101; reprinted in Davidson 1980, pp. 207–227.
- –––, 1980, Essays on Actions and Events, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- –––, 1993, ‘Thinking Causes’, in J. Heil and A. R. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 3–17.
- Davis, L. H., 1970, ‘Individuation of Actions’, The Journal of Philosophy, 67: 520–530; reprinted in Events, pp. 351–361.
- de Swart, H., 1996, ‘Meaning and Use of not … until’, Journal of Semantics, 13: 221–263.
- Dowe, P., 2001, ‘A Counterfactual Theory of Prevention and “Causation” by Omission’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79: 216–226.
- Dowty, D. R., 1979, Word Meaning and Montague Grammar. The Semantics of Verbs and Times in Generative Semantics and Montague’s PTQ, Reidel: Dordrecht.
- Dretske, F., 1967, ‘Can Events Move?’, Mind, 76: 479–492; reprinted in Events, pp. 415–428.
- Ducasse, C. J., 1926, ‘On the Nature and the Observability of the Causal Relation’, Journal of Philosophy, 23: 57–68.
- Engel, M., Jr, 1994, ‘Coarsening Brand on Events, While Proliferating Davidsonian Events’, Grazer Philosophische Studien, 47: 155–183.
- Fischer, J. M., 1997, ‘Responsibility, Control, and Omissions’, Journal of Ethics, 1: 45–64.
- Foot, P., 1984, ‘Killing and Letting Die’, in J. L. Garfield and P. Hennessey (eds.), Abortion: Moral and Legal Perspectives, Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, pp. 177–183.
- Forbes, G., 1993, ‘Time, Events and Modality’, in R. Le Poidevin and M. MacBeath (eds.), The Philosophy of Time, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 80–95.
- Foster, J., 1991, The Immaterial Self, London and New York: Routledge.
- Freed, A., 1979, The Semantics of English Aspectual Complementation, Dordrecht: Reidel.
- Fulton, J. A., 1979, ‘An Intensional Logic of Predicates’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 20: 811–822.
- Galton, A. P., 1984, The Logic of Aspect. An Axiomatic Approach, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- –––, 2006, ‘Processes as Continuants’, in J. Pustejovsky and P. Revesz (eds.), Proceedings of the 13th International Symposiym on Temporal Representation and Reasoning, IEEE Computer Society, p. 187.
- –––, 2008, ‘Experience and History: Processes and their Relation to Events’, Journal of Logic and Computation, 18: 323–340.
- Galton, A., and Mizoguchi, R., 2009, ‘The Water Falls but the Waterfall Does Not Fall: New Perspectives on Objects, Processes and Events’, Applied Ontology, 4: 71–107.
- Geach, P., 1965, ‘Some Problems about Time’, Proceedings of the British Academy, 51: 321–336.
- Gibb, S. C., Lowe, E. J., and Ingthorsson, R. D. (eds.), 2013, Mental Causation and Ontology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Gibson, J. J., 1975, ‘Events Are Perceivable but Time Is Not’, in J. T. Fraser and N. Lawrence (eds.), The Study of Time II. Proceedings of the Second Conference of the International Society for the Study of Time, Berlin: Springer, pp. 295–301.
- Gill, K., 1993, ‘On the Metaphysical Distinction Between Processes and Events’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23: 365–384; reprinted in Events, pp. 477–496.
- Gisborne, N., 2010, The Event Structure of Perception Verbs, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Goldman, A. I., 1970, A Theory of Human Action, New York: Prentice-Hall.
- –––, 1971, ‘The Individuation of Action’, The Journal of Philosophy, 68: 761–774; reprinted in Events, pp. 329–342.
- Goodman, N., 1951, The Structure of Appearance, Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press.
- Gorr, M., 1979, ‘Omissions’, Tulane Studies in Philosophy, 28: 93–102.
- Green, O. H., 1980, ‘Killing and Letting Die’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 17: 195–204.
- Hacker, P. M. S., 1982a, ‘Events, Ontology and Grammar’, Philosophy, 57: 477–486; reprinted in Events, pp. 79–88.
- –––, 1982b, ‘Events and Objects in Space and Time’, Mind, 91: 1–19; reprinted in Events, pp. 429–447.
- Hall, J. C., 1989, ‘Acts and Omissions’, Philosophical Quarterly, 39: 399–408.
- Heil, J., and Mele, A. (eds.), 1993, Mental Causation, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Heller, M., 1990, The Ontology of Physical Objects: Four Dimensional Hunks of Matter, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Hendrickson, N., 2006, ‘Towards a More Plausible Exemplification Theory of Events’, Philosophical Studies, 129: 349–375.
- Higginbotham, J., 1983, ‘The Logic of Perceptual Reports: An Extensional Alternative to Situation Semantics’, Journal of Philosophy, 80: 100–127; reprinted in Events, pp. 19–46.
- –––, 2000, ‘On Events in Linguistic Semantics’, in J. Higginbotham et al. (eds.), 2000, pp. 49–79.
- Higginbotham, J., Pianesi, F., and Varzi, A. C. (eds.), 2000, Speaking of Events, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Higginbotham, J., and Schein, B., 1986, ‘Plurals’, in J. Carter and R.-M. Déchaine (eds.), Proceedings of the Sixteenth Annual Meeting, North-Eastern Linguistic Society, University of Massachusetts at Amherst: GLSA, pp. 161–175.
- Honderich, T., 1982, ‘The Argument for Anomalous Monism’, Analysis, 42: 59–64.
- Horgan, T., 1978, ‘The Case Against Events’, Philosophical Review, 87: 28–47; reprinted in Events, pp. 243–262.
- –––, 1982, ‘Substitutivity and the Causal Connective’, Philosophical Studies, 42: 427–452.
- Hornsby, J., 1980a, Actions, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- –––, 1980b, ‘Arm Raising and Arm Rising’, Philosophy, 55: 73–84.
- Horty, J. F., 2001, Agency and Deontic Logic, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Hunt, I., 2005, ‘Omissions and Preventions as Cases of Genuine Causation’, Philosophical Papers, 34: 209–233.
- Ingarden, R., 1935, ‘Vom formalen Aufbau des individuellen Gegenstandes’, Studia Philosophica, 1: 29–106.
- Johnson, M. L., Jr., 1975, ‘Events as Recurrables’, in K. Lehrer (ed.), Analysis and Metaphysics. Essays in Honor of R. M. Chisholm, Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 209–226.
- Johnson, W. E., 1921, Logic, Vol. I, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Jones, T., 2013, ‘The Constitution of Events’, The Monist, 96: 73–86.
- Kenny, A., 1963, Action, Emotion and Will, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Kim, J., 1966, ‘On the Psycho-Physical Identity Theory’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 3: 277–285.
- –––, 1976, ‘Events as Property Exemplifications’, in M. Brand and D. Walton (eds.), Action Theory, Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 159–177; reprinted in Events, pp. 117–135, and in Kim 1993, pp. 33–52.
- –––, 1993, Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Kleinig, J., 1976, ‘Good Samaritanism’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 5: 382–407.
- Kühl, C. E., 2008, ‘Kinesis and Energeia—and What Follows. Outline of a Typology of Human Actions’, Axiomathes, 18: 303–338.
- Laliberté, S., 2013, ‘Omissions, Absences and Causation’, Ithaque, 13: 99–121.
- Landman, F., 1996, ‘Plurality’, in S. Lappin (ed.), The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 425–457.
- –––, 2000, Events and Plurality. The Jerusalem Lectures, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Lasersohn, P., 1995, Plurality, Conjunction and Events, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Lee, S., 1978, ‘Omissions’, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 16: 339–354.
- Lemmon, E. J., 1967, ‘Comments on D. Davidson’s “The Logical Form of Action Sentences”’, in N. Rescher (ed.), The Logic of Decision and Action, Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press, pp. 96–103.
- Lewis, D. K., 1986a, ‘Events’, in his Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 241–269; reprinted in Events, pp. 213–241.
- –––, 1986b, ‘Causation by Omission’, Postscript D to ‘Causation’, in his Philosophical Papers (Volume 2), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 189–193.
- –––, 1986c, On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford: Blackwell.
- –––, 2004, ‘Void and Object’, in J. Collins et al. (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals, Cambridge (MA): MIT Press, pp. 277–290.
- Link, G., 1998, Algebraic Semantics and in Language and Philosophy, Stanford: CSLI Publications.
- Lombard, L. B., 1979, ‘Events’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 9: 425–460; reprinted in Events, pp. 177–212.
- –––, 1986, Events: a Metaphysical Study, London: Routledge.
- Lombard, L. B., and Hudson, T., 2020, ‘Causation by Absence: Omission Impossible’, Philosophia, first online 04 January 2020. doi:10.1007/s11406-019-00147-8
- Lycan, W. G., 1970, ‘Identifiability-Dependence and Ontological Priority’, The Personalist, 51: 502–513.
- Macdonald, C. A., 1989, Mind-Body Identity Theories, London: Routledge.
- Mackie, D. , 1997, ‘The Individuation of Actions’, Philosophical Quarterly, 47: 38–54.
- Martin, R., 1969, ‘On Events and Event-Descriptions’, in J. Margolis (ed.), Fact and Existence, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 63–73, 97–109.
- Mayo, B., 1961, ‘Objects, Events, and Complementarity’, Mind, 70: 340–361.
- McGrath, S., 2005, ‘Causation by Omission: A Dilemma’, Philosophical Studies, 123: 125–148.
- Mele, A. R. (ed.), 1997, The Philosophy of Action, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2005, ‘Action’, in F. Jackson and M. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 335–357.
- Mellor, D. H., 1980, ‘Things and Causes in Spacetime’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 31: 282–288.
- –––, 1991, ‘Properties and Predicates’, in his Matters of Metaphysics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 170–182.
- –––, 1995, The Facts of Causation, London: Routledge.
- –––, 1998, Real Time II, London: Routledge.
- Menzies, P., 2004, ‘Difference-Making in Context’, in J. Collins et al. (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals, Cambridge (MA): MIT Press, pp. 139–180.
- Mertz, D. W., 1996, Moderate Realism and Its Logic, New Haven: Yale University Press.
- Milanich, P. G., 1984, ‘Allowing, Refraining, and Failing: The Structure of Omissions’, Philosophical Studies, 45: 57–67.
- Moltmann, F., 2013, Abstract Objects and the Semantics of Natural Language, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Montague, R., 1969, ‘On the Nature of Certain Philosophical Entities’, The Monist, 53: 159–194.
- Montmarquet, J. A., 1978 ‘Actions and Bodily Movements’, Analysis, 38: 137–140.
- –––, 1980, ‘Whither States?’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10: 251–256.
- Moravcsik, J. M. E., 1968, ‘Strawson and Ontological Priority’, in R. J. Butler (ed.), Analytical Philosophy, Second Series, New York: Barnes and Noble, pp. 106–119.
- Mossel, B., 2009, ‘Negative Actions’, Philosophia, 37: 307–333.
- Mourelatos, A. P. D., 1978, ‘Events, Processes, and States’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 2: 415–434; reprinted in Events, pp. 457–476.
- Nagel, T., 1965, ‘Physicalism’, Philosophical Review, 74: 339–356.
- Needham, P., 1988, ‘Causation: Relation or Connective?’, Dialectica, 42: 201–219.
- –––, 1994, ‘The Causal Connective’, in J. Faye et al. (eds.), Logic and Causal Reasoning, Berlin: Akademie Verlag, pp. 67–89.
- Parsons, T., 1989, ‘The Progressive in English: Events, States and Processes’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 12: 213–241; reprinted in Events, pp. 47–76.
- –––, 1990, Events in the Semantics of English. A Study in Subatomic Semantics, Cambridge (MA): MIT Press.
- –––, 1991, ‘Tropes and Supervenience’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 51: 629–632.
- Pfeifer, K., 1989, Actions and Other Events: The Unifier-Multiplier Controversy, New York and Bern: Peter Lang.
- Payton, J. D., 2018, ‘How to Identify Negative Actions with Positive Events’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 96: 87–101.
- Peterson, P. L., 1997, Fact, Proposition, Event, Berlin: Springer.
- Pianesi, F., and Varzi, A. C., 1996, ‘Events, Topology, and Temporal Relations’, The Monist, 78: 89–116.
- Pietroski, P. M., 2005, Events and Semantic Architecture, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Prior, A., 1967, Past, Present, and Future, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Przepiórkowski, A., 1999, ‘On Negative Eventualities, Negative Concord, and Negative Yes/No Questions’, in T. Matthews and D. Strolovitch (eds.), Proceeding of Semantics and Linguistic Theory 9, Ithaca (NY): CLC Publications, pp. 237–254.
- Quine, W. V. O., 1950, ‘Identity, Ostension and Hyposthasis’, Journal of Philosophy, 47: 621–633.
- –––, 1970, Philosophy of Logic, Englewood Cliffs (NJ): Prentice-Hall.
- –––, 1985, ‘Events and Reification’, in E. LePore and B. P. McLaughlin (eds.), Actions and Events. Perspectives in the Philosophy of Donald Davidson, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 162–171.
- Quinton, A., 1979, ‘Objects and Events’, Mind, 88: 197–214.
- Ramsey, F. P., 1927, ‘Facts and Propositions’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 7: 153–170.
- Reichenbach, H., 1947, Elements of Symbolic Logic, New York: Macmillan.
- Robering, K., 2014, Events, Arguments, and Aspects: Topics in the Semantics of Verbs, Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
- Roberts, J. H., 1979, ‘Activities and Performances Considered as Objects and Events’, Philosophical Studies, 35: 171–185.
- Robinson, H., 1982, Matter and Sense: A Critique of Contemporary Materialism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Rothstein, S. (ed.), 1998, Events and Grammar, Dordrecht, Kluwer.
- Russell, B., 1914, Our Knowledge of the External World, London: Allen & Unwin.
- –––, 1927, The Analysis of Matter, London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.
- Ryle, G., 1949, The Concept of Mind, London: Hutchinson.
- –––, ‘Negative “Actions”’, Hermathena, 81: 81–93.
- Sartorio, C., 2009, ‘Omissions and Causalism’, Noûs, 43: 513–530.
- Schein, B., 1993, Plurals and Events, Cambridge (MA): MIT Press.
- Searle, J., 1983 Intentionality. An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Segerberg, K., 1989, ‘Bringing It About’, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 18: 327–347.
- Sher, G., 1973, ‘Causal Explanation and the Vocabulary of Action’, Mind, 8: 22–30.
- Sider, T. 2001, Four-Dimensionalism. An Ontology of Persistence and Time, New York: Oxford University Press.
- Silver, K., 2018, ‘Omissions as Events and Actions’, Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 4: 33–48.
- Simons, P. M., 2000, ‘Continuants and Occurrents’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 74: 59–75.
- –––, 2003, ‘Events’, in M. J. Loux and D. W. Zimmerman (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 358–385.
- Smith, C., 1991, The Parameter of Aspect, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Steward, H., 1997, The Ontology of Mind: Events, Processes, and States, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2013, ‘Processes, Continuants, and Individuals’, Mind, 122: 781–812.
- –––, 2015, ‘What is a Continuant?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume, 89: 109–123.
- Stout, G. F., 1923, ‘Are the Characteristic of Things Universal or Particular?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 3: 114–122.
- Stout, R., 1997, ‘Processes’, Philosophy, 72: 19–27.
- –––, 2003, ‘The Life of a Process’, in G. Debrock (ed.), Process Pragmatism. Essays on a Quiet Philosophical Revolution, Amsterdam: Rodopi, pp. 145–157.
- –––, 2016, ‘The Category of Occurrent Continuants’, Mind, 125: 41–62.
- Strawson, P. F., 1959, Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics, London: Methuen.
- Taylor, B., 1977, ‘Tense and Continuity’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 1: 119–220.
- –––, 1985, Modes of Occurrence: Verbs, Adverbs and Events, Oxford: Blackwell.
- Tegtmeier, E., 2000, ‘Events as Facts’, in J. Faye et al. (eds.), Events, Facts and Things, Amsterdam, Rodopi, pp. 219–228.
- Tenny, C., and Pustejovsky, J. (eds.), 2000, Events as Grammatical Objects: The Converging Perspectives of Lexical Semantics, Logical Semantics and Syntax, Stanford (CA): CSLI Publications.
- Thalberg, I., 1971, ‘Singling out Actions, their Properties and Components’, Journal of Philosophy, 68: 781–787.
- Thomason, S. K., 1989, ‘Free Construction of Time from Events’, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 18: 43–67.
- Thomson, J. J., 1971, ‘Individuating Actions’, Journal of Philosophy, 68: 771–781.
- –––, 1977, Acts and Other Events, Ithaca (NY): Cornell University Press.
- –––, 2003, ‘Causation: Omissions’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66: 81–103.
- Tiles, J. E., 1981, Things that Happen, Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.
- Tuomela, R., and Sandu, G., 1994, ‘Action as Seeing to It that Something is the Case’, in P. Humphreys (ed.), Patrick Suppes: Scientific Philosopher (Volume 3), Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 193–221.
- van Benthem, J., 1983, The Logic of Time, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- van Lambalgen, M., and Hamm, F., 2005, The Proper Treatment of Events, Oxford: Blackwell.
- Varzi, A. C., 2007, ‘Omissions and Causal Explanations’, in F. Castellani and J. Quitterer (eds.), Agency and Causation in the Human Sciences, Paderborn: Mentis, pp. 155–167.
- –––, 2008, ‘Failures, Omissions, and Negative Descriptions’, in K. Korta and J. Garmendia (eds.), Meaning, Intentions, and Argumentation, Stanford (CA): CSLI Publications, pp. 61–75.
- Vendler, Z., 1957, ‘Verbs and Times’, Philosophical Review, 66: 143–60.
- –––, 1967, ‘Facts and Events’, Chapter 5 of his Linguistics in Philosophy, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 122–146.
- Verkuyl, H. J., 1989, ‘Aspectual Classes and Aspectual Composition’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 12: 39–94.
- Vermazen, B., 1985, ‘Negative Acts’, in B. Vermazen and M. B. Hintikka (eds.), Essays on Davidson: Actions and Events, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 93–104.
- Vlach, F., 1983, ‘On Situation Semantics for Perception’, Synthese, 54: 129–152.
- von Kutschera, F., 1993, ‘Sebastian’s Strolls’, Grazer Philosophische Studien, 45: 75–88.
- von Wright, G. H., 1963, Norm and Action. A Logical Inquiry, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Walker, A. G, 1947, ‘Durées et instants’, Revue Scientifique, 85: 131–134.
- Walter, S., and Heckmann, H. (eds.), 2003, Physicalism and Mental Causation: The Metaphysics of Mind and Action, Exeter: Imprint Academic.
- Walton, D. N., 1980, ‘Omitting, Refraining and Letting Happen’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 17: 319–326.
- Weinryb, E., 1980, ‘Omissions and Responsibility’, Philosophical Quarterly, 30: 1–18.
- Whitehead, A. N., 1919, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- –––, 1929, Process and Reality. An Essay in Cosmology, New York: Macmillan.
- Williams, D. C., 1953, ‘On the Elements of Being’, Review of Metaphysics, 7: 3–18 (Part I), 171–192 (Part II).
- Wilson, F., 1985, Explanation, Causation and Deduction, Dordrecht: Reidel.
- Wilson, N. L., 1974, ‘Facts, Events, and Their Identity Conditions’, Philosophical Studies, 25: 303–321.
- Williams, B., 1995, ‘Acts and Omissions, Doing and Not Doing’, in R. Hursthouse et al. (eds.), Virtues and Reasons. Philippa Foot and Moral Theory, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 331–340.
Further Readings
- Bennett, J., 1995, The Act Itself, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Bohnemeyer, J., and Pederson, E., 2011, Event Representation in Language and Cognition. New York: Cambridge University Press.
- Bott, O., 2010, The Processing of Events, Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
- Demonte, V., and McNally, L. (eds.), 2012, Telicity, Change, and State: A Cross-Categorial View of Event Structure, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Dölling, J., Heyde-Zybatow, T., and Schäfer, M. (eds.), 2008, Event Structures in Linguistic Form and Interpretation, Berlin: de Gruyter.
- Faye, J., Urchs, M., and Scheffler, U. (eds.), 2001, Things, Facts and Events, Amsterdam: Rodopi.
- Martin, R. M., 1978, Events, Reference and Logical Form, Washington (DC): Catholic University of America Press.
- Radvansky, G. A., and Zacks, J. M., 2014, Event Cognition, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Rappaport Hovav, M., Doron, E., and Sichel, I. (eds.,) 2010, Syntax, Lexical Semantics, and Event Structure, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Rothstein, S., 2004, Structuring Events. A Study in the Semantics of Lexical Aspect, Oxford: Blackwell.
- Schilder, F., Katz, G., Pustejovsky, J. (eds.), 2007, Annotating, Extracting and Reasoning about Time and Events, Berlin: Springer.
- Shipley, T. F., and Zacks, J. M. (eds.), 2008, Understanding Events: From Perception to Action, New York: Oxford University Press.
- Stoecker, R., 1992. Was sind Ereignisse? Eine Studie zur analytischen Ontologie, Berlin: De Gruyter.
- Stout, R. (ed.), 2018, Process, Action, and Experience, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Truswell, R., 2011, Events, Phrases, and Questions, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- van Voorst, J., 1988, Event Structure, Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
- Vermazen, B., and Hintikka, M. B. (eds.), 1985, Essays on Davidson: Actions and Events, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Zacks, J. M., 2020, Ten Lectures on the Representation of Events in Language, Perception, Memory, and Action Control, Leiden: Brill.
- Zucchi, S., 1993, The Language of Propositions and Events. Issues in the Syntax and Semantics of Nominalization, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Academic Tools
How to cite this entry. Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society. Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.
Other Internet Resources
- Fifty Years of Events: An Annotated Bibliography 1947 to 1997, by Roberto Casati and Achille C. Varzi.
- A Bibliography on Action and Intention, by Élisabeth Pacherie.
- Project on the Annotated Bibliography of Contemporary Research on Tense, Aspect, Aktionsart, and Related Areas, by Robert I. Binnick.