Quantum Approaches to Consciousness

First published Tue Nov 30, 2004; substantive revision Tue Jun 2, 2015

It is widely accepted that consciousness or, more generally, mental activity is in some way correlated to the behavior of the material brain. Since quantum theory is the most fundamental theory of matter that is currently available, it is a legitimate question to ask whether quantum theory can help us to understand consciousness. Several programmatic approaches answering this question affirmatively, proposed in recent decades, will be surveyed. It will be pointed out that they make different epistemological assumptions, refer to different neurophysiological levels of description, and use quantum theory in different ways. For each of the approaches discussed, problematic and promising features will be equally highlighted.

1. Introduction

The problem of how mind and matter are related to each other has many facets, and it can be approached from many different starting points. Of course, the historically leading disciplines in this respect are philosophy and psychology, which were later joined by behavioral science, cognitive science and neuroscience. In addition, the physics of complex systems and quantum physics have played stimulating roles in the discussion from their beginnings.

As regards the issue of complexity, this is quite evident: the brain is one of the most complex systems we know. The study of neural networks, their relation to the operation of single neurons and other important topics do and will profit a lot from complex systems approaches. As regards quantum physics, there can be no reasonable doubt that quantum events occur and are efficacious in the brain as elsewhere in the material world—including biological systems![1] But it is controversial whether these events are efficacious and relevant for those aspects of brain activity that are correlated with mental activity.

The original motivation in the early 20th century for relating quantum theory to consciousness was essentially philosophical. It is fairly plausible that conscious free decisions (“free will”) are problematic in a perfectly deterministic world,[2] so quantum randomness might indeed open up novel possibilities for free will. (On the other hand, randomness is problematic for volition!)

Quantum theory introduced an element of randomness standing out against the previous deterministic worldview, in which randomness, if it occurred at all, simply indicated our ignorance of a more detailed description (as in statistical physics). In sharp contrast to such epistemic randomness, quantum randomness in processes such as spontaneous emission of light, radioactive decay, or other examples of state reduction was considered a fundamental feature of nature, independent of our ignorance or knowledge. To be precise, this feature refers to individual quantum events, whereas the behavior of ensembles of such events is statistically determined. The indeterminism of individual quantum events is constrained by statistical laws.

Other features of quantum theory, which were found attractive in discussing issues of consciousness, were the concepts of complementarity and entanglement. Pioneers of quantum physics such as Planck, Bohr, Schrödinger, Pauli (and others) emphasized the various possible roles of quantum theory in reconsidering the old conflict between physical determinism and conscious free will. For informative overviews with different focal points see e.g., Squires (1990), Kane (1996), Butterfield (1998), Suarez and Adams (2013).

In this contribution, some popular approaches for applying quantum theory to consciousness will be surveyed and compared, most of them speculative, with varying degrees of elaboration and viability. Section 2 outlines two fundamentally different philosophical options for conceiving of relations between material and mental states of systems. Section 3 addresses three different neurophysiological levels of description, to which particular different quantum approaches refer. After some introductory remarks, Section 4 sketches the individual approaches themselves—Section 4.2: Stapp, Section 4.3: from Umezawa to Vitiello, Section 4.4: Beck and Eccles, Section 4.5: Penrose and Hameroff, Section 4.6: “dual-aspect” approaches such as have been tentatively proposed by Pauli and Jung as well as Bohm and Hiley, and Section 4.7: purely mental features, mathematically characterized by formal structures typical for quantum theory (pioneered by Aerts and colleagues). Section 5 offers some comparative conclusions.

2. Philosophical Background Assumptions

Variants of the dichotomy between mind and matter range from their fundamental distinction at a primordial level of description to the emergence of mind (consciousness) from the brain as an extremely sophisticated and highly developed material system. Informative overviews can be found in Popper and Eccles (1977), Chalmers (1996), and Pauen (2001).

One important aspect of all discussions about the relation between mind and matter is the distinction between descriptive and explanatory approaches. For instance, correlation is a descriptive term with empirical relevance, while causation is an explanatory term associated with theoretical attempts to understand correlations. Causation implies correlations between cause and effect, but this does not always apply the other way around: correlations between two systems can result from a common cause in their history rather than from a direct causal interaction.

In the fundamental sciences, one typically speaks of causal relations in terms of interactions. In physics, for instance, there are four fundamental kinds of interactions (electromagnetic, weak, strong, gravitational) which serve to explain the correlations that are observed in physical systems. As regards the mind-matter problem, the situation is more difficult. Far from a theoretical understanding in this field, the existing body of knowledge essentially consists of empirical correlations between material and mental states. These correlations are descriptive, not explanatory; they are not causally conditioned. It is (for some purposes) interesting to know that particular brain areas are activated during particular mental activities; but this does, of course, not explain why they are. Thus, it would be premature to talk about mind-matter interactions in the sense of causal relations. For the sake of terminological clarity, the neutral notion of relations between mind and matter will be used in this article.

In many approaches used to discuss relations between material [ma] brain states and mental [me] states of consciousness, these relations are conceived in a direct way (A):

[ma] image 1 [me]

This provides a minimal framework to study reduction, supervenience, or emergence relations (Kim 1998; Stephan 1999) which can yield both monistic and dualistic pictures. For instance, there is the classical stance of strong reduction, claiming that all mental states and properties can be reduced to the material domain (materialism) or even to physics (physicalism).[3] This point of view claims that it is both necessary and sufficient to explore and understand the material domain, e.g., the brain, in order to understand the mental domain, e.g., consciousness. More or less, this leads to a monistic picture, in which any need to discuss mental states is eliminated right away or at least considered as epiphenomenal. While mind-brain correlations are still legitimate though causally inefficacious from an epiphenomenalist point of view, eliminative materialism renders even correlations irrelevant.

The most discussed counterarguments against the validity of such strong reductionist approaches are qualia arguments, which emphasize the impossibility for materialist accounts to properly incorporate the quality of the subjective experience of a mental state, the “what it is like” (Nagel 1974) to be in that state. This leads to a gap between third-person and first-person accounts for which Chalmers (1995) has coined the notion of the “hard problem of consciousness”. Another, less discussed counterargument is that the physical domain itself is not causally closed. Any solution of fundamental equations of motion (be it experimentally, numerically, or analytically) requires to fix boundary conditions and initial conditions which are not given by the fundamental laws of nature (Primas 2002). This causal gap applies to classical physics as well as quantum physics, where a basic indeterminacy due to collapse make it even more challenging. A third class of counterarguments refer to the difficulties to include notions of temporal present and nowness in a physical description (Franck 2004, 2008).

However, direct relations between mental and material states can also be conceived in a non-reductive fashion. A number of variants of emergence (Stephan 1999) are prominent examples. Mental states and/or properties can be considered as emergent if the material brain is not necessary or not sufficient to explore and understand them.[4] This leads to a dualistic picture (less radical and more plausible than Cartesian dualism) in which residua remain if one attempts to reduce the mental to the material. Within a dualistic scheme of thinking, it becomes almost inevitable to discuss the question of causal influence between mental and material states. In particular, the causal efficacy of mental states upon brain states (“downward causation”) has recently attracted growing interest (Velmans, 2002; Ellis et al. 2011).[5]

As an alternative to (A), it is possible to conceive mind-matter relations indirectly (B), via a third category:

[ma]     [me]
image 3image 3
[mame]

This third category, here denoted [mame], is often regarded as being neutral with respect to the distinction between [ma] and [me], i.e., psychophysically neutral. In scenario (B), issues of reduction and emergence concern the relation between the unseparated “background reality” [mame] and the distinguished aspects [ma] and [me]. This will be discussed in more detail in Section 4.6.

Such a “dual aspect” option receives increasing attention in contempory discussions, and it has a long tradition. Early versions go back as far as Spinoza. In the early days of psychophysics in the 19th century, Fechner (1861) and Wundt (1911) advocated related views. Whitehead, the modern pioneer of process philosophy, referred to mental and physical poles of “actual occasions”, which themselves transcend their bipolar appearances (Whitehead 1978). Many approaches in the tradition of Feigl (1967) and Smart (1963), called “identity theories”, conceive mental and material states as essentially identical “central states”, yet considered from different perspectives. Other variants of this idea have been suggested by Jung and Pauli (1955) [see also Meier (2001)], involving Jung's conception of a psychophysically neutral, archetypal order, or by Bohm and Hiley (Bohm 1990; Bohm & Hiley 1993; Hiley 2001), referring to an implicate order which unfolds into the different explicate domains of the mental and the material.

Velmans (2002, 2009) has developed a similar approach, backed up with empirical material from psychology, and Strawson (2003) has proposed a “real materialism” which uses a closely related scheme. Another proponent of dual aspect thinking is Chalmers (1996), who considers the possibility that the underlying, psychophysically neutral level of description could be best characterized in terms of information.

Before proceeding further, it should be emphasized that many present-day approaches prefer to distinguish between first-person and third-person perspectives rather than mental and material states. This terminology serves to highlight the discrepancy between immediate conscious experiences (“qualia”) and their description, be it behavioral, neural, or biophysical. The notion of the “hard problem” of consciousness research refers to bridging the gap between first-person experience and third-person accounts of it. In the present contribution, mental conscious states are implicitly assumed to be related to first-person experience. This does not mean, however, that the problem of how to define consciousness precisely is considered as resolved. Ultimately, it will be (at least) as difficult to define a mental state in rigorous terms as it is to define a material state.

3. Neurophysiological Levels of Description

3.1 Neuronal Assemblies

A mental system can be in many different conscious, intentional, phenomenal mental states. In a hypothetical state space, a sequence of such states forms a trajectory representing what is often called the stream of consciousness. Since different subsets of the state space are typically associated with different stability properties, a mental state can be assumed to be more or less stable, depending on its position in the state space. Stable states are distinguished by a residence time at that position longer than that of metastable or unstable states. If a mental state is stable with respect to perturbations, it “activates” a mental representation encoding a content that is consciously perceived.

Moving from this purely psychological, or cognitive, description to its neurophysiological counterpart leads us to the question: What is the neural correlate of a mental representation? According to standard accounts (cf. Noë & Thompson (2004) for discussion), mental representations are correlated with the activity of neuronal assemblies, i.e., ensembles of several thousands of coupled neurons. The neural correlate of a mental representation can be characterized by the fact that the connectivities, or couplings, among those neurons form an assembly confined with respect to its environment, to which connectivities are weaker than within the assembly. The neural correlate of a mental representation is activated if the neurons forming the assembly operate more actively, e.g., produce higher firing rates, than in their default mode.

figure 1
Figure 1: Balance between inhibitory and excitatory connections among neurons.

In order to achieve a stable operation of an activated neuronal assembly, there must be a subtle balance between inhibitory and excitatory connections among neurons (cf. Figure 1). If the transfer function of individual neurons is strictly monotonic, i.e., increasing input leads to increasing output, assemblies are difficult to stabilize. For this reason, results establishing a non-monotonic transfer function with a maximal output at intermediate input are of high significance for the modeling of neuronal assemblies (Kuhn et al. 2004). For instance, network models using lattices of coupled maps with quadratic maximum (Kaneko and Tsuda 2000) are paradigmatic examples of such behavior. These and other familiar models of neuronal assemblies (for an overview see Anderson and Rosenfeld 1988) are mostly formulated in a way not invoking well-defined elements of quantum theory. An explicit exception is the approach by Umezawa, Vitiello and others (see Section 4.3).

3.2 Single Neurons and Synapses

The fact that neuronal assemblies are mostly described in terms of classical behavior does not rule out that classically undescribable quantum effects may be significant if one focuses on individual constituents of assemblies, i.e., single neurons or interfaces between them. These interfaces, through which the signals between neurons propagate, are called synapses. There are electrical and chemical synapses, depending on whether they transmit a signal electrically or chemically.

At electrical synapses, the current generated by the action potential at the presynaptic neuron flows directly into the postsynaptic cell, which is physically connected to the presynaptic terminal by a so-called gap junction. At chemical synapses, there is a cleft between pre- and postsynaptic cell. In order to propagate a signal, a chemical transmitter (glutamate) is released at the presynaptic terminal. This release process is called exocytosis. The transmitter diffuses across the synaptic cleft and binds to receptors at the postsynaptic membrane, thus opening an ion channel (Kandel et al. 2000, part III; see Fig. 2). Chemical transmission is slower than electric transmission.

Figure 2
Figure 2: Release of neurotransmitters at the synaptic cleft (exocytosis).

A model developed by Beck and Eccles applies concrete quantum mechanical features to describe details of the process of exocytosis. Their model proposes that quantum processes are relevant for exocytosis and, moreover, are tightly related to states of consciousness. This will be discussed in more detail in Section 4.4.

At this point, another approach developed by Flohr (2000) should be mentioned, for which chemical synapses with a specific type of receptors, so-called NMDA receptors,[6] are of paramount significance. Briefly, Flohr observes that the specific plasticity of NMDA receptors is a necessary condition for the formation of extended stable neuronal assemblies correlated to (higher-order) mental representations which he identifies with conscious states. Moreover, he indicates a number of mechanisms caused by anaesthetic agents, which block NMDA receptors and consequently lead to a loss of consciousness. Flohr's approach is physicalistic and reductive, and it is entirely independent of any specific quantum ideas.

3.3 Microtubuli

The lowest neurophysiological level, at which quantum processes have been proposed as a correlate to consciousness, is the level at which the interior of single neurons is considered: their cytoskeleton. It consists of protein networks essentially made up of two kinds of structures, neurofilaments and microtubuli (Fig. 3, left), which are essential for various transport processes within neurons (as well as other cells). Microtubuli are long polymers usually constructed of 13 longitudinal α and β-tubulin dimers arranged in a tubular array with an outside diameter of about 25 nm (Fig. 3, right). For more details see Kandel et al. (2000), Chap. II.4.

Figure 3a       Figure 3b

Figure 3: (left) microtubuli and neurofilaments, the width of the figure corresponds to approximately 700nm; (right) tubulin dimers, consisting of α- and β-monomers, constituting a microtubule.

The tubulins in microtubuli are the substrate which, in Hameroff's proposal, is used to embed Penrose's theoretical framework neurophysiologically. As will be discussed in more detail in Section 4.5, tubulin states are assumed to depend on quantum events, so that quantum coherence among different tubulins is possible. Further, a crucial thesis in the scenario of Penrose and Hameroff is that the (gravitation-induced) collapse of such coherent tubulin states corresponds to elementary acts of consciousness.

4. Examples

4.1 Ways to Use Quantum Theory

In the following, (some of) the better known and partly worked out approaches that use concepts of quantum theory for inquiries into the nature of consciousness will be presented and discussed. For this purpose, the philosophical distinctions A/B (Section 2) and the neurophysiological distinctions addressed in Section 3 will serve as guidelines to classify the respective quantum approaches in a systematic way. However, some preliminary qualifications concerning different ways to use quantum theory are in order.

There are quite a number of accounts discussing quantum theory in relation to consciousness that adopt basic ideas of quantum theory in a purely metaphorical manner. Quantum theoretical terms such as entanglement, superposition, collapse, complementarity, and others are used without specific reference to how they are defined precisely and how they are applicable to specific situations. For instance, conscious acts are just postulated to be interpretable somehow analogously to physical acts of measurement, or correlations in psychological systems are just postulated to be interpretable somehow analogously to physical entanglement. Such accounts may provide fascinating science fiction, and they may even be important to inspire nuclei of ideas to be worked out in detail. But unless such detailed work leads beyond vague metaphors and analogies, they do not yet represent scientific progress. Approaches falling into this category will not be discussed in this contribution.

A second category includes approaches that use the status quo of present-day quantum theory to describe neurophysiological and/or neuropsychological processes. Among these approaches, the one with the longest history was initiated by von Neumann in the 1930s, later taken up by Wigner, and currently championed by Stapp. It can be roughly characterized as the proposal to consider intentional conscious acts as intrinsically correlated with physical state reductions. Another fairly early idea dating back to Ricciardi and Umezawa in the 1960s is to treat mental states, particularly memory states, in terms of vacuum states of quantum fields. A prominent proponent of this approach at present is Vitiello. Finally, there is the idea suggested by Beck and Eccles in the 1990s, according to which quantum mechanical processes, relevant for the description of exocytosis at the synaptic cleft, can be influenced by mental intentions.

The third category refers to further developments or generalizations of present-day quantum theory. An obvious candidate in this respect is the proposal by Penrose to relate elementary conscious acts to gravitation-induced reductions of quantum states. Ultimately, this requires the framework of a future theory of quantum gravity which is far from having been developed. Together with Penrose, Hameroff has argued that microtubuli might be the right place to look for such state reductions. Another set of approaches is based on generalizations of quantum theory beyond quantum physics proper. In this way, formally generalized concepts such as complementarity and entanglement can be applied to phenomena in both mental and material domains. In particular, relations between the two can be conceived in terms of dual aspects of one underlying “reality”. This conception, drawing on the philosophy of Spinoza, has been considered attractive by 20th century scientists such as Bohr, Pauli, Bohm, Primas, d'Espagnat, and others. Finally, there are generalized quantum approaches addressing purely mental (psychological) phenomena using formal features also employed in quantum theory, such as non-commuting operations or non-Boolean logic, but without involving the full-fledged framework of quantum mechanics or quantum field theory. Some of the applications proposed, e.g., by the groups of Aerts, Atmanspacher, Bruza, Busemeyer, Khrennikov and others will be sketched.

4.2 Stapp: Quantum State Reductions and Conscious Acts

The act or process of measurement is a crucial aspect in the framework of quantum theory, that has been the subject of controversy for more than seven decades now. In his monograph on the mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics, von Neumann (1955, Chap. V.1) introduced, in an ad hoc manner, the projection postulate as a mathematical tool for describing measurement in terms of a discontinuous, non-causal, instantaneous and irreversible act given by (1) the transition of a quantum state to an eigenstate bj of the measured observable B (with a certain probability). This transition is often called the collapse or reduction of the wavefunction, as opposed to (2) the continuous, unitary (reversible) evolution of a system according to the Schrödinger equation.

In Chapter VI, von Neumann (1955) discussed the conceptual distinction between observed and observing system. In this context, he applied (1) and (2) to the general situation of a measured object system (I), a measuring instrument (II), and (the brain of) a human observer (III). His conclusion was that it makes no difference for the result of measurements on (I) whether the boundary between observed and observing system is posited between I and (II & III) or between (I & II) and III. As a consequence, it is inessential whether a detector or the human brain is ultimately referred to as the “observer”.[7]

By contrast to von Neumann's fairly cautious stance, London and Bauer (1939) went much further and proposed that it is indeed human consciousness which completes quantum measurement (see Jammer (1974, Sec. 11.3 or Shimony (1963) for a detailed account). In this way, they attributed a crucial role to consciousness in understanding quantum measurement—a truly radical position. In the 1960s, Wigner (1967) followed up on this proposal,[8] coining his now proverbial example of “Wigner's friend”. In order to describe measurement as a real dynamical process generating irreversible facts, Wigner called for some nonlinear modification of (2) to replace von Neumann's projection (1).[9]

Since the 1980s, Stapp has developed his own point of view on the background of von Neumann and Wigner. In particular, he tries to understand specific features of consciousness in relation to quantum theory. Inspired by von Neumann, Stapp uses the freedom to place the interface between observed and observing system and locates it in the observer's brain. He does not suggest any formal modifications to present-day quantum theory (in particular, he stays essentially within the “orthodox” Hilbert space representation), but adds major interpretational extensions, in particular with respect to a detailed ontological framework.

In his earlier work, Stapp (1993) starts with Heisenberg's distinction between the potential and the actual (Heisenberg 1958), implementing a decisive step beyond the operational Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics. Heisenberg's notion of the actual is related to a measured event in the sense of the Copenhagen interpretation. However, Heisenberg's notion of the potential, of a tendency, relates to the situation before measurement, which expresses the idea of a reality independent of measurement.[10]

Immediately after its actualization, each event holds the tendency for the impending actualization of another, subsequent actual event. Therefore, events are by definition ambiguous. With respect to their actualized aspect, Stapp's essential move is to “attach to each Heisenberg actual event an experiential aspect. The latter is called the feel of this event, and it can be considered to be the aspect of the actual event that gives it its status as an intrinsic actuality” (Stapp 1993, p. 149).

With respect to their tendency aspect, it is tempting to understand events in terms of scheme (B) of Sec. 2. This is related to Whitehead's ontology, in which mental and physical poles of so-called “actual occasions” are considered as psychological and physical aspects of reality. The potential antecedents of actual occasions are psychophysically neutral and refer to a a mode of existence at which mind and matter are unseparated. This is expressed, for instance, by Stapp's notion of a “hybrid ontology” with “both idea-like and matter-like qualities” and “two complementary modes of evolution” (Stapp 1999, 159). Similarities with a dual aspect approach (B) (cf. Section 4.6) can clearly be recognized.

In an interview of 2006, Stapp (2006) specifies some ontological features of his approach with respect to Whitehead's process thinking, where actual occasions rather than matter or mind are fundamental elements of reality. They are conceived as based on a processual rather than a substantial ontology (see the entry on process philosophy). Stapp relates the fundamentally processual nature of actual occasions to both the physical act of state reduction and the correlated psychological intentional act.

Another significant aspect of his approach is the possibility that “conscious intentions of a human being can influence the activities of his brain” (Stapp 1999, 153). Different from the possibly misleading notion of a direct interaction, suggesting an interpretation in terms of scheme (A) of Sec. 2, he describes this feature in a more subtle manner. The requirement that the mental and material outcomes of an actual occasion must match, i.e. be correlated, acts as a constraint on the way in which these outcomes are formed within the actual occasion (cf. Stapp 2006). The notion of interaction is thus replaced by the notion of a constraint set by mind-matter correlations (see also Stapp 2007).

At a level at which conscious mental states and material brain states are distinguished, each conscious experience, according to Stapp (1999, p. 153), has as its physical counterpart a quantum state reduction actualizing “the pattern of activity that is sometimes called the neural correlate of that conscious experience”. More precisely, this pattern of activity may encode an intention and, thus, represent a “template for action”. An intentional decision for an action, preceding the action itself, is then the key for anything like free will in this picture.

As to the quantum aspect of a template for action, Stapp argues that the mental effort, i.e. attention devoted to such intentional acts can protract the lifetime of the neuronal assemblies that represent the templates for action due to quantum Zeno-type effects. Concerning the neurophysiological implementation of this idea, intentional mental states are assumed to correspond to reductions of superposition states of neuronal assemblies. Additional commentary concerning the concepts of attention and intention in relation to James' idea of a holistic stream of consciousness (James 1950) is given in Stapp (1999).

For further progress, it will be mandatory to develop a coherent formal framework for this approach and elaborate on concrete details. For instance, it is not yet worked out precisely how quantum superpositions and their collapses are supposed to occur in neural correlates of conscious events. Some indications are outlined by Schwartz et al. (2005). With these desiderata for future work, the overall conception is conservative insofar as the physical formalism remains unchanged.

This is why Stapp insisted for years that his approach does not change what he calls “orthodox” quantum mechanics, which is essentially encoded in the statistical formulation by von Neumann (1955). From the point of view of standard present-day quantum physics, however, it is certainly unorthodox to include the mental state of observers in the theory. Although it is true that quantum measurement is not yet finally understood in terms of physical theory, introducing mental states as the essential missing link is highly speculative from a contemporary perspective.

This link is a radical conceptual move. In what Stapp now denotes as a “semi-orthodox” approach (Stapp 2015), he proposes that the blind-chance kind of randomness of individual quantum events (“nature's choices”) be reconceived as “not actually random but positively or negatively biased by the positive or negative values in the minds of the observers that are actualized by its (nature's) choices” (p. 187). This hypothesis leads into mental influences on quantum physical processes which are widely unknown territory at present.

4.3 From Umezawa to Vitiello: Quantum Field Theory of Brain States

In the 1960s, Ricciardi and Umezawa (1967) suggested to utilize the formalism of quantum field theory to describe brain states, with particular emphasis on memory. The basic idea is to conceive of memory states in terms of states of many-particle systems, as inequivalent representations of vacuum states of quantum fields.[11] This proposal has gone through several refinements (e.g., Stuart et al. 1978, 1979; Jibu and Yasue 1995). Major recent progress has been achieved by including effects of dissipation, chaos, fractals and quantum noise (Vitiello 1995; Pessa and Vitiello 2003; Vitiello 2012). For readable nontechnical accounts of the approach in its present form, embedded in quantum field theory as of today, see Vitiello (2001, 2002).

Quantum field theory (see the entry on quantum field theory) yields infinitely many representations of the canonical commutation relations, which are inequivalent to the Schrödinger representation of standard quantum mechanics. Such inequivalent representations can be generated by spontaneous symmetry breaking (see the entry on symmetry and symmetry breaking), occurring when the ground state (or the vacuum state) of a system is not invariant under the full group of transformations providing the conservation laws for the system. If symmetry breaks down, collective modes are generated (so-called Nambu-Goldstone boson modes), which propagate over the system and introduce long-range correlations in it.

These correlations are responsible for the emergence of ordered patterns. Unlike in thermal systems, a large number of bosons can be condensed in an ordered state in a highly stable fashion. Roughly speaking, this provides a quantum field theoretical derivation of ordered states in many-body systems described in terms of statistical physics. In the proposal by Umezawa these dynamically ordered states represent coherent activity in neuronal assemblies.

The activation of a neuronal assembly is necessary to make the encoded content consciously accessible. This activation is considered to be initiated by external stimuli. Unless the assembly is activated, its content remains unconscious, unaccessed memory. According to Umezawa, coherent neuronal assemblies correlated to such memory states are regarded as vacuum states; their activation leads to excited states and enables a conscious recollection of the content encoded in the vacuum (ground) state. The stability of such states and the role of external stimuli have been investigated in detail by Stuart et al. (1978, 1979).

A decisive further step in developing the approach has been achieved by taking dissipation into account. Dissipation is possible when the interaction of a system with its environment is considered. Vitiello (1995) describes how the system-environment interaction causes a doubling of the collective modes of the system in its environment. This yields infinitely many differently coded vacuum states, offering the possibility of many memory contents without overprinting. Moreover, dissipation leads to finite lifetimes of the vacuum states, thus representing temporally limited rather than unlimited memory (Alfinito and Vitiello 2000; Alfinito et al. 2001). Finally, dissipation generates a genuine arrow of time for the system, and its interaction with the environment induces entanglement. Pessa and Vitiello (2003) have addressed additional effects of chaos and quantum noise.

Umezawa's proposal addresses the brain as a many-particle system as a whole, where the “particles” are more or less neurons. In the language of Section 3.1, this refers to the level of neuronal assemblies, which correlate directly with mental activity. Another merit of the quantum field theory approach is that it avoids the restrictions of standard quantum mechanics in a formally sound way. Conceptually speaking, many of the pioneering presentations of the proposal nevertheless confused mental and material states (and their properties). This has been clarified by Freeman and Vitiello (2008): the model “describes the brain, not mental states.”

For a corresponding description of brain states, Freeman and Vitiello 2006, 2008, 2010) studied neurobiologically relevant observables such as electric and magnetic field amplitudes and neurotransmitter concentration. They found evidence for non-equilibrium analogs of phase transitions (Vitiello 2015) and power-law distributions of spectral energy densities of electrocorticograms (Freeman and Vitiello 2010, Freeman and Quian Quiroga 2013). All these observables are classical, so that neurons, glia cells, “and other physiological units are not quantum objects in the many-body model of brain” (Freeman and Vitiello 2008). However, Vitiello (2012) also points out that the emergence of (self-similar, fractal) power-law distributions in general is intimately related to dissipative quantum coherent states (see also recent developments of the Penrose-Hameroff scenario, Section 4.5).

The overall conclusion is that the application of quantum field theory describes why and how classical behavior emerges at the level of brain activity considered. The relevant brains states themselves are viewed as classical states. Similar to a classical thermodynamical description arising from quantum statistical mechanics, the idea is to identify different regimes of stable behavior (phases, attractors) and transitions between them. This way, quantum field theory provides formal elements from which a standard classical description of brain activity can be inferred, and this is its main role in the model.

4.4 Beck and Eccles: Quantum Mechanics at the Synaptic Cleft

Probably the most concrete suggestion of how quantum mechanics in its present-day appearance can play a role in brain processes is due to Beck and Eccles (1992), later refined by Beck (2001). It refers to particular mechanisms of information transfer at the synaptic cleft. However, ways in which these quantum processes might be relevant for mental activity, and in which their interactions with mental states are conceived, remain unclarified to the present day.

As presented in Section 3.2, the information flow between neurons in chemical synapses is initiated by the release of transmitters in the presynaptic terminal. This process is called exocytosis, and it is triggered by an arriving nerve impulse with some small probability. In order to describe the trigger mechanism in a statistical way, thermodynamics or quantum mechanics can be invoked. A look at the corresponding energy regimes shows (Beck and Eccles 1992) that quantum processes are distinguishable from thermal processes for energies higher than 10-2 eV (at room temperature). Assuming a typical length scale for biological microsites of the order of several nanometers, an effective mass below 10 electron masses is sufficient to ensure that quantum processes prevail over thermal processes.

The upper limit of the time scale of such processes in the quantum regime is of the order of 10-12 sec. This is significantly shorter than the time scale of cellular processes, which is 10-9 sec and longer. The sensible difference between the two time scales makes it possible to treat the corresponding processes as decoupled from one another.

The detailed trigger mechanism proposed by Beck and Eccles (1992) is based on the quantum concept of quasi-particles, reflecting the particle aspect of a collective mode. Skipping the details of the picture, the proposed trigger mechanism refers to tunneling processes of two-state quasi-particles, resulting in state collapses. It yields a probability of exocytosis in the range between 0 and 0.7, in agreement with empirical observations. Using a theoretical framework developed earlier (Marcus 1956; Jortner 1976), the quantum trigger can be concretely understood in terms of electron transfer between biomolecules. However, the question remains how the trigger may be relevant for conscious mental states. There are two aspects to this question.

The first one refers to Eccles' intention to utilize quantum processes in the brain as an entry point for mental causation. The idea, as indicated in Section 1, is that the fundamentally indeterministic nature of individual quantum state collapses offers room for the influence of mental powers on brain states. In the present picture, this is conceived in such a way that “mental intention (volition) becomes neurally effective by momentarily increasing the probability of exocytosis” (Beck and Eccles 1992, 11360). Further justification of this assumption is not given.

The second aspect refers to the problem that processes at single synapses cannot be simply correlated to mental activity, whose neural correlates are coherent assemblies of neurons. Most plausibly, prima facie uncorrelated random processes at individual synapses would result in a stochastic network of neurons (Hepp 1999). Although Beck (2001) has indicated possibilities (such as quantum stochastic resonance) for achieving ordered patterns at the level of assemblies from fundamentally random synaptic processes, this remains an unsolved problem.

With the exception of Eccles' idea of mental causation, the approach by Beck and Eccles essentially focuses on brain states and brain dynamics. In his more recent account, Beck (2001, 109f) states explicitly that “science cannot, by its very nature, present any answer to […] questions related to the mind”. In this sense, a strictly biophysical approach may open the door to controlled speculation about mind-matter relations, but more cannot be achieved.

4.5 Penrose and Hameroff: Quantum Gravity and Microtubuli

In the scenario developed by Penrose and neurophysiologically augmented by Hameroff, quantum theory is claimed to be effective for consciousness, but the way this happens is quite sophisticated. It is argued that elementary acts of consciousness are non-algorithmic, i.e., non-computable, and they are neurophysiologically realized as gravitation-induced reductions of coherent superposition states in microtubuli.

Unlike the approaches discussed so far, which are essentially based on (different features of) status quo quantum theory, the physical part of the scenario, proposed by Penrose, refers to future developments of quantum theory for a proper understanding of the physical process underlying quantum state reduction. The grander picture is that a full-blown theory of quantum gravity is required to ultimately understand quantum measurement (see the entry on quantum gravity).

This is a far-reaching assumption, and Penrose does not offer a concrete solution to this problem. However, he gives a number of plausibility arguments which clarify his own motivations and have in fact inspired others to take his ideas seriously. Penrose's rationale for invoking state reduction is not that the corresponding randomness offers room for mental causation to become efficacious (although this is not excluded). His conceptual starting point, at length developed in two books (Penrose 1989, 1994), is that elementary conscious acts must be non-algorithmic. Phrased differently, the emergence of a conscious act is a process which cannot be described algorithmically, hence cannot be computed. His background in this respect has a lot to do with the nature of creativity, mathematical insight, Gödel's incompleteness theorem, and the idea of a Platonic reality beyond mind and matter.

In contrast to the unitary time evolution of quantum processes, Penrose suggests that a valid formulation of quantum state reduction replacing von Neumann's projection postulate must faithfully describe an objective physical process that he calls objective reduction. Since present-day quantum theory does not contain such a picture, he argues that effects not currently covered by quantum theory should play a role in state reduction. Ideal candidates for him are gravitational effects since gravitation is the only fundamental interaction which is not integrated into quantum theory so far. Rather than modifying elements of the theory of gravitation (i.e., general relativity) to achieve such an integration, Penrose discusses the reverse: that novel features have to be incorporated in quantum theory for this purpose. In this way, he arrives at the proposal of gravitation-induced objective state reduction.

Why is such a version of state reduction non-computable? Initially one might think of objective state reduction in terms of a stochastic process, as most current proposals for such mechanisms indeed do (see the entry on collapse theories). This would certainly be indeterministic, but probabilistic and stochastic processes can be standardly implemented on a computer, hence they are definitely computable. Penrose (1994, Secs 7.8 and 7.10) sketches some ideas concerning genuinely non-computable, not only random, features of quantum gravity. In order for them to become viable candidates for explaining the non-computability of gravitation-induced state reduction, a long way still has to be gone.

With respect to the neurophysiological implementation of Penrose's proposal, his collaboration with Hameroff has been crucial. With his background as an anaesthesiologist, Hameroff suggested to consider microtubules as an option for where reductions of quantum states can take place in an effective way, see e.g., Hameroff and Penrose (1996). The respective quantum states are assumed to be coherent superpositions of tubulin states, ultimately extending over many neurons. Their simultaneous gravitation-induced collapse is interpreted as an individual elementary act of consciousness. The proposed mechanism by which such superpositions are established includes a number of involved details that remain to be confirmed or disproven.

The idea of focusing on microtubuli is partly motivated by the argument that special locations are required to ensure that quantum states can live long enough to become reduced by gravitational influence rather than by interactions with the warm and wet environment within the brain. Speculative remarks about how the non-computable aspects of the expected new physics mentioned above could be significant in this scenario[12] are given in Penrose (1994, Sec. 7.7).

Influential criticism of the possibility that quantum states can in fact survive long enough in the thermal environment of the brain has been raised by Tegmark (2000). He estimates the decoherence time of tubulin superpositions due to interactions in the brain to be less than 10-12 sec. Compared to typical time scales of microtubular processes of the order of milliseconds and more, he concludes that the lifetime of tubulin superpositions is much too short to be significant for neurophysiological processes in the microtubuli. In a response to this criticism, Hagan et al. (2002) showed that a corrected version of Tegmark's model provides decoherence times up to 10 to 100 μ sec, and it has been argued that this can be extended up to the neurophysiologically relevant range of 10 to 100 msec under particular assumptions of the scenario by Penrose and Hameroff.

More recently, a novel idea has entered this debate. Theoretical studies of interacting spins have shown that entangled states can be maintained in noisy open quantum systems at high temperature and far from thermal equilibrium. In these studies the effect of decoherence is counterbalanced by a simple “recoherence” mechanism (Hartmann et al. 2006, Li and Paraoanu 2009). This indicates that, under particular circumstances, entanglement may persist even in hot and noisy environments such as the brain.

However, decoherence is just one piece in the debate about the overall picture suggested by Penrose and Hameroff. From another perspective, their proposal of microtubules as quantum computing devices has recently received support from work of Bandyopadhyay's lab at Japan, showing evidence for vibrational resonances and conductivity features in microtubules that should be expected if they are macroscopic quantum systems (Sahu et al. 2013). Bandyopadhyay's results initiated considerable attention and commentary (see Hameroff and Penrose 2014). In a well-informed in-depth analysis, Pitkänen (2014) raised concerns to the effect that the reported results alone may not be sufficient to confirm the approach proposed by Hameroff and Penrose with all its ramifications.

A recent paper by Craddock et al. (2015) discusses in detail how microtubular processes (rather than, or in addition to, synaptic processes, see Flohr 2000) may be affected by anesthetics, and may also be responsible for neurodegenerative memory disorders. As the correlation between anesthetics and consciousness seems obvious at the phenomenological level, it is interesting to know the intricate mechanisms by which anesthetic drugs act on the cytoskeleton of neuronal cells,[13] and which role quantum mechanics plays in these mechanisms. Craddock et al. (2015) point out a number of possible quantum effects (including the power-law behavior addressed by Vitiello, cf. Section 4.3) which can be investigated using presently available technologies.

From a philosophical perspective, the scenario of Penrose and Hameroff has occasionally received outspoken rejection, see e.g., Grush and Churchland (1995) and the reply by Penrose and Hameroff (1995). Indeed, their approach collects several top level mysteries, among them the relation between mind and matter itself, the ultimate unification of all physical interactions, the origin of mathematical truth, and the understanding of brain dynamics across hierarchical levels. Combining such deep and fascinating issues certainly needs further work to be substantiated, and should neither be too quickly celebrated nor offhandedly dismissed. After the two decades since its inception one thing can be safely asserted: the approach has fruitfully inspired many important avenues of innovative research in consciousness studies.

4.6 Mind and Matter as Dual Aspects

Dual-aspect approaches consider mental and material domains of reality as aspects, or manifestations, of one underlying reality in which mind and matter are unseparated. In such a framework, the distinction between mind and matter results from the application of a basic tool for achieving epistemic access to, i.e., gather knowledge about, both the separated domains and the underlying reality.[14] Consequently, the status of the underlying, psychophysically neutral domain is considered as ontic relative to the mind-matter distinction.

As mentioned in Section 2, dual-aspect approaches have a long history, essentially starting with Spinoza as a most outspoken protagonist. Major directions in the 20th century have been described and compared to some detail by Atmanspacher (2014). An important distinction between two basic classes of dual-aspect thinking is the way in which the psychophysically neutral domain is related to the mental and the physical. For Russell and the neo-Russellians the compositional arrangements of psychophysically neutral elements decide how they differ with respect to mental or physical properties. As a consequence, the mental and the physical are reducible to the neutral domain. Chalmers' (1996, Chap. 8) ideas on “consciousness and information” fall into this class. Tononi's theoretical framework of “integrated information theory” (see Oizumi et al. 2014, Tononi and Koch 2015) can be seen as a concrete implementation of a number of features of Chalmers' proposal. No quantum structures are involved in this work.

The other class of dual-aspect thinking is decompositional rather than compositional. Here the basic metaphysics of the psychophysically neutral domain is holistic, and the mental and the physical (neither reducible to one another nor to the neutral) emerge by breaking the holistic symmetry or, in other words, by making distinctions. This framework is guided by the analogy to quantum holism, and the predominant versions of this picture are quantum theoretically inspired as, for instance, proposed by Pauli and Jung (Jung and Pauli 1955; Meier 2001) and by Bohm and Hiley (Bohm 1990; Bohm and Hiley 1993; Hiley 2001). They are based on speculations that clearly exceed the scope of contemporary quantum theory.

In Bohm's and Hiley's approach, the notions of implicate and explicate order mirror the distinction between ontic and epistemic domains. Mental and physical states emerge by explication, or unfoldment, from an ultimately undivided and psychophysically neutral implicate, enfolded order. This order is called holomovement because it is not static but rather dynamic, as in Whitehead's process philosophy. De Gosson and Hiley (2013) give a good introduction of how the holomovement can be addressed from a formal (algebraic) point of view.

At the level of the implicate order, the term active information expresses that this level is capable of “informing” the epistemically distinguished, explicate domains of mind and matter. At this point it should be emphasized that the usual notion of information is clearly an epistemic term. Nevertheless, there are quite a number of dual-aspect approaches addressing something like information at the ontic, psychophysically neutral level.[15] Using an information-like concept in a non-epistemic manner is inconsistent if the common (syntactic) significance of Shannon-type information is intended, which requires distinctions in order to construct partitions, providing alternatives, in the set of given events. Most information-based dual-aspect approaches do not sufficiently clarify their notion of information, so that misunderstandings abound easily.

While the proposal by Bohm and Hiley essentially sketches a conceptual framework without further concrete details, particularly concerning the mental domain, the suggestions by Pauli and Jung offer some more material to discuss. An intuitively appealing way to represent their approach considers the distinction between epistemic and ontic domains of material reality due to quantum theory in parallel with the distinction between epistemic and ontic mental domains.

On the physical side, the epistemic/ontic distinction refers to the distinction between a “local realism” of empirical facts obtained from classical measuring instruments and a “holistic realism” of entangled systems (Atmanspacher and Primas 2003). Essentially, these domains are connected by the process of measurement, thus far conceived as independent of conscious observers. The corresponding picture on the mental side refers to a distinction between the conscious and the unconscious.[16] In Jung's depth psychological conceptions, these two domains are connected by a process of emergence of conscious mental states from the unconscious, analogous to physical measurement.

In Jung's depth psychology it is crucial that the unconscious has a collective component, unseparated between individuals and consisting of the so-called archetypes. They are regarded as constituting the psychophysically neutral level covering both the collective unconscious and the holistic reality of quantum theory. At the same time they operate as “ordering factors”, being responsible for the arrangement of their psychical and physical manifestations in the epistemically distinguished domains of mind and matter. More detailed illustrations of this picture can be found in Jung and Pauli (1955), Meier (2001), Atmanspacher and Primas (2009), Atmanspacher and Fach (2013), and Atmanspacher and Fuchs (2014).

This scheme is clearly related to scenario (B) of (Sec. 2, combining an epistemically dualistic with an ontically monistic approach. There is a causal relationship (in the sense of formal rather than efficient causation) between the psychophysically neutral, monistic level and the epistemically distinguished mental and material domains. In Pauli's and Jung's terms this kind of causation is expressed by the ordering operation of archetypes in the collective unconscious.

A remarkable feature of scenario (B) is the possibility that the mental and material manifestations may inherit mutual correlations due to the fact that they are jointly caused by the psychophysically neutral level. One might say that such correlations are remnants reflecting the lost holism on this level. In this sense, they are not the result of any direct causal interaction between mental and material domains. Thus, they are not suitable for an explanation of direct mental causation in the usual sense. Their existence would require some unconscious activity entailing correlation effects that would appear as mental causation. Independently of quantum theory, a related move was suggested by Velmans (2002, 2009). But even without mental causation, scenario (B) is relevant to ubiquitous correlations between conscious mental states and brain states.

In the Pauli-Jung conjecture, these correlations are called synchronistic (see also Primas 1996), and have been extended to psychosomatic relations (Meier 1975). A more comprehensive typology of mind-matter correlations following from Pauli's and Jung's dual-aspect monism was proposed by Atmanspacher and Fach (2013). They found that a large body of empirical material concerning so-called “exceptional experiences” can be classified according to their deviation from the conventional reality model of a subject and from the conventional relations between its components. Synchronicities in the sense of Pauli and Jung appear as a special case of such relational deviations.

An essential condition required for synchronistic correlations is that they are meaningful for those who experience them. It is tempting to interpret the use of meaning as an attempt to introduce semantic information as an alternative to syntactic information as addressed above. Although this entails difficult problems concerning a clear-cut definition and operationalization, something akin to meaning, both explicitly and implicitly, might be a relevant informational currency for mind-matter relations within the framework of decompositional dual-aspect thinking (Atmanspacher 2014).

Primas (2003, 2009) has proposed a dual-aspect approach where the distinction of mental and material domains originates from the distinction between two different modes of time: tensed (mental) time, including nowness, on the one hand and tenseless (physical) time, viewed as an external parameter, on the other (see the entries on time and on being and becoming in modern physics). Regarding these two concepts of time as implied by a symmetry breaking of a timeless level of reality that is psychophysically neutral, Primas conceives the tensed time of the mental domain as quantum-correlated with the parameter time of physics via “time-entanglement”. Although this scenario has been formulated in a Hilbert space framework with appropriate time operators (Primas 2009), it is still a tentative scheme without concrete indications of how to test it empirically. Nevertheless it offers a formally elaborated and conceptually consistent dual-aspect quantum framework for basic aspects of the mind-matter problem.

As indicated above, the approaches by Stapp (Section 4.2) and Vitiello (Section 4.3) contain elements of dual-aspect thinking as well, although these are not much emphasized by the authors. The dual-aspect quantum approaches discussed in the present section tend to focus on the issue of entanglement more than on state reduction. The primary purpose here is to understand correlations between mental and material domains rather than direct interactions between them.

A final issue of dual-aspect approaches in general refers to the problem of panpsychism or panexperientialism, respectively (see the review by Skrbina 2003, and the entry on panpsychism). In the limit of a universal symmetry breaking at the psychophysically neutral level, every system has both a mental and a material aspect. In such a situation it is important to understand “mentality” much more generally than “consciousness”. Unconscious or proto-mental acts as opposed to conscious mental acts are notions sometimes used to underline this difference. The special case of human consciousness within the mental domain as a whole might be regarded as special as its material correlate, the brain, within the material domain as a whole.

4.7 Mental Quantum Features

It has been an old idea by Bohr that central conceptual features of quantum theory, such as complementarity, are also of pivotal significance outside the domain of physics. In fact, Bohr became familiar with the idea through the psychologist Edgar Rubin and, more indirectly, William James (Holton 1970) and immediately saw its potential for quantum physics. Although Bohr was always convinced of the extraphysical relevance of complementarity, he never elaborated this idea in concrete detail, and for a long time after him no one else did so either. This situation has changed: there are now a number of research programs generalizing key notions of quantum theory in a way that makes them applicable beyond physics.

Of particular interest are approaches that have been developed in order to pick up Bohr's proposal with respect to psychology and cognitive science. The first steps in this direction were made by the group of Aerts in the early 1990s (Aerts et al. 1993), using non-distributive propositional lattices to address quantum-like behavior in non-quantum systems. Alternative approaches have been initiated by Khrennikov (1999), focusing on non-classical probabilities, and Atmanspacher et al. (2002), outlining an algebraic framework with non-commuting operations. Other lines of thinking are due to Primas (2007), addressing complementarity with partial Boolean algebras, and Filk and von Müller (2008), indicating links between basic conceptual categories in quantum physics and psychology.

A formal move to incorporate quantum behavior in mental systems, without referring to quantum brain activity, is based on a state space description of mental systems. If mental states are defined on the basis of cells of a neural state space partition, then this partition needs to be well tailored to lead to robustly defined states. Ad hoc chosen partitions will generally create incompatible descriptions (Atmanspacher and beim Graben 2007). This implies that quantum brain dynamics is not the only possible explanation of quantum features in mental systems. Assuming that mental states arise from partitions of neural states in such a way that statistical neural states are co-extensive with individual mental states, the nature of mental processes depends strongly on the kind of partition chosen. If the partition is not properly constructed, it is likely that mental states and observables show features that resemble quantum behavior although the correlated brain activity may be entirely classical: quantum mind without quantum brain.

Intuitively, it is not difficult to understand why non-commuting operations or non-Boolean logic should be relevant, even inevitable, for mental systems that have nothing to do with quantum physics. Simply speaking, the non-commutativity of operations means nothing else than that the sequence, in which operations are applied, matters for the final result. And non-Boolean logic refers to propositions that may have unsharp truth values beyond yes or no, shades of plausibility or credibility as it were. Both versions obviously abound in psychology and cognitive science (and in everyday life). Pylkkänen (2015) has even suggested to use this intuitive accessibility of mental quantum features for a better conceptual grasp of quantum physics.

The particular strength of the idea of generalizing quantum theory beyond quantum physics is that it provides a formal framework which both yields a transparent well-defined link to conventional quantum physics and has been used to describe a number of concrete psychological applications with surprisingly detailed theoretical and empirical results. Corresponding approaches fall under the third category of Section 4.1: further developments or generalizations of quantum theory.

One rationale for the focus on psychological phenomena is that their detailed study is a necessary precondition for further questions as to their neural correlates. Therefore, the investigation of mental quantum features resists the temptation to reduce them (within scenario A) all-too quickly to neural activity. There are several kinds of psychological phenomena which have been addressed in the spirit of mental quantum features so far: (i) decision processes, (ii) order effects, (iii) bistable perception, (iv) learning, (v) agency, (vi) semantic networks, and (vii) super-quantum entanglement correlations.

  1. An early precursor of work on decision processes is due to Aerts and Aerts (1994). However, the first detailed account appeared in a comprehensive publication by Busemeyer et al. (2006). The key idea is to define probabilities for decision outcomes and decision times in terms of quantum probability amplitudes. Busemeyer et al. found agreement of a suitable Hilbert space model (and disagreement of a classical alternative) with empirical data. Moreover, they were able to clarify the long-standing riddle of the so-called conjunction and disjunction effects (Tversky and Shafir 1992) in decision making (Pothos and Busemeyer 2009). Another application refers to the asymmetry of similarity judgments (Tversky 1977), which can be adequately understood by quantum approaches (see Aerts et al. 2011, Pothos et al. 2013).
  2. Order effects in polls, surveys, and questionnaires, recognized for a long time (Schwarz and Sudman 1992), are still insufficiently understood today. Their study as contextual quantum features (Aerts and Aerts 1994, Busemeyer et al. 2011) offers the potential to unveil a lot more about such effects than the well-known fact that responses can drastically alter if questions are swapped. Atmanspacher and Römer (2012) proposed a complete classification of possible order effects (including uncertainty relations, and independent of Hilbert space representations), and Wang et al. (2014) discovered a fundamental covariance condition (called the QQ equation) for a wide class of order effects.
  3. The perception of a stimulus is bistable if the stimulus is ambiguous, such as the Necker cube. Atmanspacher and colleagues developed a detailed model predicting a quantitative relation between basic psychophysical time scales in bistable perception that has been confirmed experimentally (Atmanspacher and Filk 2013). Moreover, Atmanspacher and Filk (2010) conjectured that particular distinguished states in bistable perception may violate temporal Bell inqualitities—a litmus test for quantum behavior. See also Mahler (2015) for an informed overview of temporal Bell inequalities and their consequences.
  4. Another quite obvious arena for non-commutative behavior is learning behavior. In theoretical studies, Atmanspacher and Filk (2006) showed that in simple supervised learning tasks small recurrent networks not only learn the prescribed input-output relation but also the sequence in which inputs have been presented. This entails that the recognition of inputs is impaired if the sequence of presentation is changed. In very few exceptional cases, with special characteristics that remain to be explored, this impairment is avoided.
  5. A quantum approach for understanding issues related to agency, intention, and other controversial topics in the philosophy of mind has been proposed by Briegel and Müller (2014, in Other Internet Resources). This proposal is based on work on quantum algorithms for reinforcement learning in neural networks (“projective simulation”, Paparo et al. 2012), which can be regarded as a variant of quantum machine learning (Wittek 2014). The gist of the idea is how agents can develop agency as a kind of independence from their environment and the deterministic laws governing it (Briegel 2012). The behavior of the agent itself is simulated as a non-deterministic quantum random walk in its memory space.
  6. The difficult issue of meaning in natural languages is often explored in terms of semantic networks. Gabora and Aerts (2002) described the way in which concepts are evoked, used, and combined to generate meaning depending on contexts. Their ideas about concept association in evolution were further developed by Gabora and Aerts (2009). Bruza et al. (2009) referred to meaning relations in terms of entanglement-style features in quantum representations of the human mental lexicon and propose experimental work capable of testing this approach. See Bruza et al. (2013, in Other Internet Resources) for first empirical results in this direction.
  7. Quantum entanglement implies correlations exceeding standard classical correlations (by violating Bell-type inequalitites) but obeying the so-called Tsirelson bound. However, this bound does not exhaust the range by which Bell-type correlations can be violated in principle. Popescu and Rohrlich (1994) found such correlations for particular quantum measurements, and Dzhafarov and Kujala (2013) derived a compact way to distinguish the different types of correlations theoretically. Super-quantum correlations may arise due to priming or other context effects in mental systems. Possible examples are non-separable concept combinations a la Bruza et al. (2013, in Other Internet Resources).

It is a distinguishing aspect of the approaches listed above that they have led to well-defined and specific theoretical models with empirical consequences and novel predictions. A second point worth mentioning is that the approaches have formed a scientific community—there are several groups worldwide (rather than solitary actors) studying quantum ideas in cognition, partly even in collaborative efforts. For about a decade there have been regular international conferences with proceedings for the exchange of new results and ideas, and target articles and special issues of well established journals have been devoted to basic frameworks and new developments (Busemeyer and Bruza 2013, Pothos and Busemeyer 2013, Haven and Khrennikov 2013, Wang et al. 2013), Wendt (2015).

5. Conclusions

The historical motivation for exploring quantum theory in trying to understand consciousness derived from the realization that collapse-type quantum events introduce an element of randomness, which is primary (ontic) rather than merely due to ignorance or missing information (epistemic). Approaches such as those of Wigner, of Stapp, and of Beck and Eccles emphasize this (in different ways), insofar as the ontic randomness of quantum events is regarded to provide room for mental causation, i.e., the possibility that conscious mental acts can influence brain behavior. The approach by Penrose and Hameroff also focuses on state collapse, but with a significant move from mental causation to the non-computability of (particular) conscious acts.

Any discussion of state collapse or state reduction (e.g. by measurement) refers, at least implicitly, to superposition states since those are the states that are reduced. Insofar as entangled systems remain in a quantum superposition as long as no measurement has occurred, entanglement is always co-addressed when state reduction is discussed. By contrast, some of the dual-aspect quantum approaches utilize the topic of entanglement differently, and independently of state reduction in the first place. Inspired by the entanglement-induced nonlocal correlations of quantum physics, mind-matter entanglement is conceived as the hypothetical origin of mind-matter correlations. This reflects the highly speculative picture of a fundamentally holistic, psychophysically neutral level of reality from which correlated mental and material domains emerge.

Each of the examples discussed in this overview has both promising and problematic aspects. The approach by Beck and Eccles is most detailed and concrete with respect to the application of standard quantum mechanics to the process of exocytosis. However, it does not solve the problem of how the activity of single synapses enters the dynamics of neural assemblies, and it leaves mental causation of quantum processes as a mere claim. Stapp's approach suggests a radically expanded ontological basis for both the mental domain and status-quo quantum theory as a theory of matter without essentially changing the formalism of quantum theory. Although related to inspiring philosophical and some psychological background, it still lacks empirical confirmation. The proposal by Penrose and Hameroff exceeds the domain of present-day quantum theory by far and is the most speculative example among those discussed. It is not easy to see how the picture as a whole can be formally worked out and put to empirical test.

The approach initiated by Umezawa is embedded in the framework of quantum field theory, more broadly applicable and formally more sophisticated than standard quantum mechanics. It is used to describe the emergence of classical activity in neuronal assemblies on the basis of symmetry breakings in a quantum field theoretical framework. A clear conceptual distinction between brain states and mental states has often been missing, but this ambiguity has recently been resolved in favor of brain states. Their relation to mental states is ultimately left open; some of Vitiello's accounts suggest a vague inclination toward a dual-aspect approach.

The dual-aspect approaches of Pauli and Jung and of Bohm and Hiley are conceptually more transparent and more promising. On the other hand, they are essentially unsatisfactory with regard to a sound formal basis and concrete empirical scenarios. Hiley's work offers an algebraic framework which may lead to theoretical progress. A novel dual-aspect quantum proposal by Primas, based on the distinction between tensed mental time and tenseless physical time, marks a significant step forward, particularly as concerns a consistent formal framework.

Maybe the best prognosis for future success among the examples described in this overview, at least on foreseeable time scales, goes to the investigation of mental quantum features without focusing on associated brain activity to begin with. A number of corresponding approaches have been developed which include concrete models for concrete situations and have lead to successful empirical tests and further predictions. On the other hand, a coherent theory behind individual models and relating the different types of approaches is still to be settled in detail. With respect to scientific practice, a particularly promising aspect is the visible formation of a scientific community with conferences, mutual collaborations, and some perspicuous attraction for young scientists to join the field.

Bibliography

  • Aerts, D., Durt, T., Grib, A., Van Bogaert, B., and Zapatrin, A., 1993, “Quantum structures in macroscopical reality,” International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 32: 489–498.
  • Aerts, D. and Aerts, S., 1994, “Applications of quantum statistics in psychological studies of decision processes,” Foundations of Science, 1: 85–97.
  • Aerts, S., Kitto, K., and Sitbon, L., 2011, “Similarity metrics within a point of view,” in Quantum Interaction. 5th International Conference, D. Song, et al. (eds.), Berlin: Springer, pp. 13–24.
  • Alfinito, E., and Vitiello, G., 2000, “Formation and life-time of memory domains in the dissipative quantum model of brain,” International Journal of Modern Physics B, 14: 853–868.
  • Alfinito, E., Viglione, R.G., and Vitiello, G., 2001, “The decoherence criterion,” Modern Physics Letters B, 15: 127–135.
  • Anderson, J.A., and Rosenfeld, E. (eds.), 1988, Neurocomputing: Foundations of Research, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Atmanspacher, H., 2014, “20th century variants of dual-aspect thinking (with commentaries and replies),” Mind and Matter, 12: 245–288.
  • Atmanspacher H., and Fach W., 2013, “A structural-phenomenological typology of mind-matter correlations,” Journal of Analytical Psychology, 58: 218–243.
  • Atmanspacher, H., and Filk, T., 2006, “Complexity and non-commutativity of learning operations on graphs,” BioSystems, 85: 84–93.
  • –––, 2010, “A proposed test of temporal nonlocality in bistable perception,” Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 54: 314–321.
  • –––, 2013, “The Necker-Zeno model for bistable perception,” Topics in Cognitive Science, 5: 800–817.
  • Atmanspacher, H., and Fuchs, C., (eds.), 2014, The Pauli-Jung Conjecture and Its Impact Today, Exeter: Imprint Academic.
  • Atmanspacher, H. and beim Graben, P., 2007, “Contextual emergence of mental states from neurodynamics.” Chaos and Complexity Letters, 2: 151–168.
  • –––, (eds.), 2009, Recasting Reality. Wolfgang Pauli's Philosophical Ideas and Contemporary Science, Berlin: Springer.
  • Atmanspacher, H., and Römer, H., 2012, “Order effects in sequential measurememts of non-commuting psychological observables,” Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 56: 274–280.
  • Atmanspacher, H., Römer, H., and Walach, H., 2002, “Weak quantum theory: Complementarity and entanglement in physics and beyond,” Foundations of Physics, 32: 379–406.
  • Beck, F., and Eccles, J., 1992, “Quantum aspects of brain activity and the role of consciousness.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 89: 11357–11361.
  • Beck, F., 2001, “Quantum brain dynamics and consciousness,” in The Physical Nature of Consciousness, ed. by P. van Loocke, Amsterdam: Benjamins, pp. 83–116.
  • Bohm, D., 1990, “A new theory of the relationship of mind and matter,” Philosophical Psychology, 3: 271–286.
  • Bohm, D., and Hiley, B.J., 1993, The Undivided Universe, Routledge, London. See Chap. 15.
  • Briegel, H.-J., 2012, “On creative machines and the physical origins of freedom,” Scientific Reports, 2: 522.
  • Brukner, C., and Zeilinger, A., 2003, “Information and fundamental elements of the structure of quantum theory,” in Time, Quantum and Information, ed. by L. Castell and O. Ischebeck, Berlin: Springer, pp. 323–355.
  • Bruza, P.D., Kitto, K., Nelson, D., and McEvoy, C.L., 2009, “Is there something quantum-like about the human mental lexicon?” Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 53: 362-377.
  • Busemeyer, J.R., and Bruza, P.D., 2013, Quantum Models of Cognition and Decision, Cambridge: University Press.
  • Busemeyer, J.R., Wang, Z., and Townsend, J.T., 2006, “Quantum dynamics of human decision making,” Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 50: 220–241.
  • Busemeyer, J.R., Pothos, E., Franco, R., and Trueblood, J.S., 2011, “A quantum theoretical explanation for probability judgment errors,” Psychological Review, 108: 193–218.
  • Butterfield, J., 1998, “Quantum curiosities of psychophysics,” in Consciousness and Human Identity, ed. by J. Cornwell, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 122–157.
  • Chalmers, D., 1995, “Facing up to the problem of consciousness.,” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3): 200–219.
  • –––, 1996, The Conscious Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Clifton, R., Bub, J., and Halvorson, H., 2003, “Characterizing quantum theory in terms of information-theoretic constraints,” Foundations of Physics, 33: 1561–1591.
  • Craddock, T.J.A., Hameroff, S.R., Ayoub, A.T., Klobukowski, M., and Tuszynski, J.A., 2015, “Anesthetics act in quantum channels in brain microtubules to prevent consciousness,” Current Topics in Medicinal Chemistry, 15: 523–533.
  • de Gosson, M.A., and Hiley, B., 2013, “Hamiltonian flows and the holomovement,” Mind and Matter, 11: 205–221.
  • d'Espagnat, B., 1999, “Concepts of reality,” in On Quanta, Mind, and Matter, H. Atmanspacher, U. Müller-Herold, and A. Amann (eds.), Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp. 249–270.
  • Dzhafarov, E.N., and Kujala, J.V., 2013, “All-possible-couplings approach to measuring probabilistic context,” PLoS One, 8(5): e61712.
  • Ellis, G.F.R., Noble, D., and O'Connor T. (eds.), 2011, Top-Down Causation: An Integrating Theme Within and Across the Sciences?, Special Issue of Interface Focus 2(1).
  • Esfeld, M, 1999, “Wigner's view of physical reality,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 30B: 145–154.
  • Fechner, G., 1861, Über die Seelenfrage. Ein Gang durch die sichtbare Welt, um die unsichtbare zu finden, Amelang, Leipzig. Second edition: Leopold Voss, Hamburg, 1907. Reprinted Eschborn: Klotz, 1992.
  • Feigl, H., 1967, The ‘Mental’ and the ‘Physical’, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
  • Filk, T., and von Müller, A., 2009, “Quantum physics and consciousness: The quest for a common conceptual foundation,” Mind and Matter, 7(1): 59–79.
  • Flohr, H., 2000, “NMDA receptor-mediated computational processes and phenomenal consciousness,” in Neural Correlates of Consciousness. Empirical and Conceptual Questions, ed. by T. Metzinger, Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 245–258.
  • Franck, G., 2004, “Mental presence and the temporal present,” in Brain and Being, ed. by G.G. Globus, K.H. Pribram, and G. Vitiello, Amsterdam: Benjamins, pp. 47–68.
  • –––, 2008, “Presence and reality: An option to specify panpsychism?” Mind and Matter, 6(1): 123–140.
  • Freeman, W.J., and Quian, Quiroga R., 2012, Imaging Brain Function with EEG, Berlin: Springer.
  • Freeman, W.J., and Vitiello, G., 2006, “Nonlinear brain dynamics as macroscopic manifestation of underlying many-body field dynamics,” Physics of Life Reviews, 3(2): 93–118.
  • –––, 2008, “Dissipation and spontaneous symmetry breaking in brain dynamics,” Journal of Physics A, 41: 304042.
  • –––, 2010, “Vortices in brain waves,” International Journal of Modern Physics B, 24: 3269–3295.
  • Fröhlich, H., 1968, “Long range coherence and energy storage in biological systems,” International Journal of Quantum Chemistry, 2: 641–649.
  • Fuchs, C.A., 2002, “Quantum mechanics as quantum information (and only a little more),” n Quantum Theory: Reconsideration of Foundations, ed. by A. Yu. Khrennikov, Växjö: Växjö University Press, pp. 463–543.
  • Gabora L., and Aerts, D., 2002, “Contextualizing concepts using a mathematical generalization of the quantum formalism,” Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 14: 327–358.
  • –––, 2009, “A model of the emergence and evolution of integrated worldviews,” Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 53: 434–451.
  • Grush, R., and Churchland, P.S., 1995, “Gaps in Penrose's toilings,” Journal of Consciousness Studies 2(1), 10–29. (See also the response by R. Penrose and S. Hameroff in Journal of Consciousness Studies 2(2) (1995): 98–111.)
  • Hagan, S., Hameroff, S.R., and Tuszynski, J.A., 2002, “Quantum computation in brain microtubules: Decoherence and biological feasibility,” Physical Review E, 65: 061901-1 to -11.
  • Hameroff, S.R., and Penrose, R., 1996, “Conscious events as orchestrated spacetime selections,” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3(1): 36–53.
  • –––, 2014, “Consciousness in the universe: A review of the Orch OR theory (with commentaries and replies),” Physics of Life Reviews, 11: 39–112.
  • Hartmann, L., Düer, W., and Briegel, H.-J., 2006, “Steady state entanglement in open and noisy quantum systems at high temperature,” Physical Review A, 74: 052304.
  • Haven, E., and Khrennikov, A.Yu., 2013, Quantum Social Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Heisenberg, W., 1958, Physics and Philosophy, New York: Harper and Row.
  • Hepp, K., 1999, “Toward the demolition of a computational quantum brain,” in Quantum Future, ed. by P. Blanchard and A. Jadczyk, Berlin: Springer, pp. 92–104.
  • Hiley, B.J., 2001, “Non-commutative geometry, the Bohm interpretation and the mind-matter relationship,” in Computing Anticipatory Systems—CASYS 2000, ed. by D. Dubois, Berlin: Springer, pp. 77–88.
  • Holton, G., 1970, “The roots of complementarity,” Daedalus, 99: 1015–1055.
  • Huelga, S.H., and Plenio, M.B., 2013, “Vibrations, quanta, and biology,” Contemporary Physics, 54: 181–207.
  • James, W., 1950, The Principles of Psychology, Vol. 1, New York: Dover. Originally published in 1890.
  • Jammer, M., 1974, The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics, New York: Wiley.
  • Jibu, M., and Yasue, K., 1995, Quantum Brain Dynamics and Consciousness, Amsterdam: Benjamins.
  • Jortner, J., 1976, “Temperature dependent activation energy for electron transfer between biological molecules,” Journal of Chemical Physics, 64: 4860–4867.
  • Jung, C.G., and Pauli, W., 1955, The Interpretation of Nature and the Psyche, Pantheon, New York. Translated by P. Silz. German original Naturerklärung und Psyche, Zürich: Rascher, 1952.
  • Kandel, E.R., Schwartz, J.H., and Jessell, T.M., 2000, Principles of Neural Science, New York: McGraw Hill.
  • Kane, R., 1996, The Significance of Free Will, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Kaneko, K., and Tsuda, I., 2000, Chaos and Beyond, Berlin: Springer.
  • Khrennikov, A.Yu., 1999, “Classical and quantum mechanics on information spaces with applications to cognitive, psychological, social and anomalous phenomena,” Foundations of Physics, 29: 1065–1098.
  • Kim, J., 1998, Mind in a Physical World, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Kuhn, A., Aertsen, A., and Rotter, S., 2004, “Neuronal integration of synaptic input in the fluctuation-driven regime,” Journal of Neuroscience, 24: 2345–2356.
  • Li, J., and Paraoanu, G.S., 2009, “Generation and propagation of entanglement in driven coupled-qubit systems,” New Journal of Physics, 11: 113020.
  • London, F., and Bauer, E., 1939, La théorie de l'observation en mécanique quantique, Paris: Hermann; English translation, “The theory of observation in quantum mechanics,” in Quantum Theory and Measurement, ed. by J.A. Wheeler and W.H. Zurek, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983, pp. 217–259.
  • Mahler, G., 2015, “Temporal non-locality: Fact or fiction?,” in Quantum Interaction. 8th International Conference, H. Atmanspacher, et al. (eds.), Berlin: Springer, pp. 243–254.
  • Marcus, R.A., 1956, “On the theory of oxydation-reduction reactions involving electron transfer,” Journal of Chemical Physics, 24: 966–978.
  • Margenau, H., 1950, The Nature of Physical Reality, New York: McGraw Hill.
  • Meier, C.A., 1975, “Psychosomatik in Jungscher Sicht,” in Experiment und Symbol, ed. by C.A. Meier, Walter, Olten, pp. 138–156.
  • ––– (eds.), 2001, Atom and Archetype: The Pauli/Jung Letters 1932–1958, Princeton University Press, Princeton. Translated by D. Roscoe. German original Wolfgang Pauli und C.G. Jung: ein Briefwechsel, Berlin: Springer, 1992.
  • Nagel, T., 1974, “What is it like to be a bat?,” The Philosophical Review, LXXXIII: 435–450.
  • Neumann, J. von, 1955, Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Princeton University Press, Princeton. German original Die mathematischen Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik, Berlin: Springer, 1932.
  • Noë, A., and Thompson, E., 2004, “Are there neural correlates of consciousness? (with commentaries and replies),” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 11: 3–98.
  • Oizumi, M., Albantakis, L., and Tononi, G., 2014, “From the phenomenology to the mechanisms of consciousness: Integrated information theory 3.0,” PLoS Computational Biology, 10(5): e1003588.
  • Paparo, G.D., Dunjko, V., Makmal, A., Martin-Delgado, M.A., and Briegel, H.-J., 2012, “Quantum speedup for active learning agents,” Physical Review X, 4: 031002.
  • Papaseit, C., Pochon, N., and Tabony, J., 2000, “Microtubule self-organization is gravity-dependent,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 97: 8364–8368.
  • Pauen, M., 2001, Grundprobleme der Philosophie des Geistes, Frankfurt, Fischer.
  • Penrose, R., 1989, The Emperor's New Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 1994, Shadows of the Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Penrose, R., and Hameroff, S., 1995, “What gaps? Reply to Grush and Churchland,” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(2): 98–111.
  • Pessa, E., and Vitiello, G., 2003, “Quantum noise, entanglement and chaos in the quantum field theory of mind/brain states,” Mind and Matter, 1: 59–79.
  • Pitkänen, M., 2014, “New results about microtubuli as quantum systems,” Journal of Nonlocality, 3(1): available online.
  • Popescu, S., and Rohrlich, D., 1994, “Nonlocality as an axiom,” Foundations of Physics, 24: 379–385.
  • Popper, K.R., and Eccles, J.C., 1977, The Self and Its Brain, Berlin: Springer.
  • Pothos, E.M., and Busemeyer, J.R., 2009, “A quantum probability model explanation for violations of rational decision theory,” Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 276: 2171–2178.
  • –––, 2013, “Can quantum probability provide a new direction for cognitive modeling?” Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36: 255–274.
  • Pothos, E.M., Busemeyer, J.R., and Trueblood, J.S., 2013, “A quantum geometric model of similarity,” Psychological Review, 120: 679–696.
  • Pribram, K., 1971, Languages of the Brain, Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
  • Primas, H., 2002, “Hidden determinism, probability, and time's arrow,” in Between Chance and Choice, H. Atmanspacher and R.C. Bishop (eds.), Exeter: Imprint Academic, pp. 89–113.
  • –––, 2003, “Time-entanglement between mind and matter,” Mind and Matter, 1: 81–119.
  • –––, 2007, “Non-Boolean descriptions for mind-matter systems,” Mind and Matter, 5(1): 7–44.
  • –––, 2009, “Complementarity of mind and matter,” in Recasting Reality, H. Atmanspacher and H. Primas (eds.), Berlin: Springer, pp. 171–209.
  • Pylkkänen, P., 2015, “Fundamental physics and the mind – Is there a connection?,” in Quantum Interaction. 8th International Conference, H. Atmanspacher, et al. (eds.), Berlin: Springer, pp. 3–11.
  • Ricciardi, L.M., and Umezawa, H., 1967, “Brain and physics of many-body problems,” Kybernetik, 4: 44–48.
  • Sahu, S., Ghosh, S., Hirata, K., Fujita, D., and Bandyopadhyay, A., 2013, “Multi-level memory-switching properties of a single brain microtubule,” Applied Physics Letters, 102: 123701.
  • Schwartz, J.M., Stapp, H.P., and Beauregard, M., 2005, “Quantum theory in neuroscience and psychology: a neurophysical model of mind/brain interaction,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 360: 1309–1327.
  • Schwarz, N., and Sudman, S. (eds.), 1992, Context Effects in Social and Psychological Research, Berlin: Springer.
  • Shimony, A., 1963, “Role of the observer in quantum theory,” American Journal of Physics, 31: 755–773.
  • Skrbina, D., 2003, “Panpsychism in Western philosophy,” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(3): 4–46.
  • Smart, J.J.C., 1963, Philosophy and Scientific Realism, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Spencer, Brown G., 1969, Laws of Form, London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Squires, E., 1990, Conscious Mind in the Physical World, Bristol: Adam Hilger.
  • Stapp, H.P., 1993, “A quantum theory of the mind-brain interface,” in Mind, Matter, and Quantum Mechanics, Berlin: Springer, pp. 145–172.
  • –––, 1999, “Attention, intention, and will in quantum physics,” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6(8/9): 143–164.
  • –––, 2006,“Clarifications and specifications. Conversation with Harald Atmanspacher,” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13(9): 67–85.
  • –––, 2007, Mindful Universe, Berlin: Springer.
  • –––, 2015, “A quantum-mechanical theory of the mind-brain connection,” in Beyond Physicalism, ed. by E.F. Kelly et al., Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 157–193.
  • Stephan, A., 1999, Emergenz, Dresden: Dresden University Press.
  • Strawson, G., 2003, “Real materialism,” in Chomsky and His Critics, ed. by L. Anthony and N. Hornstein, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 49–88.
  • Stuart, C.I.J., Takahashi, Y., and Umezawa, H., 1978, “On the stability and non-local properties of memory,” Journal of Theoretical Biology, 71: 605–618.
  • –––, 1979, “Mixed system brain dynamics: neural memory as a macroscopic ordered state,” Foundations of Physics, 9: 301–327.
  • Suarez, A., and Adams, P. (eds.), 2013, Is Science Compatible with Free Will?, Berlin: Springer.
  • Tegmark, M., 2000, “Importance of quantum decoherence in brain processes,” Physical Review E 61, 4194–4206.
  • Tononi, G., and Koch, C., 2015, “Consciousness: Here, there and everywhere?” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 370: 20140167.
  • Tversky, A., 1977, “Features of similarity,” Psychological Review, 84: 327–352.
  • Tversky, A., and Shafir, E., 1992, “The disjunction effect in choice under uncertainty,” Psychological Science, 3: 305–309.
  • Velmans, M., 2002, “How could conscious experiences affect brains?” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9(11): 3–29. Commentaries to this article by various authors and Velman's response in the same issue, pp. 30–95. See also Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(12): 24–61 (2003), for the continuation of the debate.
  • –––, 2009, Understanding Consciousness, Routledge, London.
  • Vitiello, G., 1995, “Dissipation and memory capacity in the quantum brain model,” International Journal of Modern Physics B, 9: 973–989.
  • –––, 2001, My Double Unveiled, Amsterdam: Benjamins.
  • –––, 2002, “Dissipative quantum brain dynamics,” in No Matter, Never Mind, ed. by K. Yasue, M. Jibu, and T. Della Senta, Amsterdam: Benjamins, pp. 43–61.
  • –––, 2012, “Fractals as macroscopic manifestation of squeezed coherent states and brain dynamics,” Journal of Physics, 380: 012021.
  • –––, 2015, “The use of many-body physics and thermodynamics to describe the dynamics of rhythmic generators in sensory cortices engaged in memory and learning,” Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 31: 7–12.
  • Wang, Z., Busemeyer, J., Atmanspacher, H., and Pothos, E., 2013, “The potential of quantum theory to build models of cognition,” Topics in Cognitive Science, 5: 672–688.
  • Wang, Z., Solloway, T., Shiffrin, R.M., and Busemeyer, J.R., 2014, “Context effects produced by question orders reveal quantum nature of human judgments,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 111: 9431–9436.
  • Weizsäcker, C.F. von, 1985, Aufbau der Physik, München: Hanser.
  • Wendt, A., 2015, Quantum Mind and Social Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Wheeler, J.A., 1994, “It from bit,” in At Home in the Universe, Woodbury: American Institute of Physics, pp. 295–311, references pp. 127–133.
  • Whitehead, A.N., 1978, Process and Reality, New York: Free Press.
  • Wigner, E.P., 1967, “Remarks on the mind-body question,” in Symmetries and Reflections, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 171–184.
  • –––, 1977, “Physics and its relation to human knowledge,” Hellenike Anthropostike Heaireia, Athens, pp. 283–294. Reprinted in Wigner's Collected Works Vol. VI, edited by J. Mehra, Berlin: Springer, 1995, pp. 584–593.
  • Wittek, P., 2014, Quantum Machine Learning: What Quantum Computing Means to Data Mining, New York: Academic Press.
  • Wundt, W., 1911, Grundzüge der physiologischen Psychologie, dritter Band, Leipzig: Wilhelm Engelmann.

Other Internet Resources

Acknowledgments

Inspiring discussions on numerous topics treated in this paper with Guido Bacciagaluppi, Thomas Filk, Hans Flohr, Hans Primas, Stefan Rotter, Henry Stapp, Giuseppe Vitiello, and Max Velmans are gratefully acknowledged. Useful comments by Thomas Filk, Stuart Hameroff, and Giuseppe Vitiello helped to update the previous 2011 version of this entry.


Copyright © 2015 by
Harald Atmanspacher <atmanspacher@collegium.ethz.ch>

This is a file in the archives of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Please note that some links may no longer be functional.
[an error occurred while processing the directive]