Philosophical Issues in Quantum Theory

First published Mon Jul 25, 2016

This article is an overview of the philosophical issues raised by quantum theory, intended as a pointer to the more in-depth treatments of other entries in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

1. Introduction

Despite its status as a core part of contemporary physics, there is no consensus among physicists or philosophers of physics on the question of what, if anything, the empirical success of quantum theory is telling us about the physical world. This gives rise to the collection of philosophical issues known as “the interpretation of quantum mechanics”. One should not be misled by this terminology into thinking that what we have is an uninterpreted mathematical formalism with no connection to the physical world. Rather, there is a common core of interpretation that consists of recipes for calculating probabilities of outcomes of experiments performed on systems subjected to certain state preparation procedures. What are often referred to as different “interpretations” of quantum mechanics differ on what, if anything, is added to the common core. Arguably, two of the major approaches, hidden-variables theories and collapse theories, involve formulation of physical theories distinct from standard quantum mechanics; this renders the terminology of “interpretation” even more inappropriate.

Much of the philosophical literature connected with quantum theory centers on the problem of whether we should construe the theory, or a suitable extension or revision of it, in realist terms, and, if so, how this should be done. Various approaches to the “Measurement Problem” propose differing answers to these questions. There are, however, other questions of philosophical interest. These include the bearing of quantum nonlocality on our understanding of spacetime structure and causality, the question of the ontological character of quantum states, the implications of quantum mechanics for information theory, and the task of situating quantum theory with respect to other theories, both actual and hypothetical. In what follows, we will touch on each of these topics, with the main goal being to provide an entry into the relevant literature, including the Stanford Encyclopedia entries on these topics.

2. Quantum Theory

In this section we present a brief introduction to quantum theory; see the entry on quantum mechanics for a more detailed introduction.

2.1 Quantum states and classical states

In classical physics, with any physical system is associated a state space, which represents the totality of possible ways of assigning values to the dynamical variables that characterize the state of the system. For example, for a system consisting of \(n\) point particles, the state of the system is given by specifying the positions and momenta of all of the particles with respect to some reference frame. For systems of a great many degrees of freedom, a complete specification of the state of the system may be unavailable or unwieldy; classical statistical mechanics deals with such a situation by invoking a probability distribution over the state space of the system. A probability distribution that assigns any probability other than one or zero to some physical quantities is regarded as an incomplete specification of the state of the system.

In quantum mechanics, things are different. There are no quantum states that assign definite values to all physical quantities, and probabilities are built into the standard formulation of the theory. Construction of a quantum theory of some physical system proceeds by first associating the dynamical degrees of freedom with operators on an appropriately constructed Hilbert space (see the entry on quantum mechanics for details). A state can be characterized by an assignment of expectation values to physical quantities (“observables”). These assignments are required to respect algebraic relations between the corresponding operators. A complete set of such expectation values is equivalent to a specification of probabilities for outcomes of all experiments that could be performed on the system. Two physical quantities are said to be compatible if there is a single experiment that yields values for them both; these are associated with operators that commute, that is, operators \(A\), \(B\) such that \(AB = BA\). Incompatible observables give rise to uncertainty relations; see the entry on the uncertainty principle.

A pure state, that is, a maximally specific assignment of expectation values, may be represented in a number of physically equivalent ways, for instance by a vector in the Hilbert space or a projection operator onto a one-dimensional subspace. In addition to pure states, one can also consider non-pure states, called mixed; these are represented by operators called density operators. If a pure state assigns a definite value to a physical quantity, a vector that represents the state will be an eigenvector of the corresponding operator. This gives rise to what has been called the “eigenstate-eigenvalue link”, that is, the interpretative principle that, if a system is assigned a state vector that is an eigenvector of some operator representing a physical quantity, then the corresponding dynamical quantity has the corresponding value, and this can be regarded as a property of the physical system.

The noncontroversial core of quantum theory consists of rules for identifying, for any given system, the appropriate operators representing its dynamical quantities, and an appropriate Hilbert space for these operators to act on. In addition, there are prescriptions for evolving the state of system when it is acted upon by specified external fields or subjected to various manipulations (see section 1.3).

Whether we can or can expect to be able to go beyond this noncontroversial core, and take the theory to be more than a means for calculating probabilities of outcomes of experiments, is an issue that remains a topic of contemporary philosophical discussion.

2.2 Quantum mechanics and quantum field theory

Quantum mechanics is usually taken to refer to the quantized version of a theory of classical mechanics, involving systems with a fixed, finite number of degrees of freedom. Classically, a field, such as, for example, an electromagnetic field, is a system endowed with infinitely many degrees of freedom. Quantization of a field theory gives rise to a quantum field theory. The chief philosophical issues raised by quantum mechanics remain when the transition is made to a quantum field theory; in addition, new interpretational issues arise. There are interesting differences, both technical and interpretational, between quantum mechanical theories and quantum field theories; for an overview, see the entries on quantum field theory and quantum theory: von Neumann vs. Dirac.

The standard model of quantum field theory, successful as it is, does not yet incorporate gravitation. The attempt to develop a theory that does justice both the quantum phenomena and to gravitational phenomena gives rise to serious conceptual issues (see the entry on quantum gravity).

2.3 Quantum state evolution

2.3.1. The Schrödinger equation

The equation of motion obeyed by a quantum state vector is the Schrödinger equation. It is constructed by first forming the operator \(H\) corresponding to the Hamiltonian of the system, which represents the total energy of the system. The rate of change of a state vector is proportional to the result of operating on the vector with the Hamiltonian operator \(H\).

\[ i \hbar {\,\D}/{\D t}\, \ket{\psi (t)} = H \ket{\psi (t)}. \]

There is an operator that takes a state at time 0 into a state at time \(t\); it is given by

\[ U(t) = \exp\left(\frac{{-}i H t}{\hbar}\right). \]

This operator is a linear operator that implements a one-one mapping of the Hilbert space to itself that preserves the inner product of any two vectors; operators with these properties are called unitary operators, and, for this reason, evolution according to the Schrödinger equation is called unitary evolution.

For our purposes, the most important features of this equation is that it is deterministic and linear. The state vector at any time, together with the equation, uniquely determines the state vector at any other time. Linearity means that, if two vectors \(\ket{\psi_1(0)}\) and \(\ket{\psi_2(0)}\) evolve into vectors \(\ket{\psi_1(t) }\) and \(\ket{\psi_2(t)}\), respectively, then, if the state at time 0 is a linear combination of these two, the state at any time \(t\) will be the corresponding linear combination of \(\ket{\psi_1(t)}\) and \(\ket{\psi_2(t)}\).

\[ a\ket{\psi_{1}(0)} + b\ket{\psi_{2}(0)} \rightarrow a\ket{\psi_{1}(t)} + b\ket{\psi_{2}(t)} . \]

2.3.2. The collapse postulate

Textbook formulations of quantum mechanics usually include an additional postulate about how to assign a state vector after an experiment. This has its origins in von Neumann’s distinction between two types of processes: Process 1, which occurs upon performance of an experiment, and Process 2, the unitary evolution that takes place as long as no experiment is made (see von Neumann 1932, 1955: §V.1). In Dirac’s formulation, the postulate is

When we measure a real dynamical variable \(\xi\), the disturbance involved in the act of measurement causes a jump in the state of the dynamical system. From physical continuity, if we make a second measurement of the same dynamical variable \(\xi\) immediately after the first, the result of the second measurement must be the same as that of the first. Thus after the first measurement has been made, there is no indeterminacy in the result of the second. Hence, after the first measurement has been made, the system is in an eigenstate of the dynamical variable \(\xi\), the eigenvalue it belongs to being equal to the result of the first measurement. This conclusion must still hold if the second measurement is not actually made. In this way we see that a measurement always causes the system to jump into an eigenstate of the dynamical variable that is being measured, the eigenvalue this eigenstate belongs to being equal to the result of the measurement (Dirac 1935: 36).

Dirac’s “jump” has come to be known as state vector collapse or wave-function collapse, and the postulation of a jump of this sort is called the collapse postulate, or projection postulate.

If the quantum state vector is thought to represent only a state of belief or knowledge about a physical system, and not the physical state of the system, then one could regard an abrupt shift in the state vector upon measurement as a shift corresponding to incorporating the result of the measurement into one’s belief state. Neither von Neumann nor Dirac, however, seem to think of it this way; it is treated by both as a physical process. Note, also, that Dirac expresses the postulate in terms of “measurement”, rather than “observation”; there is no suggestion that a conscious observer must become aware of the result of the measurement in order for a collapse to occur. Though, in his extended discussion of the measurement process, von Neumann (1932, 1955, Ch. VI) does discuss the act of observation, he emphasizes that the collapse postulate may be applied to interactions with quantum systems with measuring apparatus, before an observer is aware of the result. A formulation of a version of the collapse postulate according to which a measurement is not completed until the result is observed is found in London and Bauer (1939). They deny, however, that it represents a mysterious kind of interaction between the observer and the quantum system; for them, the replacement of the pre-observation state vector with a new one is a matter of the observer acquiring new information. These two interpretations of the collapse postulate, as either a real change of the physical state of the system, or as a mere updating of information on the part of an observer, have persisted in the literature.

If state vector collapse is to be regarded as a physical process, this raises the question of what physically distinguishes interventions that are to count as “measurements”, capable of inducing an abrupt jump in the state of the system, from other interventions, which induce only continuous, unitary evolution. As John S. Bell (1990) has argued, “measurement” is not an appropriate concept to appear in the formulation of any physical theory that might be taken to be fundamental. If, however, one dispenses with the postulate, this gives rise to the so-called “measurement problem”, which we will discuss after we have introduced the notion of entanglement (see section 3).

3. Entanglement, nonlocality, and nonseparability

Given two disjoint physical systems, \(A\) and \(B\), with which we associate Hilbert spaces \(H_{A}\) and \(H_{B}\), the Hilbert space associated with the composite system is the tensor product space, denoted \(H_{A} \otimes H_{B}\).

When the two systems are independently prepared in pure states \(\ket{\psi}\) and \(\ket{\phi}\), the state of the composite system is the product state \(\ket{\psi} \otimes \ket{\phi}\) (sometimes written with the cross, \(\otimes\), omitted).

In addition to the product states, the tensor product space contains linear combinations of product states, that is, state vectors of the form

\[ a\ket{\psi_{1}} \otimes \ket{\phi_{1}} + b\ket{\psi_{2}} \otimes \ket{\phi_{2}} \]

The tensor product space can be defined as the smallest Hilbert space containing all of the product states. Any pure state represented by a state vector that is not a product vector is an entangled state.

The state of the composite system assigns probabilities to outcomes of all experiments that can be performed on the composite system. We can also consider a restriction to experiments performed on system \(A\), or a restriction to experiments performed to \(B\). Such restrictions yields states of \(A\) and \(B\), respectively, called the reduced states of the systems. When the state of the composite system \(AB\) is an entangled state, then the reduced states of \(A\) and \(B\) are mixed states. To see this, suppose that in the above state the vectors \(\ket{\phi_{1}}\) and \(\ket{\phi_{2}}\) represent distinguishable states. If one confines one’s attention to experiments performed on \(A\), it makes no difference whether an experiment is also performed on \(B\). An experiment performed on \(B\) that distinguishes \(\ket{\phi_{1}}\) and \(\ket{\phi_{2}}\) projects the state of \(A\) into either \(\ket{\psi_{1}}\) or \(\ket{\psi_{2}}\), with probabilities \(\abs{a}^{2}\) and \(\abs{b}^{2}\), respectively, and probabilities for outcomes of experiments performed on \(A\) are the corresponding averages of probabilities for states \(\ket{\psi_{1}}\) and \(\ket{\psi_{2}}\). These probabilities, as mentioned, are the same as those for the situation in which no experiment is performed on \(B\). Thus, even if no experiment is performed on \(B\), the probabilities of outcomes of experiments on \(A\) are exactly as if system \(A\) is either in the state represented by \(\ket{\psi_{1}}\) or the state represented by \(\ket{\psi_{2}}\), with probabilities \(\abs{a}^{2}\) and \(\abs{b}^{2}\), respectively.

In general, any state, pure or mixed, that is neither a product state nor a mixture of product states, is called an entangled state.

The existence of pure entangled states means that, if we consider a composite system consisting of spatially separated parts, then, even when the state of the system is a pure state, the state is not determined by the reduced states of its component parts. Thus, quantum states exhibit a form of nonseparability. See the entry on holism and nonseparability in physics for more information.

Quantum entanglement results in a form of nonlocality that is alien to classical physics. Even if we assume that the reduced states of \(A\) and \(B\) do not completely characterize their physical states, but must be supplemented by some further variables, there are quantum correlations that cannot be reduced to correlations between states of \(A\) and \(B\); see the entries on Bell’s Theorem and action at a distance in quantum mechanics.

4. The measurement problem

4.1 The measurement problem formulated

If quantum theory is meant to be (in principle) a universal theory, it should be applicable, in principle, to all physical systems, including systems as large and complicated as our experimental apparatus. Consider, now, a schematized experiment. Suppose we have a quantum system that can be prepared in at least two distinguishable states, \(\ket{0} _{S}\) and \(\ket{1} _{S}\). Let \(\ket{R} _{A}\) be a ready state of the apparatus, that is, a state in which the apparatus is ready to make a measurement.

If the apparatus is working properly, and if the measurement is a minimally disturbing one, the coupling of the system \(S\) with the apparatus \(A\) should result in an evolution that predictably yields results of the form

\[ \ket{0} _{S} \ket{R} _{A} \Rightarrow \ket{0} _{S}\ket{“0” } _{A} \] \[ \ket{1} _{S} \ket{R} _{A} \Rightarrow \ket{1} _{S}\ket{“1”} _{A} \]

where \(\ket{“0” } _{A}\) and \(\ket{“1”} _{A}\) are apparatus states indicating results 0 and 1, respectively.

Now suppose that the system \(S\) is prepared in a superposition of the states \(\ket{0} _{S}\) and \(\ket{1}_{S}\).

\[ \ket{\psi(0)} _{S} = a\ket{0} _{S} + b\ket{1} _{S}, \]

where \(a\) and \(b\) are both nonzero. If the evolution that leads from the pre-experimental state to the post-experimental state is linear Schrödinger evolution, then we will have

\[ \ket{\psi(0)} _{S} \ket{R} _{A} \rightarrow a\ket{0} _{S} \ket{“0” } _{A} + b\ket{1} _{S}\ket{“1” } _{A}. \]

This is not an eigenstate of the instrument reading variable, but is, rather, a state in the reading variable and the system variable are entangled with each other. The eigenstate-eigenvalue link, applied to a state like this, does not yield a definite result for the instrument reading. The problem of what to make of this is called the “measurement problem” which is discussed in more detail below.

4.2 Approaches to the measurement problem

If quantum state evolution proceeds via the Schrödinger equation or some other linear equation, then, as we have seen in the previous section, typical experiments will lead to quantum states that are superpositions of terms corresponding to distinct experimental outcomes. It is sometimes said that this conflicts with our experience, according to which experimental outcome variables, such as pointer readings, always have definite values. This is a misleading way of putting the issue, as it is not immediately clear how to interpret states of this sort as physical states of a system that includes experimental apparatus, and, if we can’t say what it would be like to observe the apparatus to be in such a state, it makes no sense to say that we never observe it to be in a state like that.

Nonetheless, we are faced with an interpretational problem. If we take the quantum state to be a complete description of the system, then the state is, contrary to what would antecedently expect, not a state corresponding to a unique, definite outcome. This is what led J.S. Bell to remark, “Either the wavefunction, as given by the Schrödinger equation, is not everything, or it is not right” (Bell 1987: 41, 2004: 201). This gives us a (prima facie) tidy way of classifying approaches to the measurement problem:

  1. There are approaches that involve a denial that a quantum wave function (or any other way of representing a quantum state) yields a complete description of a physical system.
  2. There are approaches that involve modification of the dynamics to produce a collapse of the wave function in appropriate circumstances.
  3. There are approaches that reject both horns of Bell’s dilemma, and hold that quantum states undergo unitary evolution at all times and that a quantum state-description is, in principle, complete.

We include in the first category approaches that deny that a quantum state should be thought of as representing anything in reality at all. These include variants of the Copenhagen interpretation, as well as pragmatic and other anti-realist approaches. Also in the first category are approaches that seek a completion of the quantum state description. These include hidden-variables approaches and modal interpretations. The second category of interpretation motivates a research programme of finding suitable indeterministic modifications of the quantum dynamics. Approaches that reject both horns of Bell’s dilemma are typified by Everettian, or “many-worlds” interpretations.

4.2.1 Non-realist approaches to quantum mechanics

From the early days of quantum mechanics, there has been a strain of thought that holds that the proper attitude to take towards quantum mechanics is an instrumentalist or pragmatic one. On such a view, quantum mechanics is a tool for coordinating our experience and for forming expectations about the outcomes of experiments. Variants of this view include what has been called the Copenhagen Interpretation (or Copenhagen Interpretations, as recent scholarship has emphasized differences between figures associated with this view); see the entry on Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics. More recently, views of this sort have been advocated by physicists, including QBists, who hold that quantum states represent subjective or epistemic probabilities (see Fuchs et al. 2014). The philosopher Richard Healey defends a related view on which quantum states, though objective, do not represent physical reality (see Healey 2012; Healey forthcoming).

4.2.2 Hidden-variables and modal interpretations

Theories whose structure include the quantum state but include additional structure, with an aim of circumventing the measurement problem, have traditionally been called “hidden-variables theories”. That a quantum state description cannot be regarded as a complete description of physical reality was argued for in a famous paper by Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen (EPR) and by Einstein in subsequent publications (Einstein 1936, 1948, 1949). See the entry on the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen argument in quantum theory.

There are a number of theorems that circumscribe the scope of possible hidden-variables theories. The most natural thought would be to seek a theory that assigns to all quantum observables definite values that are merely revealed upon measurement, in such a way that any experimental procedure that, in conventional quantum mechanics, would count as a “measurement” of an observable yields the definite value assigned to the observable. Theories of this sort are called noncontextual hidden-variables theory. It was shown by Bell (1966) and Kochen and Specker (1967) that there are no such theories for any system whose Hilbert space dimension is greater than three (see the entry on the Kochen-Specker theorem).

The Bell-Kochen-Specker Theorem does not rule out hidden-variables theories tout court. The simplest way to circumvent it is to pick as always-definite some observable or compatible set of observables that suffices to guarantee determinate outcomes of experiments; other observables are not assigned definite values and experiments thought of as “measurements” of these observables do not reveal pre-existing values.

The most thoroughly worked-out theory of this type is the pilot wave theory developed by de Broglie and presented by him at the Fifth Solvay Conference held in Brussels in 1927, revived by David Bohm in 1952, and currently an active area of research by a small group of physicists and philosophers. According to this theory, there are particles with definite trajectories, that are guided by the quantum wave function. For the history of the de Broglie theory, see the introductory chapters of Bacciagaluppi and Valentini 2009. For any overview of the de Broglie-Bohm theory and philosophical issues associated with it see the entry on Bohmian mechanics.

There have been other proposals for supplementing the quantum state with additional structure; these have come to be called modal interpretations; see the entry on modal interpretations of quantum mechanics

4.2.3 Dynamical Collapse Theories

As already mentioned, von Neumann and Dirac wrote as if the collapse of the quantum state vector precipitated by an experimental intervention on the system is a genuine physical change, distinct from the usual unitary evolution. If collapse is to be taken as a genuine physical process, then something more needs to be said about the circumstances under which it occurs than merely that it happens when an experiment is performed. This gives rise to a research programme of formulating a precisely defined dynamics for the quantum state that approximates the linear, unitary Schrödinger evolution in situations for which this is well-confirmed, and produces collapse to an eigenstate of the outcome variable in typical experimental set-ups, or, failing that, a close approximation to an eigenstate. The only promising collapse theories are stochastic in nature; indeed, it can be shown that a deterministic collapse theory would permit superluminal signalling. (see the entry on collapse theories for an overview).

Prima facie, a dynamical collapse theory of this type can be a quantum state monist theory, one on which, in Bell’s words, “the wave function is everything”. In recent years, this has been disputed; it has been argued that collapse theories require “primitive ontology” in addition to the quantum state. See Allori et al. 2008; also the entry on collapse theories, and references therein.

4.2.4 Everettian, or “many worlds” theories

In his doctoral dissertation of 1957 (reprinted in Everett 2012), Hugh Everett III proposed that quantum mechanics be taken as it is, without a collapse postulate and without any “hidden variables”. The resulting interpretation he called the relative state interpretation.

The basic idea is this. After an experiment, the quantum state of the system plus apparatus is typically a superposition of terms corresponding to distinct outcomes. As the apparatus interacts with its environment, which may include observers, these systems become entangled with the apparatus and quantum system, the net result of which is a quantum state involving, for each of the possible experimental outcomes, a term in which the apparatus reading corresponds to that outcome, there are records of that outcome in the environment, observers observe that outcome, etc.. Everett proposed that each of these terms be taken to be equally real. From a God’s-eye-view, there is no unique experimental outcome, but one can also focus on a particular determinate state of one subsystem, say, the experimental apparatus, and attribute to the other systems participating in the entangled state a relative state, relative to that state of the apparatus. That is, relative to the apparatus reading ‘+’ is a state of the environment recording that result and states of observers observing that result (see the entry on Everett’s relative-state formulation of quantum mechanics, for more detail on Everett’s views).

Everett’s work has inspired a family of views that go by the name of “Many Worlds” interpretations; the idea is that each of the terms of the superposition corresponds to a coherent world, and all of these worlds are equally real. As time goes on, there is a proliferation of these worlds, as situations arise that give rise to a further multiplicity of outcomes (see the entry many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics, and Saunders 2007, for overviews of recent discussions; Wallace 2012 is an extended defense of an Everettian interpretation of quantum mechanics).

There is a family of distinct, but related views, that go by the name of “Relational Quantum Mechanics”. These views agree with Everett in attributing to a system definite values of dynamical variables only relative to the states of other systems; they differ in that, unlike Everett, they do not take the quantum state as their basic ontology (see the entry on relational quantum mechanics for more detail).

4.3 The role of decoherence

A quantum state that is a superposition of two distinct terms, such as

\[ \ket{\psi} = a \ket{\psi_{1}} + b \ket{\psi_{2}} , \]

where \(\ket{\psi_{1}}\) and \(\ket{\psi_{2}}\) are distinguishable states, is not the same state as a mixture of \(\ket{\psi_{1}}\) and \(\ket{\psi_{2}}\), which would be appropriate for a situation in which the state prepared was either \(\ket{\psi_{1}}\) or \(\ket{\psi_{2}}\), but we don’t know which. The difference between a coherent superposition of two terms and a mixture has empirical consequences. To see this, consider the double-slit experiment, in which a beam of particles (such as electrons, neutrons, or photons) passes through two narrow slits and then impinges on a screen, where the particles are detected. Take \(\ket{\psi_{1}}\) to be a state in which a particle passes through the top slit, and \(\ket{\psi_{2}}\), a state in which it passes through the bottom slit. The fact that the state is a superposition of these two alternatives is exhibited in interference fringes at the screen, alternating bands of high and low rates of absorption.

This is often expressed in terms of a difference between classical and quantum probabilities. If the particles were classical particles, the probability of detection at some point \(p\) of the screen would simply be a weighted average of two conditional probabilities: the probability of detection at \(p\), given that the particle passed through the top slit, and the probability of detection at \(p\), given that the particle passed through the bottom slit. The appearance of interference is an index of nonclassicality.

Suppose, now, that the electrons interact with something else (call it the environment) on the way to the screen, that could serve as a “which-way” detector; that is, the state of this auxiliary system becomes entangled with the state of the electron in such a way that its state is correlated with \(\ket{\psi_{1}}\) and \(\ket{\psi_{2}}\). Then the state of the quantum system, \(s\), and its environment, \(e\), is

\[ \ket{\psi} _{se} = a \ket{ \psi_{1}} _{s} \ket{ \phi_{1}} _{e} + b \ket{ \psi_{2}}_{s} \ket{ \phi_{2}} _{e} \]

If the environment states \(\ket{\phi_{1}} _{e}\) are \(\ket{\phi_{2}}_{e}\) are distinguishable states, then this completely destroys the interference fringes: the particles interact with the screen as if they determinately went through one slit or the other, and the pattern that emerges is the result of overlaying the two single-slit patterns. That is, we can treat the particles as if they obeyed (approximately) definite trajectories, and apply probabilities in a classical manner.

Now, macroscopic objects are typically in interaction with a large and complex environment—they are constantly being bombarded with air molecules, photons, and the like. As a result, the reduced state of such a system quickly becomes a mixture of quasi-classical states, a phenomenon known as decoherence.

A generalization of decoherence lies at the heart of an approach to the interpretation of quantum mechanics that goes by the name of decoherent histories approach (see the entry on the consistent histories approach to quantum mechanics for an overview).

Decoherence plays important roles in the other approaches to quantum mechanics, though the role it plays varies with approach; see the entry on the role of decoherence in quantum mechanics for information on this.

4.4 Comparison of approaches to the measurement problem

All of the above approaches take it that the goal is to provide an account of events in the world that recovers, at least in some approximation, something like our familiar world of ordinary objects behaving classically. None of the mainstream approaches accord any special physical role to conscious observers. There have, however, been proposals in that direction (see the entry on quantum approaches to consciousness for discussion).

All of the above-mentioned approaches are consistent with observation. Mere consistency, however, is not enough; the rules for connecting quantum theory with experimental results typically involve nontrivial (that is, not equal to zero or one) probabilities assigned to experimental outcomes. These calculated probabilities are confronted with empirical evidence in the form of statistical data from repeated experiments. Extant hidden-variables theories reproduce the quantum probabilities, and collapse theories have the intriguing feature of reproducing very close approximations to quantum probabilities for all experiments that have been performed so far but departing from the quantum probabilities for other conceivable experiments. This permits, in principle, an empirical discrimination between such theories and no-collapse theories.

A criticism that has been raised against Everettian theories is that it is not clear whether they can even make sense of statistical testing of this kind, as it does not, in any straightforward way, make sense to talk of the probability of obtaining, say, a ‘+” outcome of a given experiment when it is certain that all possible outcomes will occur on some branch of the wavefunction. This has been called the “Everettian evidential problem”. It has been the subject of much recent work on Everettian theories; see Saunders (2007) for an introduction and overview.

If one accepts that Everettians have a solution to the evidential problem, then, among the major lines of approach, none is favored in a straightforward way by the empirical evidence. If one is to make a decision as to which, if any, one should accept, it is to be made on other grounds. There will not be space here to give an in-depth overview of these ongoing discussions, but a few considerations can be mentioned, to give the reader a flavor of the discussions; see entries on particular approaches for more detail.

Bohmians claim, in favor of the Bohmian approach, that a theory on these lines provides the most straightforward picture of events; ontological issues are less clear-cut when it comes to Everettian theories or collapse theories.

Another consideration is compatibility with relativistic causal structure. The de Broglie-Bohm theory requires a distinguished relation of distant simultaneity for its formulation, and, it can be argued, this is an ineliminable feature of any hidden-variables theory of this sort, that selects some observable to always have definite values (see Berndl et al. 1996; Myrvold 2002). On the other hand, there are collapse models that are fully relativistic. On such models, collapses are localized events. Though probabilities of collapses at spacelike separation from each other are not independent, this probabilistic dependence does not require us to single one out as earlier and the other later. Thus, such theories do not require a distinguished relation of distant simultaneity. There remains, however, some discussion of how to equip such theories with beables (or “elements of reality”). See the entry on collapse theories and references therein; see also, for two recent contributions to the discussion, Fleming 2016, Maudlin 2016, and Myrvold 2016.

In the case of Everettian theories, one must first think about how to formulate the question of relativistic locality. Several authors have approached this issue in somewhat different ways, with a common conclusion that Everettian quantum mechanics is, indeed, local. (See Vaidman 1994; Baccialuppi 2002; Chapter 8 of Wallace 2012; Tipler 2014; Vaidman 2016; and Brown and Timpson 2016.)

5. Ontological Issues

As mentioned, a central question of interpretation of quantum mechanics concerns whether quantum states should be regarded as representing anything in physical reality. If this is answered in the affirmative, this gives rise to new questions, namely, what sort of physical reality is represented by the quantum state, and whether a quantum state could in principle give an exhaustive account of physical reality.

5.1 The question of quantum state realism.

Harrigan and Spekkens (2010) have introduced a framework for discussing these issues. In their terminology, a complete specification of the physical properties is given by the ontic state of a system. An ontological model posits a space of ontic states and associates, with any preparation procedure, a probability distribution over ontic states. A model is said to be \(\psi\)-ontic if the ontic state uniquely determines the quantum state; that is, if there is a function from ontic states to quantum states (this includes both cases in which the quantum state also completely determines the physical state, and cases, such as hidden-variables theories, in which the quantum state does not completely determine the physical state). In their terminology, models that are not \(\psi\)-ontic are called \(\psi\)-epistemic. If a model is not \(\psi\)-ontic, this means that it is possible for some ontic states to be the result of two or more preparations that lead to different assignments of pure quantum states; that is, the same ontic state may be compatible with distinct quantum states.

This gives a nice way of posing the question of quantum state realism: are there preparations corresponding to distinct pure quantum states that can give rise to the same ontic state, or, conversely, are there ontic states compatible with distinct quantum states? Pusey, Barrett, and Rudolph (2012) showed that, if one adopts a natural independence assumption about state preparations—namely, the assumption that it is possible to prepare a pair of systems in such a way that the probabilities for ontic states of the two systems are effectively independent—then the answer is negative; any ontological model that reproduces quantum predictions and satisfies this Preparation Independence assumption must be a \(\psi\)-ontic model.

The Pusey, Barrett and Rudolph (PBR) theorem does not close off all options for anti-realism about quantum states; an anti-realist about quantum states could reject the Preparation Independence assumption, or reject the framework within which the theorem is set; see discussion in Spekkens 2015: 92–93. See also Leifer (2014) for a careful and thorough overview of theorems relevant to quantum state realism.

5.2 Ontological category of quantum states

The major realist approaches to the measurement problem are all, in some sense, realist about quantum states. Merely saying this is insufficient to give an account of the ontology of a given interpretation. Among the questions to be addressed are: if quantum states represent something physically real, what sort of thing is it? This is the question of the ontological construal of quantum states. Another question is the EPR question, whether a description in terms of quantum states can be taken as, in principle, complete, or whether it must be supplemented by different ontology.

De Broglie’s original conception of the “pilot wave” was that it would be a field, analogous to an electromagnetic field. The original conception was that each particle would have its own guiding wave. However, in quantum mechanics as it was developed at the hands of Schrödinger, for a system of two or more particles we don’t have individual wave functions for each particle, but, rather, a single wave function that is defined on \(n\)-tuples of points in space, where \(n\) is the number of particles. This was taken, by de Broglie, Schrödinger and others, to militate against the conception of quantum wave functions as fields. If quantum states represent something in physical reality, they are unlike anything familiar in classical physics.

One response that has been taken is to insist that quantum wave functions are fields nonetheless, albeit fields on a space of enormously high dimension, namely, \(3n\), where \(n\) is the number of elementary particles in the universe. On this view, this high-dimensional space is thought of as more fundamental than the familiar three-dimensional space (or four-dimensional spacetime) that is usually taken to be the arena of physical events. See Albert (1996, 2013), for the classic statement of the view; other proponents include Loewer (1996), Lewis (2004), Ney (2012, 2013a,b, 2015), and North (2013). Most of the discussion of this proposal has taken place within the context of nonrelativistic quantum mechanics, which is not a fundamental theory. It has been argued that considerations of how the wave functions of nonrelativistic quantum mechanics arise from a quantum field theory undermines the idea that wave functions are relevantly like fields on configuration space, and also the idea that configuration spaces can be thought of as more fundamental than ordinary spacetime (Myrvold 2015).

A view that takes a wave function as a field on a high-dimensional space must be distinguished from a view that takes it to be what Belot (2012) has called a multi-field, which assigns properties to \(n\)-tuples of points of ordinary three-dimensional space. These are distinct views; proponents of the \(3n\)-dimensional conception make much of the fact that it restores Separability: on this view, a complete specification of the way the world is, at some time, is given by specification of local states of affairs at each address in the fundamental (\(3n\)-dimensional) space. Taking a wave function to be a multi-field, on the other hand, involves accepting nonseparability. Another difference between taking wave-functions as multi-fields on ordinary space and taking them to be fields on a high-dimensional space is that, on the multi-field view, there is no question about the relation of ordinary three-dimensional space to some more fundamental space.­

It has been argued that, on the de Broglie-Bohm pilot wave theory and related pilot wave theories, the quantum state plays a role more similar to that of a law in classical mechanics; its role is to provide dynamics for the Bohmian corpuscles, which, according to the theory, compose ordinary objects. See Dürr, Goldstein, and Zanghì 1997 and Allori et al. 2008.

Dürr, Goldstein, and Zanghì (1992) introduced the term “primitive ontology” for what, according to a physical theory, makes up ordinary physical objects; on the de Broglie-Bohm theory, this is the Bohmian corpuscles. The conception is extended to interpretations of collapse theories by Allori et al. (2008). Primitive ontology is to be distinguished from other ontology, such as the quantum state, that is introduced into the theory to account for the behavior of the primitive ontology. The distinction is meant to be a guide as to how to conceive of the nonprimitive ontology of the theory.

6. Quantum computing and quantum information theory

Quantum mechanics has not only given rise to interpretational conundrums; it has given rise to new concepts in computing and in information theory. Quantum information theory is the study of the possibilities for information processing and transmission opened up by quantum theory. This has given rise to a different perspective on quantum theory, one on which, as Bub (2000, 597) put it, “the puzzling features of quantum mechanics are seen as a resource to be developed rather than a problem to be solved” (see the entries on quantum computing and quantum entanglement and information).

7. Reconstructions of quantum mechanics and beyond

Another area of active research in the foundations of quantum mechanics is the attempt to gain deeper insight into the structure of the theory, and the ways in which it differs from both classical physics and other theories that one might construct, by characterizing the structure of the theory in terms of very general principles, often with an information-theoretic flavour.

This project has its roots in early work of Mackey (1957, 1963), Ludwig (1964), and Piron (1964) aiming to characterize quantum mechanics in operational terms. This has led to the development of a framework of generalized probabilistic model. It also has connections with the investigations into quantum logic initiated by Birkhoff and von Neumann (1936) (see the entry quantum logic and probability theory for an overview).

Interest in the project of deriving quantum theory from axioms with clear operational content was revived by the work of Hardy (2001 [2008], Other Internet Resources). Significant results along these lines include the axiomatizations of Masanes and Müller (2011) and Chiribella, D’Ariano, and Perinotti (2011). See Spekkens and Chiribella 2015 for a snapshot of the state of the art of this endeavour.

Bibliography

  • Albert, David Z., 1996, “Elementary quantum metaphysics”, in J.T. Cushing, A. Fine, & S. Goldstein (eds.), Bohmian Mechanics and Quantum Mechanics: An appraisal, Dordrecht: Kluwer, 277–284.
  • –––, 2013, “Wave function realism”, in Ney and Albert (eds.) 2013: 52–57.
  • Allori, Valia, Sheldon Goldstein, Roderich Tumulka, and Nino Zanghì, 2008, “On the Common Structure of Bohmian Mechanics and the Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber Theory”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59(3): 353–389. doi:10.1093/bjps/axn012
  • Bacciagaluppi, Guido, 2002, “Remarks on Space-time and Locality in Everett’s Interpretation”, in T. Placzek and J. Butterfield (eds), Non-locality and Modality, Berlin: Springer, 105–124.
  • Bacciagaluppi, Guido, and Antony Valentini, 2009, Quantum Theory at the Crossroads: Reconsidering the 1927 Solvay Conference, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Bell, J.S., 1966, “On the Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics”, Reviews of Modern Physics, 38: 447–52. Reprinted in Bell 2004: 1–13.
  • –––, 1987, “Are There Quantum Jumps?” in C.W. Kilmister (ed), Schrödinger: Centenary celebration of a polymath, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 41–52. Reprinted in Bell 2004: 201–212.
  • –––, 1990, “Against ‘Measurement’”, Physics World, 3: 33–40. Reprinted in Bell 2004: 213–231.
  • –––, 2004, Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics, 2nd edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Bell, Mary and Shan Gao (eds.), 2016, Quantum Nonlocality and Reality: 50 Years of Bell’s Theorem, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Belot, Gordon, 2012, “Quantum States for primitive ontologists: a case study”, European Journal for the Philosophy of Science 2: 67–83.
  • Berndl, Karin, Detlef Dürr, Sheldon Goldstein, and Nino Zanghì, 1996, “Nonlocality, Lorentz invariance, and Bohmian quantum theory”, Physical Review A, 53: 2062–2073.
  • Birkhoff, Garrett, and John von Neumann, 1936, “The Logic of Quantum Mechanics”, Annals of Mathematics (Second series), 37: 823–43.
  • Brown, Harvey R. and Christopher G. Timpson, 2016,“Bell on Bell’s Theorem: The Changing Face of Nonlocality”, in Bell and Gao (eds.) 2016: 91–123.
  • Bub, Jeffrey, 2000, “Indeterminacy and entanglement: the challenge of quantum mechanics”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51: 597–615.
  • Chiribella, Giulio, Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano, and Paolo Perinotti, 2011, “Informational derivation of quantum theory”, Physical Review A, 84: 012311. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.84.012311
  • Chiribella, Giulio and Robert W. Spekkens (eds), 2015, Quantum Theory: Informational Foundations and Foils, Berlin: Springer.
  • Deutsch, David and Patrick Hayden, 2000, “Information flow in entangled quantum systems”, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A, 456: 1759–74.
  • Dirac, P.A.M., 1935, Principles of Quantum Mechanics, 2nd edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Dürr, Detlef, Sheldon Goldstein, and Nino Zanghì, “Quantum Equilibrium and the Origin of Absolute Uncertainty”, Journal of Statistical Physics 67:843–907.
  • –––, 1997, “Bohmian Mechanics and the Meaning of the Wave Function”, in R.S. Cohen, M. Horne and J. Stachel (eds), Experimental Metaphysics: Quantum Mechanical Studies for Abner Shimony, Volume One, Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Einstein, Albert, Boris Podolsky, and Nathan Rosen, 1935, “Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Reality Be Considered Complete?” Physical Review, 47: 777–780.
  • Einstein, Albert, 1936, “Physik und Realität”, Journal of the Franklin Institute, 221: 349–382. English translation in Einstein 1954.
  • –––, 1948, “Quanten-Mechanik und Wirklichkeit”, Dialectica, 2: 320–324.
  • –––, 1949, “Autobiographical notes”, in P.A. Schilpp (ed.), Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, Chicago: Open Court.
  • –––, 1954, “Physics and reality”, in Ideas and Opinions, New York: Crown Publishers, Inc., 290–323. Translation of Einstein 1936.
  • Everett, Hugh, III, 2012, The Everett Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Collected Works 1955–1980 With Commentary, Jeffrey A. Barrett and Peter Byrne (eds), Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Fleming, Gordon N., 2016, “Bell Nonlocality, Hardy’s Paradox and Hyperplane Dependence”, in Bell and Gao (eds.) 2016: 261–281.
  • Fuchs, Christopher A., N. David Mermin, and Rüdiger Schack, 2014, “An introduction to QBism with an application to the locality of quantum mechanics”, American Journal of Physics, 82: 749–752.
  • Harrigan, Nicholas and Robert W. Spekkens, 2010, “Einstein, Incompleteness, and the Epistemic View of Quantum States”, Foundations of Physics, 40: 125–157.
  • Healey, Richard, 2012, “Quantum Theory: A Pragmatist Approach”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63: 729–771.
  • –––, forthcoming, “Quantum States as Objective Informational Bridges”, Foundations of Physics. doi:10.1007/s10701-015-9949-7
  • Kochen, Simon and Ernst Specker, 1967, “The Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics”, Journal of Mathematics and Mechanics, 17: 59–87.
  • Leifer, Matthew Saul, 2014, “Is the Quantum State Real? An Extended Review of \(\psi\)-ontology Theorems”, Quanta, 3: 67–155.
  • Lewis, Peter J., 2004, “Life in configuration space”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55: 713–729. doi:10.1093/bjps/55.4.713
  • Loewer, B., 1996, “Humean supervenience”, Philosophical Topics, 24: 101–127.
  • London, Fritz and Edmond Bauer, 1939, La théorie de l’observation en mécanique quantique, Paris: Hermann. English translation, “The theory of observation in quantum mechanics”, in Quantum Theory and Measurement, J.A. Wheeler and W.H. Zurek (eds), Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983, 217–259.
  • Ludwig, G., 1964, “Versuch einer axiomatischen Grundlegung der Quantenmechanik und allgemeinerer physikalischer Theorien”, Zeitschrift für Physik, 181: 233–260.
  • Mackey, George W. 1957, “Quantum Mechanics and Hilbert Space”, American Mathematical Monthly, 64: 45–57.
  • –––,1963, The Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics: A lecture-note volume, New York: W.A. Benjamin.
  • Masanes, Lluís and Markus P. Müller, 2011, “A derivation of quantum theory from physical Requirements”, New Journal of Physics, 13: 063001.
  • Maudlin, Tim, 2016, “Local Beables and the Foundations of Physics”, in Bell and Gao (eds.) 2016: 317–330.
  • Myrvold, Wayne C., 2002, “Modal Interpretations and Relativity”, Foundations of Physics, 32: 1773–1784.
  • –––, 2015, “What is a Wavefunction?” Synthese, 192: 3247–3274.
  • –––, 2016, “Lessons of Bell”s Theorem: Nonlocality, Yes; Action at a Distance, Not Necessarily”, in Bell and Gao (eds.) 2016: 237–260.
  • Ney, Alyssa, 2012, “The status of our ordinary three dimensions in a quantum universe”, Noûs, 46: 525–560.
  • –––, 2013a, “Introduction”, in Ney and Albert (eds.) 2013: 1–51.
  • –––, 2013b, “Ontological reduction and the wave function ontology”, in Ney and Albert (eds.) 2013: 168– 183.
  • –––, 2015, “Fundamental physical ontologies and the constraint of empirical coherence: a defense of wave function realism”, Synthese, 192: 3105–3124.
  • Ney, Alyssa and David Z. Albert (eds.), 2013, The Wave Function: Essays on the Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • North, Jill, 2013, “The structure of a quantum world”, in Ney and Albert (eds.) 2013: 184–202.
  • Piron, Constantin, 1964, “Axiomatique quantique”, Helvetica Physica Acta, 37: 439–468.
  • Pusey, Matthew F., Jonathan Barrett, and Terry Rudolph, 2012, “On the Reality of the Quantum State”, Nature Physics, 8: 475–478.
  • Saunders, Simon, 2007. “Many Worlds? An Introduction”, in S. Saunders, J. Barrett, A. Kent, and D. Wallace (eds.), Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory, and Reality, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1–50.
  • Spekkens, Robert W., 2007, “Evidence for the Epistemic view of Quantum States: A Toy Theory”, Physical Review A, 75: 032110.
  • –––, 2015, “Quasi-Quantization: Classical Statistical Theories with an Epistemic Restriction”, in Chiribella and Spekkens 2015: 83–135.
  • Tipler, Frank J., 2014, “Quantum nonlocality does not exist”, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 111: 11281–6.
  • Vaidman, Lev, 1994, “On the paradoxical aspects of new quantum experiments”, in D. Hull, M. Forbes and R.M. Burian (eds.), PSA 1994 Vol. 1 (Philosophy of Science Association), 211–17.
  • –––, 2016, “The Bell Inequality and the Many-Worlds Interpretation”, in Bell and Gao (eds.) 2016: 195–203.
  • von Neumann, John, 1932, Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik, Berlin, Springer Verlag.
  • –––, 1955, Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Robert T. Beyer (trans.), Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Wallace, David, 2012, The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory according to the Everett interpretation, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Other Internet Resources

Copyright © 2016 by
Wayne Myrvold <wmyrvold@uwo.ca>

This is a file in the archives of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Please note that some links may no longer be functional.
[an error occurred while processing the directive]