Notes to Tense and Aspect

1. For a thorough discussion of these issues we refer the reader to Comrie (1985).

2. But see Lecarme (2008) for possible exceptions.

3. But note that verbs, verb phrases or sentences may be nominalized and this nominalization process may transfer verbal properties to nominals. We will not discuss these linguistic subtleties here.

4. For further evidence from Hausa and Chichewâ see Spencer (1991: chapter 1.3).

5. The actions and fluents are assumed to be used uniquely. It is, for instance, not possible that Shoot and Smoke are identical actions. Technically, this can be done by adding a set of uniqueness-of-names-axioms (see e.g., Shanahan 1997). For simplicity, we will leave them out.

6. Precise definitions of logic programs and their completions can be found in Doets (1994) and Nienhuys-Cheng and de Wolf (1997).

7. To be complete we also have to show how to compute the completion of a rule. We will not go into this here. The interested reader is referred to (van Lambalgen and Hamm 2005: definition 14). To give an idea of how this works we will illustrate the completion of two propositional rules with the same head (p1, …, pn, r1, …, rm, q all are propositions):

(i)a.
p1 ∧ … ∧ pnq
b.
r1 ∧ … ∧ rmq

The completion is:

(ii)
q ↔ (p1 ∧ … ∧ pn) ∨ (r1 ∧ … ∧ rm)

This means that q is false iff neither of the rules (ia) or (ib) is true.

8. This agrees with Vendler's philosophical position in chapter five of Vendler 1967.

9. See also Kamp (1991).

10. See our discussion of example (8a) in section 3.

Copyright © 2014 by
Friedrich Hamm <friedrich.hamm@uni-tuebingen.de>
Oliver Bott <oliver.bott@uni-tuebingen.de>

This is a file in the archives of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Please note that some links may no longer be functional.
[an error occurred while processing the directive]