Liberal Feminism
Liberals hold that freedom is a fundamental value, and that the just state ensures freedom for citizens. Liberal feminists share this view, and insist on freedom for women. There is disagreement among liberals about what freedom means, and thus liberal feminism takes more than one form. This entry discusses 1) classical liberal or libertarian feminism and 2) egalitarian liberal feminism.
Classical liberal or libertarian feminism conceives of freedom as freedom from coercive interference. It holds that women, as well as men, have a right to such freedom due to their status as self-owners. It holds that coercive state power is justified only to the extent necessary to protect the right to freedom from coercive interference. Equity feminists are classical liberal or libertarian feminists who hold that, in societies like the United States, the only morally significant source of oppression of women is the state. They hold that feminism's political role is to bring an end to laws that limit women's liberty in particular, but also to laws that grant special privileges to women. Some equity feminists see a nonpolitical role for feminism, helping women to benefit from their freedom by developing beneficial character traits or strategies for success, or navigating among their increasing options. Other equity feminists are socially conservative and argue that, while the state should not enforce them, traditional values function as bulwarks against state power and produce independent and self-restraining citizens. Cultural libertarian feminists are classical liberal or libertarian feminists who hold that the culture of societies like the United States is patriarchal and a significant source of oppression of women. They hold that the patriarchal culture and the state are complementary systems of oppression. Cultural libertarian feminists hold that much of the oppression women suffer today is noncoercive, however, and thus should not be met with state remedies but with a nonviolent movement for feminist social change. Readers interested in classical liberal or libertarian feminism may want to skip ahead to that section now.
Egalitarian liberal feminism conceives of freedom as personal autonomy — living a life of one's own choosing — and political autonomy — being co-author of the conditions under which one lives. Egalitarian liberal feminists hold that the exercise of personal autonomy depends on certain enabling conditions that are insufficiently present in women's lives, or that social arrangements often fail to respect women's personal autonomy and other elements of women's flourishing. They hold also that women's needs and interests are insufficiently reflected in the basic conditions under which they live, and that those conditions lack legitimacy because women are inadequately represented in the processes of democratic self-determination. Egalitarian liberal feminists hold that autonomy deficits like these are due to the “gender system” (Okin 1989, 89), or the patriarchal nature of inherited traditions and institutions, and that the women's movement should work to identify and remedy them. As the protection and promotion of citizens' autonomy is the appropriate role of the state on the egalitarian liberal view, egalitarian liberal feminists hold that the state can and should be the women's movement's ally in protecting and promoting women's autonomy. There is disagreement among egalitarian liberal feminists, however, about the role of personal autonomy in the good life, the appropriate role of the state, and how egalitarian liberal feminism is to be justified. Readers interested in egalitarian liberal feminism may want to skip ahead to that section now.
- 1. Classical Liberal or Libertarian Feminism
- 2. Egalitarian Liberal Feminism
- Bibliography
- Other Internet Resources
- Related Entries
1. Classical Liberal or Libertarian Feminism
1.1 Self-Ownership and Women's Rights
Classical liberalism or libertarianism (these terms will be used interchangeably here[1]) holds that women and men are self-owners capable of acquiring property rights over things. As such women and men, equally, have the right to freedom from coercive interference with their person and property. This right to freedom from coercive interference consists in, at least, rights to freedom of conscience and expression, freedom to control what happens to one's body, freedom of association, freedom to acquire, control and transfer property, freedom of contract, as well as the right to compensation when rights are violated. The state's role is, exclusively, to protect citizens from coercive interference by protecting their rights. Some reject even a limited state, however, holding that nongovernmental means of protecting rights are to be preferred.
Classical liberal or libertarian feminists hold that the right to freedom from coercive interference has powerful implications for women's lives. It implies that women have the right to freedom in intimate, sexual and reproductive matters. This includes sexual autonomy (the right to engage in sexual activity of one's choosing including the buying and selling of sex (Almodovar 2002; Lehrman 1997, 23), and the right to defend oneself against sexual aggression, including the use of firearms (Stevens et al. 2002)); freedom of expression (the right to appear in, publish, and consume pornography free of censorship (McElroy 1995; Strossen 2000)); freedom of intimate association (the right to partner or enter into a private marriage contract (McElroy 1991a, 20)); and reproductive freedom (the right to use birth control, have an abortion (on the minority of pro-life libertarians see Tabarrok 2002, 157), and buy and sell bodily reproductive services as in surrogate motherhood (Lehrman 1997, 22; McElroy 2002c; Paul 2002)). Freedom from interference with person and property also means that women have the right to engage in economic activity in a free market, entering contracts, and acquiring, controlling and transferring property free of sexist state limits (Epstein 1992; Kirp, Yudolf, and Franks 1986, 204).
One way to characterize the wrong involved when states fail to recognize these rights of women is as a failure to respect women's right to be treated as men's equal, or the right to equal treatment under the law. To be sure, classical liberal feminists hold that the law should not treat women and men differently. But this is because they believe everyone has the same rights, not because they believe women have a right to be treated the same as men. This is clear when we note that, for classical liberal or libertarian feminism, equal treatment under unjust law is not justice (McElroy 1991a, 3).
Same treatment under the law does not guarantee same outcomes. Classical liberal or libertarian feminists hold that women's rights are not violated when citizens exercise their rights in ways that create unequal outcomes (Epstein 2002, 30). A woman's rights are violated only when she is interfered with coercively, that is, when there is, or is a threat of, forced loss of freedom, property or life (which does not serve as just restraint or compensation).
1.2 Equity Feminism
Equity feminism is a form of classical liberal or libertarian feminism that holds that feminism's political role is simply to ensure that everyone's, including women's, right against coercive interference is respected (Sommers 1994, 22). Wendy McElroy, an equity feminist writes: “I've always maintained that the only reason I call myself a feminist is because of [the] gov[ernment]. By which I mean, if the government (or an anarchist defense assoc[iation]) acknowledged the full equal rights of women without paternalistic protection or oppression, I would stop writing about women's issues” (McElroy 1998c).
Feminism's political role involves assuring that women's right against coercive interference by private individuals is recognized and protected by the state (for example women's right against groping on the street or rape within marriage (McElroy 1991a)), and that women's right against coercive interference by the state itself is respected. The latter means feminists should object to laws that restrict women's liberty in particular (for example laws that limit women's employment options (Taylor 1992, 228)), and laws that protect women in particular (for example laws that grant preferential treatment to women (Paul 1989)). Equity feminists suggest that this has been largely accomplished in countries like the United States. Joan Kennedy Taylor explains: feminism's “goal of equal political liberty for women has been pretty much reached in the United States” (Taylor 2001; see also Sommers 1994, 274).
1.2.1 Equity Feminism on the Oppression of Women
On the equity feminist view, the feminist slogan “the personal is political” is accurate when the state fails to recognize women's right against coercive interference, especially in women's personal lives. So, for example, in some countries husbands have legal control over their wives' persons and property. (Some equity feminists argue that the women's movement in Western countries should not hesitate to criticize countries in which this occurs (Sommers 2007).) But in countries like the United States, where the right of women against this sort of coercive interference is recognized and protected by law, equity feminists hold that “the personal is no longer political” (Lehrman 1997, 5; see also 21).
If an individual or group of individuals suffers sustained and systematic denial of their rights, on the equity feminist view, we may call them oppressed. Women were oppressed in the United States during most of its first two centuries; people of African descent were oppressed before the dismantling of Jim Crow laws. While the culture of the United States supported this denial of rights, equity feminists hold that the oppressor was the state (McElroy 1998c), which refused to recognize and protect the right of women and people of African descent to treatment as self-owners. When the state recognizes and protects this right of women and Americans of African descent, they are no longer oppressed, even if the culture disadvantages them. So, for example, in a discussion of whether Muslim women are oppressed, Cathy Young focuses on whether women's conformity with a religious tradition that subordinates them is enforced by law. If it is, then women are oppressed (Young 2006).
If women are to be described as currently oppressed in societies like the United States, on the equity feminist view, one must show that the state fails to protect women, as a group, from sustained and systematic rights violations. Some feminists have argued that violence against women is pervasive in societies like the United States so that, even though the law recognizes women's right against it, that right is insufficiently protected, and thus women endure sustained and systematic denial of their right to bodily integrity (Dworkin 1991). Equity feminists endeavor to refute this claim by showing that the prevalence of violence against women has been exaggerated. For example Rita Simon contests the claim that as many as 154 out of 1,000 women have been raped. On her accounting, the number is closer to 19 per 1,000; and “rape is less common than other violent crimes” (Simon 2002, 235). In addition, she claims, “the criminal justice system does not ignore or make light of crimes against females” (Simon 2002, 236). Katie Roiphe argues that date rape is not a significant threat to women (Roiphe 1994). Concurring with Roiphe, Cathy Young writes: “women have sex after initial reluctance for a number of reasons … fear of being beaten up by their dates is rarely reported as one of them” (Young 1992).
Women have also been said to be oppressed because their right to be treated the same as men by employers, educational institutions, and associations has been violated in a sustained and systematic way. That is, some argue, women have been regularly denied the right to equal access to opportunities because they are women. Equity feminists generally hold that no rights are violated when employers, educational institutions, public accommodations or associations discriminate against women (see section 1.5). Nonetheless, equity feminists argue that discrimination against women is not a serious problem. Diana Furchtgott-Roth and Christine Stolba argue that “complaints about systematic economic discrimination against women simply do not square with the evidence” (Stolba and Furchtgott-Roth 1999, xi; see also 2001). They argue that “women's wages and education levels are closing the gap with those of men” (xii). In addition, Stolba and Furchtgott-Roth claim that women have “surpassed men in education” (23; see also 23-43). Christina Hoff Sommers concurs, arguing that, rather than failing to provide girls with an education equal to that of boys, our current educational system disproportionately benefits girls (Sommers 2000, 20-23, 178).
Equity feminists argue that the differences in outcomes between women and men can be explained, not by violence against women and sex discrimination, but by differences in the preferences of women and men (Epstein 2002, 33; Stolba and Furchtgott-Roth 1999, xii). “In many cases where women remain behind men, personal choices explain outcomes more readily than does overt discrimination” (Stolba and Furchtgott-Roth 1999, xii). To be sure, classical liberal or libertarian feminists hold that women and men are sufficiently the same that they have the “same political interests,” in particular the interest in being treated as a self-owner (McElroy 2002a, 14-15). But, for some equity feminists, biological differences between the sexes largely explain the sex segregation in the workplace and in family roles still common in countries like the United States (Epstein 2002; Lehrman 1997, 5, 31).
Other equity feminists think biological sex differences alone do not explain this phenomenon (Young 2004). Women's preferences may reflect the effects of socialization or incentives: for example women may be socialized to prefer stereotypically female roles, or the rewards associated with such roles for women may provide motivation for women to take them up. But equity feminists hold that, because women are not legally required, or actually forced in some other way, to choose traditional roles, their choices are not coerced, and thus state remedies are inappropriate. On the equity feminist view, a law prohibiting women to become surgeons is coercive because it constitutes a threat of loss of liberty or property. But if one is socialized to prefer stay-at-home motherhood, or one discovers that one prefers to stay home with children given the other real options, one may still choose to become a surgeon without risking loss of liberty or property. As Stolba and Furchtgott-Roth put it (using the word “prevents” in a very strong sense): “Nothing prevents women from choosing the surgical specialty” (Stolba and Furchtgott-Roth 1999, 60; my emphasis).
1.2.2 Feminism's Nonpolitical Role
While equity feminists hold that feminism's political task — securing for women the right to freedom from coercive interference — is nearly completed, some equity feminists believe that feminism has a nonpolitical role to play in women's personal lives. In its nonpolitical role, feminism can help women to develop character traits and strategies that will help them benefit from their freedom; and it can help women to navigate personally among their increasing options.
Karen Lehrman writes: “Men have typically held title to quite a few traits that women can now put to good use. In addition to ambition, assertiveness, and independence, there's also decisiveness” (Lehrman 1997, 33; see also 62). Other character traits emphasized by equity feminists include “self-confidence” (Stevens et al. 2002, 255), being able to think and argue independently (McElroy 1998a — see Other Internet Resources), and taking responsibility for oneself (Taylor 1992, 86). Some equity feminists suggest that feminism offers individual women and men the opportunity for freedom from conformity with sex roles (Lehrman 1997, 6; Taylor 1992, 23-24).
Equity feminists recommend strategies for success for women in education and employment as alternatives to state regulation. In male dominated fields, for example, equity feminists recommend that women mentor one another, or organize supportive associations, making use of the techniques of 1960's feminism like consciousness-raising (Taylor 1992, 100-101). In What You Can Do About Sexual Harassment When You Don't Want to Call the Cops, Joan Kennedy Taylor argues that women can avoid sexual harassment or lessen its impact if they learn to diffuse conflicts with men and understand the role of sexual banter in male culture (Taylor 1999). Equity feminists also recommend that women make full use of their right to contract by turning their preferences — for example the preference for being paid and/or promoted on the basis of one's job performance and not on the basis of sexual favors — into rights through contract (Epstein 2002, 40; Taylor 1992, 169).
Some equity feminists stress that women need not give up their gender difference to benefit from their freedom (Lehrman 1997, 198). As Karen Lehrman writes, “completing the feminist revolution … primarily involves [women] completing their own personal evolutions” (35). Lehrman quotes Elizabeth Cady Stanton: “the strongest reason for giving woman a complete emancipation from all forms of bondage of custom, dependence, superstition … is the solitude and personal responsibility of her own individual life” (Lehrman 1997, 201). An important part of this individual life, on Lehrman's view, is navigating among sexual difference and sameness in the personal construction of a satisfying life.
1.2.3 Socially Conservative Equity Feminism
Some equity feminists are socially conservative (Morse 2001; Sommers 2000a). To be sure, equity feminism as described here is a form of classical liberal or libertarian feminism. As such it involves the claim that traditional values should not be imposed on citizens by the state. For example, the state should not tax citizens to support institutions that promote traditional values, nor should the criminal or civil law create incentives for adherence to such values. But some equity feminists hold that it is best when citizens voluntarily adhere to traditional values. They hold that widespread voluntary adherence to traditional values is conducive to well-being in society because traditional values make possible the reproduction of independent and “self-restraining citizens” which are “the basis of free institutions, both economic and political” (Morse 2001, 161).
Socially conservative equity feminists do not take the classical liberal or libertarian theory of the limits of state power to imply endorsement of a libertine cultural ethos. So, for example, while socially conservative equity feminists hold that the state should not force citizens to accept traditional family forms (because individuals have a right against such coercive interference), they hold that society should strongly discourage disfavored ways of life and encourage favored ones through noncoercive, nonstate means. Socially conservative equity feminists hold that when feminism strays from its political role of assuring equal rights and ventures into women's personal lives it tends to discourage in women the kinds of delayed gratification and self-sacrifice on which vital social institutions, like the family, depend (Morse 2001, 133).
To be sure, there are political conservatives who take equity feminism's claim that women and men should be treated the same by the law as a rule of thumb. Elizabeth Fox-Genovese is an example of such a political conservative (Fox-Genovese 1991; 1996). The difference between political conservatives who embrace the equity feminist account of women's equality and socially conservative equity feminists is that the former endorse the use of state power to promote traditional values while the latter do not. Also, socially conservative equity feminists hold that individuals' political rights derive from their status as self-owners (Morse 2001, 57) while political conservatives hold that citizens' political rights derive from their status as members of communities (Fox-Genovese 1991, 9). In contemporary popular political discourse it is often hard to distinguish these two, as they are in political coalition. To appeal to both libertarian and socially conservative constituencies, on occasion theorists help themselves to a bit of both traditions. For example, Jennifer Roback Morse identifies herself as a libertarian: “When the topic is the proper relationship between the individual and the state, libertarianism is pretty much the right path” (Morse 2001, 4). She tells us that “the moral and ethical system underlying the polity must be secured outside the political process itself” (124). But she also makes the unlibertarian and politically conservative recommendation that the state should intervene in personal relationships by making it “costly to divorce” (164, see also 104, 111).
1.3 Cultural Libertarian Feminism
Cultural libertarianism is a form of classical liberalism or libertarianism that is “concerned about constraints on individual freedom from government as well as from traditionalist familial, religious, and community institutions-the same civil institutions that conservatives see as necessary for ordered liberty to thrive” (Young 2007). Cultural libertarian feminism holds that these institutions reflect the patriarchal nature of society and are oppressive of women. Thus cultural libertarian feminism recognizes sources of women's oppression other than the state (Presley 2000; Johnson and Long 2005). As Frederick Johnson and Roderick Long put it, patriarchal culture and the state are “interlocking systems of oppression” (Johnson and Long 2005), both of which should be opposed by feminists. They explain: “There is nothing inconsistent or un-libertarian in holding that women's choices under patriarchal social structures can be sufficiently ‘voluntary,’ in the libertarian sense, to be entitled to immunity from coercive legislative interference, while at the same time being sufficiently ‘involuntary,’ in a broader sense, to be recognized as morally problematic and as a legitimate target of social activism” (Johnson and Long 2005).
Calling this view “anarchist feminism,” Sharon Presley writes: “What the anarchist feminists are calling for is a radical restructuring of society, both in its public and private institutions” (Presley 2000). Such feminists hold that much of the oppression women currently suffer is noncoercive, however. Laws against prostitution are coercive — the state can put a violator in jail or force her to pay a fine. But on the cultural libertarian feminist view, much of the pressure to conform to gender roles is not coercive. Noncoercive oppression can be resisted, although it is often not easy to do so. Cultural libertarian feminists hold that noncoercive oppression should not be remedied by the state. As Presley and Kinsky explain, on the cultural libertarian view, to try to remedy the noncoercive oppression of women with coercive state action “just changes the sort of oppression, not the fact” (Presley and Kinsky 1991, 78). This oppression should be opposed by a nonviolent movement for feminist social change.
Cultural libertarian feminists target the patriarchal culture by, for example, developing in individuals (especially women) the ability to be independent. This involves enabling individuals to resist authority and think for themselves (Presley 2001). Cultural libertarian feminists also recommend the development of more deeply consensual relationships and institutions (Heckert 2004 — see Other Internet Resources), relationships and institutions in which there is an equality of authority (Long 2001 — see Other Internet Resources). While some equity feminists (see section 1.2) would applaud this work, they would call it “personal,” reserving the term “political” for the work of securing for women their right against coercive interference. Equity feminist Wendy McElroy writes: “I understand that there is a cultural form of feminism and many women would still fight for improved prestige or status, and I wouldn't criticis[e] them for doing so. It just wouldn't grip me. Guess I'm a political animal after all” (McElroy 1998c). But cultural libertarian feminists consider this work to be an integral part of a larger political struggle for women's freedom.
1.4 Historical Sources
Classical liberal or libertarian feminists understand themselves as heirs to the first generation of feminist political philosophers, for example Mary Wollstonecraft, Harriet Taylor Mill, and John Stuart Mill (Taylor 1992, 25-39); the first generation of feminist political reformers in the United States, for example the abolitionist feminists Elizabeth Cady Stanton and Sarah Grimke (McElroy 2002a, 6-7); and the tradition of 19th century anarchist feminism, including figures such as Voltairine de Cleyre (McElroy 2002a, 8; Presley 2000; Presley and Sartwell 2005). Equity feminists stress the extent to which these early thinkers and activists identify women's liberation with equal respect for women's right against coercive interference (Stolba and Furchtgott-Roth 2001, 1-2). Cultural libertarian feminists emphasize the extent to which these thinkers and activists challenged both coercive state power and the patriarchal culture (Presley 2000; Johnson and Long 2005 — see Other Internet Resources).
Classical liberal or libertarian feminists hold that “the very arguments that rightly led to the legal reforms affecting the status of women during the 19th century militate against the demands for reform from the late 20th century women's movement” (Epstein 2002, 30). That is, they hold that the defense of equal rights and independence for women promulgated by these early feminists is incompatible with the tendency of the contemporary women's movement to call on the state to improve the lives of women.
1.5 Anti-Discrimination Law and Preferential Treatment
Classical liberal or libertarian feminism requires same treatment of women and men under the law. This means that sex discrimination by the state, for example when the state functions as an employer, is impermissible (Block 1991, 102; Epstein 2002, 34; Warnick 2003, 1608). But classical liberal or libertarian feminists oppose laws that prohibit discrimination against women by nonstate actors, for example in employment, education, public accommodations, or associations (McElroy 1991a, 22-23; Epstein 1992). They hold that the interaction of citizens should be subject to state control only to the extent necessary to protect citizens' right against coercive interference. Businesses violate citizens' right against coercive interference when they steal from their customers or employees; associations violate it when they extort their members; colleges violate it when they kidnap students. But businesses do not violate this right when they refuse to do business with women, pay women less for the same work, or create a working environment that is hostile to them because of their sex. Private educational institutions do not violate this right when they refuse to educate girls or women, offer them an inferior education, or create a learning environment that is hostile to them because of their sex. Business and professional associations do not violate this right when they refuse to admit women as members or make them feel unwelcome.
Classical liberal or libertarian feminism, as described here, clearly implies rejection of legal prohibition of private discrimination in employment, education, public accommodations, and associations. But in the literature one finds a range of views. Some categorically reject any legal protection against private discrimination (Taylor 1992, 62). Others accept basic protections such as those afforded in U.S. law by the Equal Pay Act of 1963, Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, and title IX of the Educational Amendments of 1972; but reject more robust protections, such as non-remedial affirmative action or comparable worth (Stolba and Furchtgott-Roth 2001, 179; see also 107-108).
Classical liberal or libertarian feminism holds that private businesses, educational institutions, and associations are free to give or withhold preferential treatment to women. But the state may not treat women preferentially because the state must treat citizens the same regardless of sex. Nor may the state require that private businesses, educational institutions, or associations treat women preferentially. This is because, on the equity feminist view, failure to treat women preferentially is not a violation of anyone's right against coercive interference. Examples of preferential treatment under the law, which classical liberal or libertarian feminists oppose, include affirmative action in employment and education (Lehrman 1997, 25), comparable worth (Paul 1989), and advantages for women in the legal treatment of custody and domestic violence (Simon 2002).
While equity feminists resist state remedies for private discrimination against women, they also hold that such discrimination is not currently a serious problem in countries like the United States (see section 1.2.1). In addition, they argue, “even where discrimination may exist, we find little, if any, evidence that expanded government intervention would serve any useful purpose” (Stolba and Furchtgott-Roth 1999, xii), and speculate that freer markets would make whatever discrimination currently takes place even more rare (McElroy 2002b, 187).
1.6 Justification
Why should individuals be treated as self-owners? Much of the classical liberal or libertarian feminist literature, especially the equity feminist literature, is written for public policy and popular audiences. Thus more attention is paid to implications and policy applications than to philosophical justifications. A variety of justifications are mentioned in the literature. Kirp, Yudoff, and Franks, for example, refer to Kant's categorical imperative and claim that treating individuals as self-owners is what is meant by treating individuals as ends in themselves ((Kirp et al. 1986, 13-14). Wendy McElroy grounds her thought in the natural law tradition (McElroy 1998b). Some imply a perfectionist justification according to which the perfection of the human being requires being treated as a self-owner (Presley 2001).
By far the most common argument in the classical liberal or libertarian feminist literature is consequentialist. The argument says that the political arrangements recommended by classical liberalism or libertarianism, as compared with the alternatives, will provide women with more of what is good for them: for example safety, income and wealth, choices, and options. Liberalizing guns laws will make women safer (Stevens, et al. 2002); legalizing prostitution and porn will improve the lives of women in those trades (Almodovar 2002; Strossen 2000) and open opportunities for others; freer markets will root out discrimination against women and stimulate the proliferation of amenities essential to working women, like daycare centers (Epstein 2002, 33; Paul 2002, 208-209; Stolba and Furchtgott-Roth 2001, 124, 180; Conway 1998). Indeed, some argue that liberalizing the market will release such an “explosion of prosperity” that women will not need help from a welfare state (Long 1997 — see Other Internet Resources).
1.7 Criticism
1.7.1 General Criticism
Classical liberalism or libertarianism holds that women and men are self-owners capable of acquiring property rights over things. In her discussion of Robert Nozick's libertarianism, Susan Okin argues that if libertarianism includes the claim that individuals have a right to control their own bodies and own the fruits of their own labor, then women — who presumably make children from resources that have been given to them freely or were bought by them — own their children (Nozick 1974; Okin 1989, 80, 81; see also Jeske 1996). But if women own their children, and everyone begins as a child, then no one owns herself (Okin 1989, 85). If classical liberal or libertarian feminists hold something like Nozick's theory of property, namely that one owns what one has made with resources justly acquired, then it would seem that classical liberal or libertarian feminism includes the claim that women own their children and therefore no one owns herself. This criticism suggests that when classical liberal or libertarian theory takes women's experience seriously (for example the experience of reproduction) it refutes itself.
Okin and others raise a second, related, concern. Classical liberalism or libertarianism holds that the only interest that places a (coercible) duty on others is the interest in being free of coercive interference. But surely, some contend, all individuals have a high priority interest in receiving care, especially as children and when disabled or infirm (Kittay 1999; Nussbaum 2000). As Susan Okin argues, a theory that ignores this interest must assume that there is a “realm of private life in which the reproductive and nurturant needs of human beings are taken care of” (Okin 1989, 75). This assumption hides the fact that it is women who typically satisfy this interest, and do so often without pay and at great sacrifice to themselves. This renders classical liberalism or libertarianism, including its feminist versions, blind to the nature of our obligations to children and others who cannot care for themselves. In addition, because women's caring labor is hidden from view, it becomes impossible to evaluate the justice of the arrangements under which the interest in receiving care is commonly satisfied.
These first two criticisms suggest that classical liberal or libertarian feminism does not pay sufficient attention to human reproduction. Jennifer Roback Morse, herself a classical liberal or libertarian feminist, concedes: “I think it is well to admit … that our inattention to family life and community responsibility has left libertarians open to the charge that we do not care very much about these matters” (Morse 2001, 28). Responses to this concern include Morse's own attempt to develop a libertarian political theory capable of taking “account of infant helplessness” (Morse 2001, 28).
Some critics take aim at the consequentialist argument offered in support of classical liberal or libertarian feminism (see section 1.6). The consequentialist argument says that the political arrangements recommended by classical liberalism or libertarianism, as compared with the alternatives, will provide women with more of what is good for them. Ashlie Warnick argues that the case can be made that some particular liberty-restricting policies harm women, and that some particular liberty-enhancing policies are good for women. But, she argues, the larger case — that all liberty-restricting policies harm women, or that a minimal state (or no state) would be better for women overall — has not been made convincingly (Warnick 2003). What's more, it's not clear that that larger case can be made because much of the support offered is speculative, for example Roderick Long's assertion that “the explosion of prosperity that a libertarian society would see, would go a long way toward providing women with an economic safety net more effective than any government welfare program” (Long 1997 — see Other Internet Resources).
1.7.2 Criticism of Equity Feminism
Equity feminism holds that feminism's political role is to ensure that everyone's, including women's, right against coercive interference is respected. It denies that women are oppressed in societies like the United States; that is, it denies that the state fails to protect women, as a group, from sustained and systematic violation of their right against coercive interference. For example, equity feminists deny that law enforcement fails adequately to protect women from rape and other coercive sexual practices (see section 1.2.1). Other feminists contest this. For example Deborah Rhode argues that rape and coercive sexual practices remain common, and thus that the state fails to adequately protect women (Rhode 1997, 120; see also Cudd 2006, 93ff). If Rhode is right, equity feminists would have to concede that women are, to some degree, oppressed.
Equity feminists claim that while state action to counter violence against women is justified, state action to counter sex discrimination by private employers is neither just nor necessary. It is not just because sex discrimination by private employers does not count as a violation of a woman's right against coercive interference (see section 1.5). It is not necessary, equity feminists claim, because such discrimination is rare (see section 1.2.1). Some contest the claim that sex discrimination by private employers is rare. These critics hold that current laws against sex discrimination fail to adequately protect women (Rhode 1997, 156; Cudd 2006, 140-142), and that other common and largely unregulated forms of discrimination — such as discrimination against parents — disparately impact women (Williams 2000; Cudd 2006, 147-152). To be sure, because equity feminists hold that state action may not be used to protect women from such discrimination, that it may be pervasive is not decisive.
Other critics take aim at the account of coercion that informs equity feminism. Equity feminists oppose laws that restrict women's choices. These they describe as coercive. But they do not oppose restrictive social conventions if they do not involve violence against women or are not enshrined in law. These, they hold, are not coercive. But surely, just as one can resist conforming with a social convention, one can choose to provoke threatened violence and one can violate a law. As Ann Cudd explains, what informs the claim that restrictive laws are coercive but restrictive social conventions are not is a moral account of what costs individuals should not have to pay, that is, what individuals are entitled to (Cudd 2006, 129). Equity feminism, as a form of classical liberal or libertarian philosophy, holds that individuals are entitled to being treated as self-owners. If this moral account of what individuals are entitled to is replaced with a different account, for example the account that says that individuals are entitled to well-being or fairness, then we get a different account of coercion. Then restrictive social norms can count as coercive (Cudd 2006, 151).
In addition, some critics of equity feminism argue that once it is recognized that patriarchal culture is oppressive, or at least that it situates women and men differently, one must reject equity feminism's categorical insistence on same treatment under the law. While different treatment can surely stigmatize and entrench stereotypes, same treatment can disadvantage women if they are not similarly situated to men (Minow 1990).
1.7.3 Criticism of Socially Conservative Equity Feminism
Socially conservative equity feminists argue that women and men should voluntarily adhere to traditional values because those values are essential to the production of citizens capable of independence and self-restraint (see section 1.2.3). But such values have been roundly criticized by feminists. For example, some argue, the traditional nuclear family celebrated by social conservatives (Morse 2001) places on women a disproportionate and disadvantaging share of the burdens of social reproduction (Okin 1989). Socially conservative equity feminists are untroubled by this disadvantage as long as it is voluntarily chosen. Some argue that the fact that a political philosophy grounded in the value of voluntary choice is compatible with traditions and institutions that disadvantage women shows that feminism should not be so grounded (Jaggar 1983, 194; Yuracko 2003, 25-26). Others embrace the value of voluntary choice for feminism, but argue that women often cannot exercise it, because sexist socialization and a homogeneous culture render them incapable of critically assessing their preferences and imagining life otherwise (Meyers 2004; Cornell 1998; Cudd 2004). Indeed, if critical thinking is necessary for freedom but corrosive of tradition, cultural conservatives must be wary of freedom. Thus, the critics claim, there is a tension within socially conservative equity feminism between equity feminism's emphasis on voluntariness and social conservatism's emphasis on tradition. (For related criticism, see Loudermilk 2004, 149-172).
1.7.4 Criticism of Cultural Libertarian Feminism
Cultural libertarian feminism holds that the traditional culture of societies like the United States is patriarchal and a morally objectionable source of oppression of women. Cultural libertarian feminism aims to dismantle this culture, and its traditional morality, through a nonviolent movement for feminist social change. It seeks to replace this culture with relationships and institutions that are more deeply voluntary, in which there is an equality of authority (see section 1.3). But some argue that classical liberalism or libertarianism must call for voluntary adherence to traditional morality because that morality is necessary for the reproduction of citizens capable of independence and self-restraint. Edward Feser writes: “[T]he same fundamental moral vision and the same sorts of arguments ultimately underlie respect for both the free society and traditional morality; and hostility toward both also has the same psychological and philosophical roots” (Feser 2001 — see Other Internet Resources). This criticism of cultural libertarian feminism stems from a larger discussion among classical liberals or libertarians concerning whether it is best allied with the cultural left or the cultural right (see also Johnson and Long 2005 — see Other Internet Resources).
2. Egalitarian Liberal Feminism
Egalitarian liberal feminism conceives of freedom as personal autonomy — living a life of one's own choosing — and political autonomy — being co-author of the conditions under which one lives. Egalitarian liberal feminists hold that the exercise of personal autonomy depends on certain enabling conditions that are insufficiently present in women's lives, or that social arrangements often fail to respect women's personal autonomy and other elements of women's flourishing. They hold also that women's needs and interests are insufficiently reflected in the basic conditions under which they live, and that those conditions lack legitimacy because women are inadequately represented in the processes of democratic self-determination. Egalitarian liberal feminists hold that autonomy deficits like these are due to the “gender system” (Okin 1989, 89), or the patriarchal nature of inherited traditions and institutions, and that the women's movement should work to identify and remedy them. As the protection and promotion of citizens' autonomy is the appropriate role of the state on the egalitarian liberal view, egalitarian liberal feminists hold that the state can and should be the women's movement's ally in promoting women's autonomy. There is disagreement among egalitarian liberal feminists, however, about the role of personal autonomy in the good life, the appropriate role of the state, and how egalitarian liberal feminism is to be justified.
2.1 Personal Autonomy
2.1.1 Procedural Accounts of Personal Autonomy
Egalitarian liberal feminists hold that women should enjoy personal autonomy. That is, they hold that women should live lives of their own choosing. Some offer “procedural” accounts of personal autonomy (MacKenzie and Stoljar discuss these, 1999, 13-19). These accounts suggest that to say that women should enjoy personal autonomy means that they are entitled to a broad range of autonomy-enabling conditions. On this view, the women's movement should work to identify and promote these conditions. Identifying these enabling conditions requires careful attention to the particular ways in which autonomy deficits are produced in diverse women's lives. Procedural accounts avoid judging directly the substance of women's choices or the arrangements that ensue. The following list of enabling conditions is representative.
Being free of violence and the threat of violence: Violence and the threat of violence violate women's dignity; they make women do what others want or reduce women's sphere of activity to avoiding harm. In some cases violence fractures the self and takes from women their sense of self-respect (Brison 1997). The feminist literature on violence against women documents the particular role that violence and the threat of violence play in unfairly disempowering and limiting women (Cudd 2006, 85-118).
Being free of the limits set by paternalistic and moralistic laws: Paternalistic laws restrict women's options on the grounds that such limits are in women's interest. Think for example of laws that limit women's employment options on the grounds that taking certain jobs is not in women's interest (Smith 2004). Moralistic laws restrict women's options on the grounds that certain choices should not be available to women because they are immoral. Think for example of laws that prohibit or restrict prostitution or abortion, or laws that favor certain kinds of sexual expression or family forms (Cornell 1998; Brake 2004). Together, paternalistic and moralistic laws steer women into socially preferred ways of life. These are unfair restrictions on women's choices, on the egalitarian liberal feminist view, because women's choices should be guided by their own sense of their self-interest and by their own values.
Having access to options: On the egalitarian liberal feminist view, women are entitled to access to options (Alstott 2004, 52; Brison 2006, 193). Women's access to options is frequently and unfairly restricted due to economic deprivation, in particular due to the “feminization of poverty” (Pearce 1978; see also Cudd 2006, 119-154). Other sources of unfairly reduced options for women are stereotyping and sex discrimination in education and employment (Smith 2004; Rhode 1997). Such stereotyping and discrimination effect racial, ethnic and cultural minorities in particularly pernicious ways. Egalitarian liberal feminists also point to the way cultural homogeneity unfairly limits women options (Cudd 2006, 234), for example when culture assigns identities and social roles according to sex (Okin 1989, 170ff; Alstott 2004; Meyers 2004; Cornell 1998, x).
Some emphasize the importance of internal, psychological enabling conditions as well, for example the ability to assess one's own preferences and imagine life otherwise (Meyers 2002, 168; Cudd 2006, 234-235; MacKenzie 1999). Without the ability to assess the preferences on the basis of which one makes choices, and the ability to imagine life otherwise, one can't meaningfully be said to have options other than affirming the status quo. These internal enabling conditions are related to the external ones. Violence and the threat of violence, stereotyping and discrimination, material deprivation, and cultural homogeneity all can have the effect of closing down reflection and imagination.
On this view, the women's movement should work to identify and promote autonomy-enabling conditions. Identifying these conditions requires careful attention to the particular ways in which autonomy deficits are produced in women's lives. On the egalitarian liberal feminist view, the state has an important role to play in promoting these conditions (see sections 2.1.4, 2.2.1, and 2.2.2). But there is much that cannot be done by the state (Cudd 2006, 223). For example, while the state can refrain from blocking such endeavors, women themselves must develop new “alternative emancipatory imagery” (Meyers 2002, 168), and fashion new ways of being a woman and new kinds of relationships through experiments in living (Cudd 2006, 234; Cornell 1998).
Some critics argue that freedom is of limited value because, even when enabling conditions like these are in place, women may continue to choose limiting and disadvantaging social arrangements. Some point to the phenomenon of deformed preferences: when attractive options are limited or arrangements unfair, people may develop preferences for those limits or for less than their fair share (Nussbaum 1999, 33, 50; Cudd 2006, 152). This phenomenon makes changing preferences through increased freedom problematic, and leads some feminists to reject theories that prioritize free choice (Yuracko 2003). Advocates of procedural accounts of autonomy concede that the enabling conditions do not rule out that a woman could choose, for example, to undergo clitorectomy (Meyers 2004, 213) or become a pornographic model (Cudd 2004, 58). As Ann Cudd explains, possibilities like these must be accepted because liberal feminism values freedom and thus cannot advocate direct “preference education” (Cudd 2004, 57). Liberal feminism must offer only a “… gradualist approach. Individuals and groups will make various experiments in living that we cannot now precisely imagine. They … will sometimes go on a mistaken path” (57). But they must be freed up to find their own way. As Diana Meyers explains, the moral imagination of feminist theorists and activists is limited (as is everyone's); they cannot know with certainty what substantive choices are compatible with personal autonomy (Meyers 2004, 213). Moreover, one should expect autonomous lives to take diverse forms in diverse cultural contexts. On this view, “a morally defensible and politically viable conception of autonomy for an era of global feminism” must be agnostic about the content of women's choices as long as they do not close off autonomy (205).
2.1.2 Fairness in Personal Relationships
Some egalitarian liberal feminists hold that the value of personal autonomy does put a substantive constraint on choices and social arrangements. They hold that the social arrangements of personal life should not only be freely chosen, but should be characterized by fairness or justice. Jean Hampton draws on the contractualist tradition in moral and political philosophy to describe one way in which heterosexual intimate relationships often fail to be fair or just (Hampton 1993). (For more on feminist uses of contractualism, see section 2.2.1.).
On Hampton's view, a personal relationship is fair only if both parties to it could “reasonably accept the distribution of costs and benefits (that is, the costs and benefits that are not themselves side effects of any affective or duty-based tie between us) if it were the subject of an informed, unforced agreement in which we think of ourselves as motivated solely by self-interest” (Hampton 1993, 240). Of course, many women choose to enter or remain in relationships in part because of affective benefits; for example women often get satisfaction from satisfying others or fulfilling a duty. Why set aside these affective benefits, as Hampton recommends, when evaluating the fairness of a relationship? Hampton does not set them aside out of a conviction that a woman's affective nature is not part of her essential self. Nor does she set them aside out of a conviction that this aspect of a woman's nature is not valuable. (For criticism of Hampton, see Sample 2002). Her test sets them aside because affective benefits of relationships are not received from the other; they are benefits that flow from one's own nature (Radzik 2005, 51). Thus while they may, and probably should, figure in a woman's overall decision about whether to enter or remain in a particular relationship, Hampton believes they should not figure in the evaluation of a relationship's fairness. As Linda Radzik explains in her defense of Hampton, a relationship is fair or just if the benefits that flow from each to the other are on par, that is, if each gives as much as she gets (51). When one party gets from the other significantly more than he gives, he is denying the other her legitimate entitlement to reciprocation.
This test formalizes an important insight of the women's movement: personal relationships, in particular traditional heterosexual relationships, are often unfair to women, indeed often exploit women's tendency to care about others. Injustice of this sort is not uncommon. Thus Hampton's test invites criticism of a wide swath of human social life (Sample 2002, 271). But Hampton does not call on women to cease valuing others' satisfaction or the fulfillment of duty (Hampton 1993, 227). Instead, she calls on the women's movement to cultivate in women and men a sensitivity and an aversion to this kind of injustice, and to develop remedies.
Procedural accounts of personal autonomy (see section 2.1.1) do not require that relationships be just in the way Hampton recommends. According to procedural accounts, it is possible that a choice to enter or remain in a personal relationship in which one gives more than she gets from the other can be autonomous. Therefore, according to procedural accounts, liberal feminists should focus on ensuring that women are not pressured into or unable to exit them.
To be sure, Hampton's account of justice in personal relationships can be a resource to women and men reflecting on their own preferences. It invites reflection on how one's own preferences affect the distribution of benefits and burdens within a relationship. Also, moral criticism of relationships that exploit women's preferences reminds us that relationships can be otherwise (because ought implies can). This reminder enhances personal autonomy by broadening the imagination. Thus procedural accounts of personal autonomy can include Hampton's test, not as definitive of the acceptability of social arrangements, but as a contribution to the kind of reflection about the good life on which the personal autonomy of individuals depends.
2.1.3 Personal Autonomy and Human Flourishing
Martha Nussbaum proposes an account of the good life that has “at its heart, a profoundly liberal idea … the idea of the citizen as a free and dignified human being, a maker of choices” (Nussbaum 1999, 46). Echoing procedural accounts of personal autonomy (section 2.1.1), Nussbaum explains: “If one cares about people's powers to choose a conception of the good, then one must care about the rest of the form of life that supports those powers” (45). But for Nussbaum personal autonomy is merely one of the “major human functionings” (43) which define “a good human life” (42). These functionings include, among other things, bodily health and integrity, affiliation, and political participation (41-42). To be sure, personal autonomy, or in Nussbaum's words “practical reason,” is a good that “suffuses all the other functions” (44). But personal autonomy is not prioritized. A good life is one in which one is able to enjoy all of the major human functionings, that is, to flourish.
Nussbaum's approach takes on the problem of deformed preferences (see section 2.1.1) directly. To be sure, some may choose lives that do not include the actual exercise of some of the functionings — an ascetic may choose to compromise bodily health. But, Nussbaum explains, one must be able to function in each of these ways. Social arrangements are to be criticized if they render their participants unable to function in the valued ways regardless of their preferences (50). The women's movement should sensitize women and men to the injustice of denying women the ability to function in these valued ways, identify arrangements that are unjust to women by paying careful attention to diverse women's lives, and recommend remedies. Nussbaum holds that her account is compatible with global moral pluralism and thus may function as a foundation for a global feminism (Nussbaum 1990, 40).
Nussbaum's “capabilities approach” may be compared with procedural accounts of autonomy (see section 2.1.1). Procedural accounts suggest that the women's movement should work to protect and promote women's ability to live lives of their own choosing by identifying particular autonomy deficits in women's lives and promoting the conditions that enable autonomy. These approaches avoid directly judging the substance of the choices women make or the arrangements that result. They leave it to individuals and groups to fashion new, diverse, non-oppressive ways of life. The list of enabling conditions for personal autonomy is not unlike Nussbaum's list of human functionings. But advocates of procedural approaches may worry that the goal of the women's movement, according to the capabilities approach, is to bring to women a particular way of life, namely one in which women can function in these ways, instead of freeing women up to find their own way (Cudd 2004, 50). As Drucilla Cornell, an advocate of a procedural approach explains, “social equality [should be] redefined so as to serve freedom” (Cornell 1998, xii) because “there is nothing more fundamental for a human being” (17; see also Cudd 2004, 51-52). Procedural accounts of autonomy can include Nussbaum's approach, not as definitive of the kinds of lives women should live, but as an important contribution to the kind of reflection on the good life on which personal autonomy depends.
2.1.4 Personal Autonomy and the State
Although there is disagreement among egalitarian liberal feminists about the role of personal autonomy in the good life, there is substantial agreement that the gender system, or the patriarchal nature of inherited traditions and institutions, is responsible for a morally objectionable deficit in personal autonomy in women's lives, and that the state can and should take action to remedy this deficit. There is also substantial agreement among egalitarian liberal feminists concerning what the state should do. There is disagreement about some hard cases, however, which pit liberal values against one another.
Egalitarian liberal feminists hold that the state must effectively protect women from violence, regardless of where that violence takes place (Cudd 2006, 85-118, 209; Rhode 1997, 1193-95). They also hold that paternalistic and moralistic laws are an unjust use of state power. Such laws place control over women's lives in the hands of others and steer women into preferred ways of life. Laws restricting access to abortion are of particular import in this context because they take an extremely momentous choice away from women, and together with the cultural assignment of caregiving duties to women, steer women into the social role of mother. Women must have a legal right to abortion and meaningful access to abortion services. In addition, egalitarian liberal feminists hold that the state must not grant preferential treatment to particular family forms (Brake 2004, 293; Lloyd 1995, 1328; McClain 2006, 60). Some argue that this means giving gay and lesbian partnerships the same protections currently available to heterosexuals (McClain 2006, 6). Others argue for removing marriage's privileged legal status altogether or treating it legally more like other associations (Case 2006).
Egalitarian liberals tend to reject laws prohibiting prostitution. They advocate instead the legal regulation of the sex trade prioritizing women's safety and women's control over their own working conditions (Cornell 1998, 57; Nussbaum 2002, 90). They support the right to collective bargaining to secure decent wages and working conditions (Cornell 1998, 57; Cudd 2006, 211), as well as a guaranteed minimum income (Cudd 2006, 154). They also support laws against sex discrimination in education, employment, and public accommodations. According to egalitarian liberal feminists, the refusal to hire or promote a woman or do business with her because she is a woman is a morally objectionable limit on her options. But so are workplaces that are hostile to women or practices that have negative disparate impact on women. Egalitarian liberal feminists argue that laws prohibiting sexual harassment, and requiring affirmative action and comparable worth policies are often called for to remedy past and ongoing sex discrimination (Williams 2000, 253).
Egalitarian liberal feminists hold also that a significant source of women's reduced options is the structure of the workplace, which assumes that workers are free of caregiving responsibilities (Okin 1989, 176; Williams 2000). Women, and increasingly men, do not fit this model. The effect of not fitting the model is dramatic. As Anne L. Alstott explains: “Caretakers at every income level have fewer options than noncaretakers at the same income level” (Alstott 2004, 97). She continues: “I am worried that child-rearing too dramatically contracts the options among which mothers can choose” (23). Alstott and others argue that the state must ensure that the socially essential work of providing care to dependents does not unreasonably interfere with the personal autonomy of caregivers. Policies proposed to ensure sufficient personal autonomy for caregivers include parental leave, state subsidized, high quality day care, and flexible work schedules (Cudd 2006, 228; Okin 1989, 175). Some recommend financial support for caregivers (Alstott 2004, 75ff), others suggest guaranteeing a non-wage-earning spouse one half of her wage-earning spouse's paycheck (Okin 1989, 181).
But workplaces fail to accommodate the socially essential caregiving work of their employees in various ways. Thus Joan Williams has argued for legal recognition of the right to not be discriminated against in employment on the basis of one's caregiving responsibilities. Williams recommends, if necessary, legal action alleging failure to recognize this right as an incentive to employers to accommodate caregivers (Williams 2000, 274).
There is disagreement among egalitarian liberal feminists about some hard cases that pit liberal values against one another. Egalitarian liberal feminists tend to reject legal limits on pornography (Cornell 1998, 57-58). But some hold that arguments for restricting violent pornography are not unreasonable (Laden 2003, 148-149), and that the best arguments for freedom of expression fail to show that it should not be limited (Brison 1998). Indeed some argue that violent pornography can undermine the autonomy of viewers (Scoccia 1996) and the status of women as equal citizens (Spaulding 1988-89).
Other hard cases concern the role of the state in family life. Family life has dramatic affects on the personal autonomy of its adult members. Assuming the role of caregiver, for example, dramatically contracts women's options. On an egalitarian liberal feminist view, the state has an interest in ensuring that family life does not undermine women's autonomy. Some hold that the state should promote justice in the family — for example, the sharing of paid and unpaid labor by its adult members (Okin 1989, 171). To that end Hilde Bjoer recommends compulsory parental leave for both parents (Bjoer 2002, 403), as well as legal limits on overtime (405). She even muses that the state might prohibit ways of life that are incompatible with active childrearing (405). Others hold that the state may not be guided by a substantive ideal of family life (Alstott 2004, 114; see also Nussbaum 2000, 279-280; and Wolf-Devine 2003). (See section 2.2.1 for more discussion of this issue).
Girls' participation in families is, especially in the early years, nonvoluntary. The family affects the development of girls' sense of self-worth, as well as their preferences, and the capacities, like the capacity for reflection and imagination, on which their ability to live lives of their own choosing depends (Okin 1989, 97). Egalitarian liberal feminists hold that the state must protect and promote the development of autonomy capacities in children, especially girls. For example they hold that child-marriage should be legally prohibited (McClain 2006, 79); girls should have access to abortion without parental consent or notification (Rhode 1994, 1204); girls must receive a formal education free of sexist stereotyping, including instruction in the legal equality of women (McClain 2006, 81; Lloyd 1995, 1332), including autonomy-promoting sex education (McClain 2006, 57-58), and ensuring that girls are prepared to be economically independent (Lloyd 1995, 1332). Beyond this some hold that girls' interest in developing autonomy capacities requires that families be internally just, that is, that there be an equal division of paid and unpaid labor between adults, so that families are not characterized by “dependence and domination” (Okin 1989, 99-100). Others are not convinced that there is a necessary connection between this kind of justice in families and the development of girls' autonomy capacities (Lloyd 1995, 1335-1343), and hold that the state may not be guided by a substantive ideal of family life (Alstott 2004, 114; see also Nussbaum 2000a, 279-280; and Wolf-Devine 2003). (See section 2.2.1 for more discussion of this issue).
2.2 Political Autonomy
Some egalitarian liberal feminists emphasize the importance of political autonomy, that is, being co-author of the conditions under which one lives. Some use contractualist political theory to argue that the state should ensure that the basic structure of society satisfies principles of justice that women, as well as men, could endorse. Others argue that the democratic legitimacy of the basic conditions under which citizens live depends on the inclusion of women in the processes of public deliberation and electoral politics.
2.2.1 Distributive Justice
Some egalitarian liberal feminists, inspired by John Rawls' contractualist liberal theory of justice (Rawls 1971; 1993), argue that the state should ensure that the basic structure of society distributes the benefits and burdens of social cooperation fairly, that is, in a manner that women as well as men could endorse (Alstott 2004; Bjoer 2002; Lloyd 1998; McClain 2006; Okin 1989; Thompson 1993). They argue that the basic structure currently distributes benefits and burdens unfairly, in part due to the gender system or the patriarchal nature of inherited traditions and institutions. And they argue that, for this reason, remedial state action is called for.
As Rawls puts it, the basic structure of society is: “The way in which the major social institutions distribute fundamental rights and duties and determine the division of advantages from social cooperation. By major institutions I understand the political constitution and the principal economic and social arrangements… Competitive markets and the monogamous family [are] examples of major social institutions… The basic structure is the primary subject of justice because its effects are so profound and present from the start. The intuitive notion here is that this structure contains various social positions and that men born into different positions have different expectations of life determined, in part, by the political system as well as by economic and social circumstances. In this way the institutions of society favor certain starting places over others” (Rawls 1971, 6-7).
Rawls argues that the fairness of the basic structure of society may be assessed by asking what principles representatives of citizens (parties) would choose to determine the distribution of primary goods in society if they were behind a “veil of ignorance” (Rawls 1971, 12). The veil of ignorance blocks from the parties knowledge of their place in society: for example their socio-economic status, religion, and sex. (Rawls does not include sex in A Theory of Justice (Rawls 1971), but adds it in “Fairness to Goodness” (Rawls 1975, 537).) Susan Okin proposes we “take seriously both the notion that those behind the veil of ignorance do not know what sex they are and the requirement that the family and the gender system, as basic social institutions, are to be subject to scrutiny” (Okin 1989, 101).
Rawls argues that parties behind the veil of ignorance would choose two principles: a liberty principle providing for the “most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all;” and a principle of equality requiring equality of opportunity, and permitting inequalities only if they are to the benefit of the least well off (Rawls 1971, 302-303).
Okin argues that the “gender system” violates both the liberty and equality of opportunity principles because by effectively assigning roles to citizens according to sex it circumvents citizens' “free choice of occupation” (Okin 1989, 103). On Okin's view, this means that in a just society “gender could no longer form a legitimate part of the social structure, whether inside or outside the family” (103). None of the institutions of the basic structure, including the family, could assign roles according to sex.[2] It is common to argue that the state, educational institutions, and workplaces should not assign roles according to sex. But Okin argues that this applies to the family as well. Gender blindness must play the same role in the family that it plays in these institutions. In Okin's words, there must be “congruence” between the principles that govern these institutions and those that govern family life (21). That is, families must be just.
Okin offers a second argument to support the claim that families must be just. Rawls explains that a society based on his two principles of justice can be stable because within it citizens develop a sense of justice (Rawls 1971, 453ff). For our purposes consider that citizens must develop the conviction that citizens generally are due the rights of equal citizenship. Okin argues that when children are raised within unjust families, families which lack “equality and reciprocity,” and are characterized by “dependence and domination,” they are not likely to develop the requisite sense of justice (Okin 1989, 99-100; see also McClain 2006, 73-84). Instead, girls and boys and may grow to believe that women are not entitled to equal citizenship. Therefore, if the society governed by Rawls' two principles of justice is to be stable, families must be just.
What can and should the state do to ensure that gender no longer forms a “part of the social structure, whether inside or outside the family” (Okin 1989, 103)? Okin endorses measures for the workplace, for example state subsidized daycare, parental leave, and flextime (176, 186). These accommodations make it possible for women and men to choose against traditional roles. She also recommends protecting from vulnerability those women who do choose traditional roles by making them entitled to half of their spouse's paycheck (181). But Okin does not think that the state should stop at increasing the voluntariness of women's choices and compensating for disadvantage. She argues instead that the state may and should promote a particular ideal of family life. She tells us that the state should “encourage and facilitate the equal sharing by men and women of paid and unpaid work, or productive and reproductive labor” (171). Accommodations by employers may be understood, then, not only as a way of making options available to women, but as a way of encouraging the sharing of paid and unpaid work by spouses. Another way the state may encourage such egalitarianism is through autonomy-promoting education, especially for girls (177). To be sure, Okin argues that what is desired is a “future in which all will be likely to choose this mode of life” (171, my emphasis). But the fact that many people currently don't choose it does not mean, for Okin, that it is not an appropriate goal of state action (172). (There is a substantial literature on Okin's use of Rawls' theory of justice. See Egalitarian Liberal Feminism Works.)
Other egalitarian feminists apply contractualist political philosophy inspired by Rawls to the problem of justice for women but draw slightly different conclusions from Okin. S.A. Lloyd (1998), Anne L. Alstott (2004) and Linda C. McClain (2006) each argue that a basically Rawlsian contractualist argument supports the claim that the current disadvantages women suffer as a result of their shouldering a disproportionate share of the burdens of social reproduction must be remedied by state action. All three endorse many of Okin's policy proposals (Lloyd 1995, 1332; 1998, 218; Alstott 2004). But they reject Okin's claim that the state should promote a particular substantive ideal of family life (Lloyd 1995, 1340-1341; Lloyd 1998, 218; McClain 2006, 78). Alstott writes: “The egalitarian family is, even in principle, a troubling ideal. Strictly equal sharing seems unduly constraining, not merely because families today deviate from the idea, but because free people might want to organize their lives differently” (Alstott 2004, 113). Other egalitarian liberal feminists have voiced similar concerns. Ann Cudd worries that state action intended to promote gender fairness and foster women's autonomy could impose a homogenizing conception of the good life, and stifle the very reinventions of self and experiments in living that women's liberation requires (Cudd 2006, 209, 223; see also Wolf-Devine 2003).
2.2.2 Public Deliberation and Electoral Politics
Some egalitarian liberal feminists who emphasize the importance of political autonomy — that women be co-authors of the conditions under which they live — focus in particular on participation in the processes of democratic self-determination. These processes include both political deliberation in the many arenas of public political discourse, and electoral politics. Egalitarian liberal feminists hold that the conditions under which women live lack legitimacy because women are inadequately represented in these processes. They hold that this political autonomy deficit is, in large part, due to the “gender system” (Okin 1989, 89), or the patriarchal nature of inherited traditions and institutions, and that the women's movement should work to identify and remedy it.
Attempts to increase women's participation in public deliberation and electoral politics confront a vicious circle of women's exclusion. The gender system, or the patriarchal nature of inherited traditions and institutions, leads to women's being underrepresented in influential forums of public deliberation and in elected law-making bodies. For example women have less free time to engage in public deliberation because of the double-burden they carry of paid and unpaid labor; sex stereotyping leads many to think that women (especially women from ethnic and cultural minorities) are less capable of leadership than men; the behavior called for in agonistic public deliberation and electoral politics is understood to be masculine; issues of particular interest to women are seen as personal and not political issues; women lack power in the many institutions (like churches, universities, and think tanks) that influence political debate, etc. But when women are underrepresented in these forums and law-making bodies, it is unlikely that the justice of the gender system will become the subject of public conversation or its dismantling a target of legislative action.
Some egalitarian liberal feminists explore ways to escape this vicious circle. Because women are excluded from important forums of public deliberation and electoral politics in complex ways, remedies must address a variety of problems. Justice in the distribution of benefits and burdens in society would go some way towards enabling women to access forums of public debate on equal terms with men (Okin 1989, 104). But cultural change is necessary as well if stereotypes about women's abilities are not to interfere with their participation, if women's needs and interests are to be understood as legitimate claims on democratic power, and if men's dominance in institutions of influence is to be overcome. Seyla Benhabib argues that the women's movement, along with other new social movements like the gay and lesbian liberation movements, has begun this work (Benhabib 1992). While much of this change is cultural and must come about through civic action, the state has a role to play. Linda McClain argues that all children must receive civic education — to equip them for democratic citizenship — including instruction in women's equality (McClain 2006, 81). She also argues that the state may use its persuasive power to put traditionally excluded issues, like violence against women or the dilemma of balancing work and family, on the agenda for public deliberation (78).
Others take on the vicious circle of women's exclusion by recommending legal mechanisms for the inclusion of women in electoral politics (see Rhode 1994, 1205-1208; Peters 2006; Phillips 1991). Some suggest that legal mechanisms for including those who have been systematically excluded may be justified as remedies for the unjust disproportionate political power enjoyed by others (Phillips 2004, 6-10). Suggested mechanisms include targets or quotas for women (and other underrepresented groups) on party slates, or proportional representation in elected bodies. Karen Green, for example, argues for “guaranteed equal representation of both sexes in parliament” (Green 2006). There is diversity of opinion, however, among liberal feminists about the justice and efficacy of such mechanisms (Peters 2006; see also Rhode 1994, 1205).
2.3 Justification
Why are individuals entitled to personal and political autonomy? Why should social arrangements respect individuals' personal and political autonomy? And why should the state protect and promote it? Following John Rawls, we may distinguish broadly between two kinds of answers to these questions. The answers provided by “comprehensive liberals” rest on moral grounds. That is, comprehensive liberals point to moral theories to justify the importance of autonomy. The answers that “political liberals” offer, on the other hand, rest on “public reason.” That is, political liberals claim that, in societies like the United States, respect for autonomy is a shared, public value (Rawls 1993).
Jean Hampton may be counted among comprehensive liberals. Hampton's feminist contractualist account of justice in personal relationships (see section 2.2.1) is explicitly grounded in Kant's moral philosophy (Hampton 1993, 241). Drucilla Cornell also offers an egalitarian liberal feminist theory — focused on the right to intimate and sexual self-determination — that is explicitly grounded in Kant's moral theory (Cornell 1998, 17-18; see also Thurschwell 1999, 771-772). Ann Cudd too explains that her liberal feminist account of oppression as harm is grounded in a “background moral theory,” namely “a liberal contractarian view of the sort developed by John Rawls in A Theory of Justice, or the more libertarian version of David Gauthier in Morals by Agreement” (Cudd 2006, 231). Susan Okin's feminist theory of justice is also a comprehensive view (Okin 1999, 129). Okin draws on Rawls' A Theory of Justice, which Rawls himself claims is a comprehensive moral theory (Rawls 1993, xvii). In addition, as many argue, the substantive ideal of family life that Okin recommends (according to which paid and unpaid labor should be shared equally by spouses) (see section 2.2.1) conflicts with many reasonable conceptions of family life, and cannot be counted as, or derived from, a public value.
Other egalitarian liberal feminists argue that public reason, that is, shared, public values, support significant feminist conclusions. S.A. Lloyd argues also that feminists would do well to limit themselves to such values (Lloyd 1998, 210). She explains that “it's true that confining the argument to talk of socially recognized values requires operating with one hand tied behind one's back, so to speak. Conclusions that would be quite easy to reach from stronger feminist principles, or other comprehensive egalitarian principles, are much harder to reach using the sparse … toolbox [of public reason]” (210). But, she continues, if we can reach feminist conclusions on these sparse grounds, they will be much more difficult to reject. Lloyd constructs an argument based on shared, public values to the conclusion that justice requires that “women's disproportionate burden in social reproduction [must] be eliminated” (Lloyd 1998, 214). (She rejects, however, Okin's call for state promotion of egalitarianism in the family (Lloyd 1998, 218) (see section 2.2.1).
Linda McClain also argues that an egalitarian liberal feminism may proceed on the basis of public reason (McClain 2006). Through a discussion of recent constitutional and family law, McClain argues that sex equality is a public and constitutional principle (60; see also 22-23, 60-62, and 76). She explains that this principle requires state opposition to relations of subordination and domination in the family (62); state support for autonomy in intimate matters (22); and support for the development of autonomy capacities in children, especially girls (109). (She too rejects Okin's call for state promotion of egalitarianism within the family (78)). Martha Nussbaum also presents her “capabilities approach” as a political, and not a comprehensive, liberalism (see section 2.1.3.). The capabilities list, she argues, can be shared by citizens holding a wide variety of comprehensive conceptions of the good life, and thus should be able to function as a foundation for a political liberalism (Nussbaum 2000a, 76).
2.4 Criticism
2.4.1 Liberal Criticism
Some, including some egalitarian liberal feminists, argue that egalitarian liberal feminisms run the risk of being insufficiently liberal. Measures intended to promote gender fairness and the autonomy of women could end up unreasonably hindering citizen autonomy (Cudd 2006, 223). Some argue that Susan Okin's claim that the state should be guided by an egalitarian ideal of family life is an example of such a measure (see section 2.2.1). Other measures recommended by some egalitarian liberal feminists that some hold may be illiberal include quotas on party slates or in elected bodies (Peters 2006) (see section 2.2.2), and bans on violent pornography (see section 2.2.4).
Classical liberals or libertarians are critical of egalitarian liberal feminisms because, on their view, liberalism cannot support the claim that the right of some against coercive interference may be violated in order to promote the autonomy capacities of others, such as we find in affirmative action programs, or in the substantial taxation that would be necessary to fund the social programs egalitarian liberals endorse (Epstein 2002).
2.4.2 Conservative Criticism
Conservatives hold that reformers can do more harm than good when they undermine the institutions and norms which, while surely offending in many ways, also serve as the foundation for many people's well-being (Muller 1997; see also Fox-Genovese 1996). Such conservatives worry about the radical implications of liberal feminism, its willingness to put women's autonomy ahead of institutions and norms on which many people rely for their well-being. Ann Cudd suggests that the expansion of opportunity and equality promised by egalitarian liberal feminism “makes us all better off” (Cudd 2006, 237). Conservatives encourage us to consider also the loss that is in liberation.
2.4.3 Feminist Criticism
Some argue that egalitarian liberal feminism is insufficiently feminist. Some argue that the value of autonomy cannot support robust feminist criticism, and that robust feminist criticism requires a substantive feminist ideal of the good life (Yuracko 2003). Some argue that liberalism's central concern with fully functioning adult citizens renders it incapable of accounting sufficiently for the political value of caregiving work and the moral attitudes characteristic of the caring relation (Held 1987; Kittay 1999; Baier 1987; Ruddick 1989). Some argue that liberalism's focus on the distribution of benefits and burdens in society must be replaced with a focus on power relations (Young 1990, 37). Indeed, some argue that egalitarian liberal feminism's focus on women's disadvantage in the distribution of benefits and burdens, and on deficits in women's personal autonomy, overlooks the deeper problems of power inequality and the eroticization of domination and subordination that are the true lynchpins of the gender system (MacKinnon 1987; 1989).
Bibliography
Classical Liberal or Libertarian Feminism Works
Works Cited
- Almodovar, Norma Jean. (2002). ‘For Their Own Good: The Results of the Prostitution Laws as Enforced by Cops, Politicians, and Judges.’ In McElroy (2002): 71-87.
- Block, Walter. (1991). ‘Levin on Feminism and Freedom.’ Journal of Libertarian Studies X: 97-106.
- Boaz, David. (1997). Libertarianism: A Primer. New York: Free Press.
- Conway, David. (1998). Free-Market Feminism. London: Institute of Economic Affairs.
- Cornell, Drucilla. (1998). At the Heart of Freedom: Feminism, Sex, and Equality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
- Cudd, Ann. (2006). Analysing Oppression. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Dworkin, Andrea. (1991). ‘Terror, Torture, and Resistance.’ Canadian Women's Studies 12: 37-42
- Epstein, Richard. (2002). ‘Liberty and Feminism.’ In McElroy (2002): 30-42.
- –––. (1999). ‘Liberty, Patriarchy, and Feminism.’ University of Chicago Legal Forum 89: 106-111.
- –––. (1992). Forbidden Grounds: The Case Against Employment Discrimination Laws. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Fox-Genovese, Elizabeth. (1996). Feminism Is Not the Story of My Life: How Today's Feminist Elite Has Lost Touch with the Real Concerns of Women. London: Doubleday.
- –––. 1991. Feminism Without Illusions: A Critique of Individualism. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.
- Jaggar, Alison. (1983). Feminist Politics and Human Nature. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.
- Kirp, David L., Mark G. Yudoff, and Marlene Strong Franks. (1986). Gender Justice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Kittay, Eva. (1999). Love's Labor: Essays on Women, Equality and Dependency. New York: Routledge.
- Lehrman, Karen. (1997). The Lipstick Proviso: Women, Sex & Power in the Real World. New York: Anchor/Doubleday.
- Loudermilk, Kim. (2004). Fictional Feminism: How American Bestsellers Effect the Movement for Women's Equality. New York: Routledge.
- McElroy, Wendy, ed. (2002). Liberty for Women: Freedom and Feminism in the Twenty-First Century. Chicago: Ivan R. D.
- McElroy, Wendy. (2002a). ‘Introduction: Foundation of Individualist Freedom.’ In McElroy (2002): 5-26.
- –––. (2002b). ‘What Does Affirmative Action Affirm?’ In McElroy (2002): 181-188.
- –––. (2002c). ‘Breeder Reactionaries: The ‘Feminist’ War on New Reproductive Technologies.’ In McElroy (2002): 267-278.
- ––– (1998c). ‘An Exchange of E-Mail Letters on Gertrude B. Kelly.’ Association of Libertarian Feminists (ALF) News 68. [Available online].
- –––. (1998b). ‘The Non-Absurdity of Natural Law.’ The Freeman 48: 108-111.
- –––. (1995). XXX: A Woman's Right to Pornography. New York: St. Martin's Press.
- –––. (1991a). ‘The Roots of Individualist Feminist in 19th Century America.’ In McElroy (1991): 3-28.
- –––. (1991). Freedom, Feminism and the State: An Overview of Individualist Feminism. Chicago: Ivan R. Dee.
- Meyers, Diana. (2004). Being Yourself: Essays on Identity, Action, and Social Life. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
- Minow, Martha. (1990). Making All the Difference: Inclusion, Exclusion, and American Law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Morse, Jennifer Roback. (2001). Love and Economics: Why the Laissez-Faire Family Doesn't Work. Dallas: Spence Publishing.
- Nussbaum, Martha. (2000). ‘The Future of Feminist Liberalism.’ Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 74: 47-79.
- Paul, Ellen Frankel. (2002). ‘Fetal Protection and Freedom of Contract.’ In McElroy (2002): 131-151.
- –––. (1989). Equity and Gender: The Comparable Worth Debate. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.
- Presley, Sharon. (2001). Think For Yourself: Questioning Pressures to Conform. Ronin Publishing.
- –––. (2000). ‘No Authority But Oneself: The Anarchist Feminist Philosophy of Autonomy and Freedom.’ Social Anarchism 27 (Fall-Winter).
- Presley, Sharon and Lynn Kinsky. (1991). ‘Government is Women's Enemy.’ In McElroy (1991): 77-86.
- Presley, Sharon and Chrispin Sartwell, eds. (2005). Exquisite Rebel: Essays of Voltairine De Cleyre- Feminist, Anarchist, Genius. Albany: State University of New York.
- Rhode, Deborah. (1997). Speaking of Sex: The Denial of Gender Inequality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Roiphe, Katie. (1994). The Morning After: Sex, Fear and Feminism. Boston: Back Bay Books.
- Simon, Rita. (2002). ‘Women and Violent Crime.’ In McElroy (2002): 231-237.
- Sommers, Christina Hoff. (2007). “The Subjection of Islamic Women.” Weekly Standard Vol. 12, No. 34. [Available online]
- –––. (2002). ‘The Case against Ratifying the United Nations Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women (CEDAW).’ Government Testimony to the Senate Foreign Relations Committee, published by American Enterprise Institute. [Available online]
- –––. (2000). The War Against Boys: How Misguided Feminism is Harming Our Young Men. New York: Simon and Schuster.
- –––. (1994). Who Stole Feminism? How Women Have Betrayed Women. New York: Simon and Schuster.
- Stevens, Richard W., Hugo Teufel III, and Matthew Y. Biscan. (2002). ‘Disarming Women: Comparing ‘Gun Control’ to Self-Defense.’ In McElroy (2002): 238-263.
- Stolba, Christine and Diana Furchtgott-Roth. (2001). The Feminist Dilemma: When Success Is Not Enough. Washington, DC: AIE Press.
- –––. (1999). Women's Figures: An Illustrated Guide to the Ecnomic Progress of Women in America. Washington, DC: AEI Press and Independent Women's Forum.
- Strossen, Nadine. (2000). Defending Pornography: Free Speech, Sex and the Fight for Women's Rights. New York: New York University Press.
- Tabarrok, Alexander. (2002). ‘Abortion and Liberty.’ In McElroy (2002): 152-177.
- Taylor, Joan Kennedy. (2001). ‘A New View of the Libertarian Family: Review of Love and Economics.’ Association of Libertarian Feminists (ALF) News 80. [Available online].
- –––. (1999). What You Can Do About Sexual Harassment When You Don't Want to Call the Cops. New York: New York University Press.
- –––. (1993). Women's Issues: Feminism, Classical Liberalism, and the Future. Stanford, CA: Hoover Institution.
- –––. (1992). Reclaiming the Mainstream: Individualist Feminism Rediscovered. Buffalo: Prometheus Books.
- –––. (1991). ‘Protective Labor Legislation.’ In McElroy (1991): 187-192.
- Vaughn, Karen I. (1993). ‘Who Owns the Children? Libertarianism, Feminism, and Property.’ Reason Papers 18: 189-200.
- Warnick, Ashlie. (2003). ‘IFeminism. Review of Liberty for Women: Freedom and Feminism in the Twenty-First Century, Edited by Wendy McElroy.’ Michigan Law Review 101: 1602-1621.
- Williams, Joan C. (2000). Unbending Gender: Why Family and Work Conflict and What to Do About It. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Young, Cathy. (2007). ‘Enforcing Virtue.’ Reasononline. [Available online]
- –––. (2006). ‘Are Muslim Women Oppressed?: An Exploration of the Place of Women in Islam.’ Reasononline. [Available online]
- –––. (2004). ‘Taking Science Seriously: Conservative Dogma About Sex Roles Ignores Inconvenient Realities.’ Reasononline. [Available online]
- Yuracko, Kimberly. (2003). Perfectionism and Contemporary Feminist Values. Bloomington: University of Indiana Press.
Additional Sources
- Almeder, Robert F. (1994). ‘Liberal Feminism and Academic Feminism.’ Public-Affairs-Quarterly 8: 299-315.
- Case, Mary Anne. (1995). ‘Of Richard Epstein and Other Radical Feminists.’ Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 18: 369-418.
- Elshtain, Jean Bethke. (1991). ‘Antigone's Daughters.’ In McElroy (1991): 61-76.
- Gladstein, Mimi and Chris Sciabarra (eds). (1999). Feminist Interpretations of Ayn Rand. University Park: Penn State University Press.
- Jeske, Diane. (1996). ‘Libertarianism, Self-Ownership and Motherhood.’ Social Theory and Practice 22: 137-160.
- Jones, Bernie D. (2003). ‘Single Motherhood by Choice, Libertarian Feminism, and the Uniform Parentage Act.’ Texas Journal of Women and the Law 12: 419-449.
- Machan, Tibor (ed).(2006). Liberty and Justice. Washington, D.C.: Hoover Institution Press.
- McElroy, Wendy. (1998). The Reasonable Woman. A Guide to Intellectual Survival. Amherst: Prometheus Books.
- –––. (1991). ‘Abortion.’ In McElroy (1991): 145-156.
- –––. (1981). ‘Against the ERA.’ Libertarian Forum (June-July).
- McKitrick, Jennifer. (2006). ‘Liberty, Gender, and the Family.’ In Machan (2006).
- Morse, Jennifer Roback. (1999). ‘No Families, No Freedom: Human Flourishing in a Free Society.’ Social Philosophy and Policy 16: 290-314.
- –––. (1986). A Matter of Choice: A Critique of Comparable Worth by a Skeptical Feminist. New York: Priority Press.
- Posner, Richard A. (1989). ‘Conservative Feminism.’University of Chicago Legal Forum 191: 209-217.
- Presley, Sharon. (1999). ‘Ayn Rand's Philosophy of Individualism: A Feminist Psychologist's Perspective.’ In Gladstein and Schiabarra (1999).
- Presley, Sharon and Lynn Kinsky. (1991). ‘Government is Women's Enemy.’ In McElroy (1991): 77-86.
- Roiphe, Katie. (2007). Uncommon Arrangements: Seven Portraits of Married Life in London Literary Circles 1910-1939. The Dial Press.
- Sears, Hal D. (1977). The Sex Radicals: Free Love in High Victorian America. Lawrence, KS: Regents Press of Kansas.
- Strossen, Nadine. (1993). ‘Fighting Big Sister for Liberty and Equality.’ New York Law School Law Review 38: 1-8.
- –––. (1991). ‘The American Civil Liberties Union and Women's Rights.’ New York University Law Review 66: 1940-1961.
- Taylor, Joan Kennedy. (2001). ‘A New View of the Libertarian Family: Review of Love and Economics.’ Association of Libertairan Feminists (ALF) News 80. [Available online].
- Tong, Rosemarie. (1998). ‘Radical Feminism: Libertarian and Cultural Perspectives.’ In Tong (1998): 45-93.
- –––. (1998). Feminist Thought. Oxford: Westview.
- Young, Cathy. (1999). Ceasefire: Why Women and Men Must Join Forces to Achieve True Equality. New York: The Free Press.
- Young, Cathy and Michael Weiss. (1996). ‘Feminist Jurisprudence: Equal Rights or Neo-Paternalism?’ Policy Analysis 256 (Cato Institute).
Egalitarian Liberal Feminism Works
Works Cited
- Alstott, Linda. (2004). No Exit: What Parents Owe Their Children and What Society Owes Parents. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Antony, Louise and Charlotte Witt (eds.) (1993). A Mind of One's Own. Oxford: Westview.
- Baehr, Amy R., (ed). (2004a). Varieties of Feminist Liberalism. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
- Baier, Annette. (1987). ‘The Need for More than Justice.’ In Hanen and Nielsen (1987).
- Benhabib, Seyla. (1992). Situating the Self. New York: Routledge.
- Bjoer, Hilde. (2002). ‘Women and the Rawlsian Social Contract.’ Social Justice Research 15: 393-407.
- Brake, Elizabeth. (2004). ‘Rawls and Feminism: What Should Feminists Make of Liberal Neutrality?’ Journal of Moral Philosophy 1: 293-309.
- Brison, Susan. (1998). ‘The Autonomy Defense of Freedom of Speech.’ Ethics 108: 312-339.
- –––. (1997). ‘Outliving Oneself: Trauma, Memory and Personal Identity.’ In Meyers (1997): 12-39.
- Case, Mary Anne. (2006). ‘Marriage Licenses.’ Minnesota Law Review 89: 1758-1796.
- Cornell, Drucilla. (1998). At the Heart of Freedom: Feminism, Sex, and Equality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
- Cudd, Ann. (2006). Analysing Oppression. New York: Oxford University Press.
- –––. (2004). ‘The Paradox of Liberal Feminism: Preference Rationality, and Oppression.’ In Baehr (2004): 37-62.
- Fox-Genovese, Elizabeth. (1991). Feminism Without Illusions: A Critique of Individualism. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.
- Freeman, Samuel, ed. (2003). Cambridge Companion to Rawls. New York: Cambridge University Press.
- –––. (1999). John Rawls: Collected Papers. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Green, Karen. (2006). ‘Parity and Procedural Justice.’ Essays in Philosophy 7. URL=<http://www.humboldt.edu/~essays/green.html>.
- Hampton, Jean. (1993). ‘Feminist Contractarianism.’ In Antony and Witt (1993): 227-56.
- Hanen, Marsha and Kai Nielsen. (1987). Science, Morality and Feminist Theory. Calgary: University of Calgary Press.
- Held, Virginia. (1987). ‘Non-contractual Society: A Feminist View.’ In Hanen and Nielsen (1987).
- Kittay, Eva. (1999). Love's Labor: Essays on Women, Equality and Dependency. New York: Routledge.
- Laden, Anthony Simon. (2003). ‘Radical Liberals, Reasonable Feminists: Reason, Power and Objectivity in MacKinnon and Rawls.’ Journal of Political Philosophy 11: 133-152.
- Lloyd, S.A. (1998). ‘Toward a Liberal Theory of Sexual Equality.’ Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues 9: 203-224.
- –––. (1995). ‘Situating a Feminist Critique of John Rawls' Political Liberalism.’ Loyola Law Review 28: 1319-1344.
- MacKenzie, Catriona. (1999). ‘Imagining Oneself Otherwise.’ In MacKenzie and Stoljar (1999): 124-150.
- MacKenzie, Catriona and Natalie Stoljar. (1999). ‘Autonomy Refigured.’ In MacKenzie and Stoljar (1999): 3-34.
- MacKenzie, Catriona and Natalie Stoljar, (eds.) (1999). Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self. New York: Oxford University Press.
- MacKinnon, Catharine. (1989). Toward a Feminist Theory of the State. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- –––. (1987). Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Mansbridge, Jane. (1997). ‘Should Blacks Represent Blacks and Women Represent Women? A Contingent “Yes”.’ The Journal of Politics 61: 628-657.
- McClain, Linda. (2006). The Place of Families: Fostering Capacity, Equality and Responsibility. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Meyers, Diana. (2004). Being Yourself: Essays on Identity, Action, and Social Life. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
- –––. (2002). Gender in the Mirror: Cultural Images and Women's Agency. New York: Oxford.
- Meyers, Diana T. (ed.) (1997). Feminists Rethink the Self. Boulder: Westview.
- Muller, Jerry Z. 1997. ‘What is Conservative Social and Political Thought?' In Muller (1997): 3-31.
- Muller, Jerry Z. ed. (1997). Conservatism: An Anthology of Social and Political Thought from David Hume to the Present. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
- Nussbaum, Martha C. (2002). ‘Whether from Reason or Prejudice: Taking Money for Bodily Services.’ In Nussbaum (1999): 276-298.
- –––. (2000). Women and Human Development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- –––. (1999). Sex and Social Justice. New York: Oxford.
- Okin, Susan. (1989). Justice, Gender and the Family. Basic Books: New York.
- Pearce, Diana. 1978. ‘The Feminization of Poverty.’ Urban and Social Change Review 1978: 28-36.
- Peters, Anne. (2006). ‘Electoral Gender Quotas: Undemocratic, Unfair and Inefficient?’ Unpublished manuscript on file with the author.
- Phillips, Anne. (2004). ‘Defending Equality of Outcome.’ Journal of Political Philosophy 12: 1-19.
- –––. 1991. Engendering Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.
- Radzik, Linda. (2005). ‘Justice in the Family: A Defence of Feminist Contractarianism.’ Journal of Applied Philosophy 22: 45-54.
- Rawls, John. (1997). ‘The Idea of Public Reason Revisited.’ In Freeman (1999): 573-615.
- –––. (1993). Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
- –––. (1975). ‘Fairness to Goodness.’ In Freeman (1999): 267-285.
- –––. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Rhode, Deborah. (1997). Speaking of Sex: The Denial of Gender Inequality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- –––. (1994). “Feminism and the State.” Harvard Law Review 107: 1181-1208.
- Ruddick, Sarah. (1989). Maternal Thinking. New York: Ballentine Books.
- Sample, Ruth. (2002). ‘Why Feminist Contractarianism?’ Journal of Social Philosophy 33: 257-281.
- Scoccia, Danny. (1996). ‘Can Liberals Support a Ban on Violent Pornography?’ Ethics 106: 776-799.
- Smith, Patricia. (2004). ‘Liberalism as an Antidote to Stereotyping.’ In Baehr (2004): 21-36.
- Spaulding, Christina. (1988-89). ‘Anti-Pornography Laws as a Claim for Equal Respect: Feminism, Liberalism, and Community.’ Berkeley Women's Law Journal 4: 128-165.
- Williams, Joan. (2000). Unbending Gender: Why Family and Work Conflict and What to Do About It. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Wolf, Christopher, ed. (2004). Liberalism at the Crossroads: An Introduction to Contemporary Liberal Political Theory and Its Critics (2nd Edition). Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
- Wolf-Devine, Celia. (2004). ‘The Hegemonic Liberalism of Susan Moller Okin.’ In Wolf (2004): 41-59.
- Young, Iris. (1990). Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
- Yuracko, Kimberly. (2003). Perfectionism and Contemporary Feminist Values. Bloomington: University of Indiana Press.
Additional Sources
- Abbey, Ruth. (2007). ‘Back Toward a Comprehensive Liberalism? Justice as Fairness, Gender and Families.’ Political Theory 35: 5-28.
- Allen, Anita L. (2003). Why Privacy Isn't Everything: Feminist Reflections on Personal Accountability. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
- Antony, Louise M. (1998). ‘Back to Androgyny: What Bathrooms Can Teach Us About Equality.’ Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues 9: 1-20.
- Baehr, Amy R. (2004b). ‘Feminist Politics and Feminist Pluralism: Can We Do Feminist Political Theory without Theories of Gender?’ Journal of Political Philosophy 12: 411-436.
- –––. (2003). ‘A Feminist Liberal Approach to Hate Crime Legislation.’ The Journal of Social Philosophy 34: 134-152. Reprinted in Baehr (2004): 265-286.
- –––. (1996). ‘Towards a New Feminist Liberalism: Okin, Rawls, and Habermas. Hypatia 11: 49-66. Reprinted in The Philosophy of Rawls: A Collection of Essays, vol. 3 Henry S. Richardson and Paul J. Weithman, eds. (New York: Garland Publishing, 1999): 295-312.
- Bassham, Gregory. (1992). ‘Feminist Legal Theory: A Liberal Response.’ Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics and Public Policy 6: 293-319.
- Bjoer, Hilde. (2000). ‘Children and Theories of Social Justice.’ Feminist Economics 6: 23-39.
- Brake, Elizabeth. (2000). ‘A Liberal Response to Catharine MacKinnon.’ Southwest Philosophical Studies 22: 17-23.
- Brennan, Samantha. (2004). ‘The Liberal Rights of Feminist Liberalism.’ In Baehr (2004): 85-102.
- Card, Robert F. (2001). ‘Gender, Justice Within the Family, and the Commitments of Rawlsian Liberalism.’ Public-Affairs-Quarterly 15: 155-171.
- Cohen, Joshua. (1992). ‘Okin on Justice, Gender and Family.’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22: 263-287.
- Cornell, Drucilla. (1995). The Imaginary Domain: Abortion, Pornography, and Sexual Harassment. New York: Routledge.
- De Wijze, Stephen. (2000). ‘The Family and Political Justice.’ The Journal of Ethics 4: 257-282.
- English, Jane. (1977). ‘Justice Between Generations.’ Philosophical Studies 31: 91-104.
- Exdell, J. (1994). ‘Feminism, Fundamentalism and Liberal Legitimacy.’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24: 441-463.
- Gill, Emily R. (2001). Becoming Free: Autonomy and Diversity in the Liberal Polity. Lawrence: University of Kansas Press.
- Graham, Gordon. (1994). ‘Liberal vs Radical Feminism Revisited.’ Journal of Applied Philosophy 11: 155-170.
- Green, Karen. (1994). ‘Freud, Wollstonecraft, and Ecofeminism: A Defense of Liberal Feminism.’ Environmental Ethics 16: 117-33.
- –––. (1986). ‘Rawls, Women and the Priority of Liberty.’ Australian Journal of Philosophy 64: 26-36.
- Groenhout, Ruth. (2002). ‘Essentialist Challenges to Liberal Feminism.’ Social Theory and Practice 28: 51-75.
- Hager, Mark M. (1999). ‘Sex in the Original Position: A Restatement of Liberal Feminism.’ University of Wisconsin Women's Law Journal 14: 181-241.
- Jensen, Pamela Grande, ed. (1996). Finding a New Feminism: Rethinking the Woman Question for Liberal Democracy. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
- Johnson, Pauline. (1994). Feminism as Radical Humanism. Boulder: Westview.
- Kearnes, Debrah. (1983). ‘A Theory of Justice — and Love; Rawls on the Family.’ Politics 18 (Journal of the Australasian Political Studies Association): 36-42.
- Kensinger, Loretta. (1997). ‘(In)Quest of Liberal Feminism.’ Hypatia 12: 178-197.
- Kymlicka, Will. (1991). ‘Rethinking the Family.’ Philosophy and Public Affairs 20: 77-97.
- Laden, Anthony Simon. (2001). Reasonably Radical: Deliberative Liberalism and the Politics of Identity. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
- Lloyd, S.A. (1994). “Family Justice and Social Justice.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 75: 353-371.
- McKeen, Catherine. (2006). ‘Gender, Choice and Partiality: A Defense of Rawls on the Family.’ Essays in Philosophy Vo. 7, No. 1. URL=<http://www.humboldt.edu/~essays/mckeen.html>.
- Mendus, Susan. (1999). ‘The Importance of Love in Rawls' Theory of Justice’. British Journal of Political Science 29: 57-75.
- Minow, Martha. (1990). Making All the Difference: Inclusion, Exclusion, and American Law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Munuz-Darde, Veronique. (1998). ‘Rawls, Justice in the Family and Justice of the Family.’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 48: 335-353.
- Nash, Kate. (1998). Universal Difference: Feminism and the Undecidability of ‘Women.’ Basingstoke: Macmillan.
- Nussbaum, Martha C. (2003). ‘Rawls and Feminism.’ In Freeman (2003): 488-520.
- –––. (2000). ‘The Future of Feminist Liberalism.’ Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 74: 47-79.
- Okin, Susan. (2005). ‘ ‘Forty Acres and a Mule’ for Women: Rawls and Feminism.’ Politics, Philosophy and Economics 4: 233-248.
- –––. (1999). Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? Princeton: Princeton University Press.
- –––. (1994). ‘Political Liberalism, Justice and Gender.’ Ethics 105: 23-43.
- Phillips, Anne. (2001). ‘Feminism and Liberalism Revisited: Has Martha Nussbaum Got it Right?’ Constellations 8: 249-266.
- Radzik, Linda. (2005). ‘Justice in the Family: A Defence of Feminist Contractarianism.’ Journal of Applied Philosophy 22: 45-54.
- Richardson, Janice. (2007). “On Not Making Ourselves the Prey of Others.” Feminist Legal Studies 15: 33-55.
- Russell, J.S. (1995). ‘Okin's Rawlsian Feminism? Justice in the Family and Another Liberalism.’ Social Theory and Practice 21: 397-426.
- Schaeffer, Denise. (2001). ‘Feminism and Liberalism Reconsidered: The Case of Catherine MacKinnon.’ American Political Science Review 95: 699-708.
- Schwartz, Justin. (2001). ‘Rights of Inequality: Rawlsian Justice, Equal Opportunity, and the Status of the Family.’ Legal Theory 7: 83-117.
- Smith, Andrew F. (2004). ‘Closer but Still No Cigar: On the Inadequacy of Rawls's Reply to Okin's “Political Liberalism, Justice, and Gender.”’ Social Theory and Practice 30: 59-71.
- Smith, Patricia. (1998). ‘Autonomy, Aspiration and Accomplishment: Some Steps and Barriers to Equality for Women.’ Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues 9: 257-278.
- Spinner-Halev, Jeff. (2001). ‘Feminism, Multiculturalism, Oppression and the State.’ Ethics 112: 84-113.
- Thompson, Janna. (1993). ‘What Do Women Want? Rewriting the Social Contract.’ International Journal of Moral and Social Studies 8: 257-272.
- Thurschwell, Adam. (1999). ‘Radical Feminist Liberalism: At the Heart of Freedom: Feminism, Sex, and Equality by Drucilla Cornell.’ Rutgers Law Review 51: 745-776.
- Tong, Rosemarie. (1998). ‘Liberal Feminism.’ In Tong (1998): 10-44.
- –––. (1998). Feminist Thought. Oxford: Westview.
- Walker, John D. (1995). ‘Liberalism, Consent, and the Problem of Adaptive Preferences.’ Social Theory and Practice 21: 457-471.
- Ward, Cynthia. (1994). ‘A Kinder, Gentler Liberalism? Visions of Empathy in Feminist and Communitarian Literature.’ University of Chicago Law Review 61: 929-955.
- Ward, Cynthia. (1999). ‘Introduction: Reconstructing Liberalism.’ William and Mary Law Review 40: 719-21.
- Wendell, Susan. (1987). ‘A (Qualified) Defense of Liberalism.’ Hypatia 2: 65-93.
- Wijze, S.D. (2000). ‘The Family and Political Justice — The Case for Political Liberalisms.’ The Journal of Ethics 4: 257-282.
- Williams, Joan. (2006). Opt Out or Forced Out? The Untold Story of Why Women Leave the Workforce. The Center for WorkLife Law, University of California, Hastings College of Law. [Available online (PDF)]
- Wolf, Christopher, ed. (2003). Liberalism at the Crossroads: An Introduction to Contemporary Liberal Political Theory and Its Critics (2nd Edition). Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Historical Sources
- Abbey, Ruth. (1999). ‘Back to the Future: Marriage as Friendship in the Thoughts of Mary Wollstoncraft.’ Hypatia 14: 78-95.
- Anderson, Elizabeth. 1991. “John Stuart Mill and Experiments in Living.” Ethics 102: 4-26.
- Baum, Bruce. (1997). ‘Feminism, Liberalism and Cultural Pluralism: J. S. Mill on Mormon Polygyny.’ Journal of Political Philosophy 5: 230-253.
- Boucher, J. (2003). ‘Betty Friedan and the Radical Past of Liberal Feminism.’ New Politics 9: 23-32.
- Burgess-Jackson, Keith. (1995). ‘John Stuart Mill, Radical Feminist.’ Social Theory and Practice 21: 369-396
- Donner, Wendy. (1993). ‘John Stuart Mill's Liberal Feminism.’ Philosophical Studies 69: 155-166.
- Engster, Daniel. (1995).‘Mary Wollstonecraft's Nurturing Liberalism: Between and Ethic of Justice and Care.’ American Political Science Review 95: 577-588.
- Friedan, Betty. (1974) (1963). The Feminine Mystique. New York: Norton.
- Gerson, Gal. (2004). ‘Gender in the Liberal Tradition: Hobhouse on the Family.’ History of Political Thought 25: 700-725.
- –––. (2002). ‘Liberal Feminism: Individuality and Oppositions in Wollstonecraft and Mill.’ Political Studies 50: 794-810.
- Hekman, Susan. (1992). ‘John Stuart Mill's “The Subjection of Women”: The Foundations of Liberal Feminism.’ History of European Ideas 15: 681-686.
- Makus, Ingrid. (1996). Women, Politics and Reproduction: The Liberal Legacy. Tonawanda: University of Toronto Press.
- Mill, John Stuart. (1989) (1869). The Subjection of Women. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- –––. (1989) (1859). On Liberty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Smith, G.W. (2000). ‘J.S. Mill on What We Don't Know about Women.’ Utilitas: A Journal of Utilitarian Studies 12: 41-61.
- Stafford, W. (2004). ‘Is Mill's Liberal Feminism Masculinist?’ Journal of Political Ideologies 9: 159-79.
- Tulloch, Gail. (1989). ‘Mill's Epistemology in Practice in his Liberal Feminism.’ Educational Philosophy and Theory 21: 32-39.
- Wollstonecraft, Mary. (1998) (1792). A Vindication of the Rights of Woman. New York: Norton.
Selected Feminist Criticism
- Fox-Genovese, Elizabeth. (1990). Feminism Without Illusions: A Critique of Individualism. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.
- Held, Virginia. (1987). ‘Non-contractual Society: A Feminist View.’ In Marsha Hanen and Kai Nielsen (eds.) Science, Morality and Feminist Theory. Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary 13: 111-37.
- Jaggar, Alison. (1983). Feminist Politics and Human Nature. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.
- MacKinnon, Catharine. (1989). Toward a Feminist Theory of the State. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- –––. (1987). Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Pateman, Carole. (1988). The Sexual Contract. Cambridge: Polity Press.
- Young, Iris. (2006). ‘Taking the Basic Structure Seriously.’ Perspectives on Politics 4: 91-97.
- –––. (1990). Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
- Yuracko, Kimberly. (2003). Perfectionism and Contemporary Feminist Values. Bloomington: University of Indiana Press.
Other Internet Resources
Cited Resources
- Feser, Edward. (2001). ‘What Libertarianism Isn't.’
- Heckert, Jamie. (2004). ‘Towards Consenting Relations: Anarchism and Sexuality.’ [DOC]
- Long, Roderick. (2001). ‘Equality: The Unknown Ideal.’
- –––. (1997). ‘Beyond Patriarchy: A Libertarian Model of the Family.’
- Long, Roderick and Frederick Johnson. (2005). ‘Libertarian Feminism: Can This Marriage Be Saved?’ [PDF]
- McElroy, Wendy. (2001). ‘Individualism: A New View of Feminism.’
Classical Liberal or Libertarian Feminist Internet Resources
- Association of Libertarian Feminists
- Ifeminism
- Individualist Feminist Compendium
- Libertarians for Life
Egalitarian Liberal Feminist Internet Resources
- Center for WorkLife Law (Hastings College of the Law)
- National Abortion Rights Action League (NARAL)
- National Organization for Women (NOW)
Other Resources
Related Entries
democracy | feminism, approaches to | feminist (topics) | feminist (topics): perspectives on autonomy | feminist (topics): perspectives on power | feminist (topics): perspectives on reproduction and the family | justice: distributive | liberalism | libertarianism | liberty | pornography: and censorship | rights