Supplement to Quantum Logic and Probability Theory
The Basic Theory of Ordering Relations
What follows is the briefest possible summary of the order-theoretic notions used in the main text. For a good introduction to this material, see Davey & Priestley [1990]. More advanced treatments can be found in Gratzer [1998] and Birkhoff [1967].
- 1. Ordered sets
- 2. Lattices
- 3. Ortholattices
- 4. Orthomodularity
- 5. Closure Operators, Interior Operators and Adjunctions
1. Ordered Sets
A partial ordering—henceforth, just an ordering—on a set P is a reflexive, anti-symmetric, and transitive binary relation ⊴ on P. Thus, for all p, q, r ∈ P, we have
- p ⊴ p
- p ⊴ q and q ⊴ p only if p = q.
- if p ⊴ q and q ⊴ r then p ⊴ r
If p ⊴ q, we speak of p as being less than, or below q, and of q as being greater than, or above p, in the ordering.
A partially ordered set, or poset, is a pair (P, ⊴ ) where P is a set and ⊴ is a specified ordering on P. It is usual to let P denote both the set and the structure, leaving ⊴ tacit wherever possible. Any collection of subsets of some fixed set X, ordered by set-inclusion, is a poset; in particular, the full power set ℘(X) is a poset under set inclusion.
Let P be a poset. The meet, or greatest lower bound, of p, q ∈ P, denoted by p∧q, is the greatest element of P—if there is one—lying below both p and q. The join, or least upper bound, of p and q, denoted by p∨q, is the least element of P—if there is one—lying above both p and q. Thus, for any elements p, q, r of P, we have
- if r ⊴ p∧q, then r ⊴ p and r ⊴ q
- if p∨q ⊴ r, then p ⊴ r and q ⊴ r
Note that p∧p = p∨p = p for all p in P. Note also that p ⊴ q iff p∧q = p iff p∨q = q.
Note that if the set P = ℘(X), ordered by set-inclusion, then p∧q = p∩q and p∨q = p∪q. However, if P is an arbitrary collection of subsets of X ordered by inclusion, this need not be true. For instance, consider the collection P of all subsets of X = {1,2,...,n} having even cardinality. Then, for instance, {1,2}∨{2,3} does not exist in P, since there is no smallest set of 4 elements of X containing {1,2,3}. For a different sort of example, let X be a vector space and let P be the set of subspaces of X. For subspaces M and N, we have
M∧N = M∩N, but M∨N = span(M∪N).
The concepts of meet and join extend to infinite subsets of a poset P. Thus, if A⊆P, the meet of A is the largest element (if any) below A, while the join of A is the least element (if any) above A. We denote the meet of A by ∧A or by ∧a∈A a. Similarly, the join of A is denoted by ∨A or by ∨a∈A a.
2. Lattices
A lattice is a poset (L, ⊴ ) in which every pair of elements has both a meet and a join. A complete lattice is one in which every subset of L has a meet and a join. Note that ℘(X) is a complete lattice with respect to set inclusion, as is the set of all subspaces of a vector space. The set of finite subsets of an infinite set X is a lattice, but not a complete lattice. The set of subsets of a finite set having an even number of elements is an example of a poset that is not a lattice.
A lattice (L, ⊴ ) is distributive iff meets distribute over joins and vice versa:
p ∧ (q∨r) = (p∧q) ∨ (p∧r), andp ∨ (q∧r) = (p∨q) ∧ (p∨r).
The power set lattice ℘(X), for instance, is distributive (as is any lattice of sets in which meet and join are given by set-theoretic intersection and union). On the other hand, the lattice of subspaces of a vector space is not distributive, for reasons that will become clear in a moment.
A lattice L is said to be bounded iff it contains a smallest element 0 and a largest element 1. Note that any complete lattice is automatically bounded. For the balance of this appendix, all lattices are assumed to be bounded, absent any indication to the contrary.
A complement for an element p of a (bounded) lattice L is another element q such that p ∧ q = 0 and p ∨ q = 1.
In the lattice ℘(X), every element has exactly one complement, namely, its usual set-theoretic complement. On the other hand, in the lattice of subspaces of a vector space, an element will typically have infinitely many complements. For instance, if L is the lattice of subspaces of 3-dimensional Euclidean space, then a complement for a given plane through the origin is provided by any line through the origin not lying in that plane.
Proposition:
If L is distributive, an element of L can have at most one complement.Proof:
Suppose that q and r both serve as complements for p. Then, since L is distributive, we have
q = q∧1 = q ∧ (p∨r) = (q∧p) ∨ (q∧r) = 0 ∨ (q∧r) = q∧r Hence, q ⊴ r. Symmetrically, we have r ⊴ q; thus, q = r.
Thus, no lattice in which elements have multiple complements is distributive. In particular, the subspace lattice of a vector space (of dimension greater than 1) is not distributive.
If a lattice is distributive, it may be that some of its elements have a complement, while others lack a complement. A distributive lattice in which every element has a complement is called a Boolean lattice or a Boolean algebra. The basic example, of course, is the power set ℘(X) of a set X. More generally, any collection of subsets of X closed under unions, intersections and complements is a Boolean algebra; a theorem of Stone and Birkhoff tells us that, up to isomorphism, every Boolean algebra arises in this way.
3. Ortholattices
In some non-uniquely complemented (hence, non-distributive) lattices, it is possible to pick out, for each element p, a preferred complement p′ in such a way that
- if p ⊴ q then q′ ⊴ p′
- p′′ = p
When these conditions are satisfied, one calls the mapping p→p′ an orthocomplementation on L, and the structure (L, ⊴ ,′) an orthocomplemented lattice, or an ortholattice for short.
Note again that if a distributive lattice can be orthocomplemented at all, it is a Boolean algebra, and hence can be orthocomplemented in only one way. In the case of L(H) the orthocomplementation one has in mind is M → M⊥ where M⊥ is defined as in Section 1 of the main text. More generally, if V is any inner product space (complete or not), let L(V) denote the set of subspaces M of V such that M = M⊥⊥ (such a subspace is said to be algebraically closed). This again is a complete lattice, orthocomplemented by the mapping M → M⊥.
4. Orthomodularity
There is a striking order-theoretic characterization of the lattice of closed subspaces of a Hilbert space among lattices L(V) of closed subspaces of more general inner product spaces. An ortholattice L is said to be orthomodular iff, for any pair p, q in L with p ⊴ q,
(OMI) (q∧p′)∨p = q.
Note that this is a weakening of the distributive law. Hence, a Boolean lattice is orthomodular. It is not difficult to show that if H is a Hilbert space, then L(H) is orthomodular. The striking converse of this fact is due to Amemiya and Araki [1965]:
Theorem:
Let V be an inner product space (over R, C or the quaternions) such that L(V) is orthomodular. Then V is complete, i.e., a Hilbert space.
5. Closure Operators, Interior Operators and Adjunctions
Let P and Q be posets. A mapping f : P → Q is order preserving iff for all p,q ∈ P, if p ⊴ q then f(p) ⊴ f(q).
A closure operator on a poset P is an order-preserving map cl : P → P such that for all p ∈ P,
- cl(cl(p)) = cl(p)
- p ⊴ cl(p).
Dually, an interior operator on P is an order-preserving mapping int : P → P on P such that for all p ∈ P,
- int(int(p)) = int(p)
- int(p) ⊴ p
Elements in the range of cl are said to be closed; those in the range of int are said to be open. If P is a (complete) lattice, then the set of closed, respectively open, subsets of P under a closure or interior mapping is again a (complete) lattice.
By way of illustration, suppose that O and C are collections of subsets of a set X with O closed under arbitrary unions and C under arbitrary intersections. For any set A ⊆ X, let
cl(A) = ∩{C∈C | A ⊆ C}, andint(A) = ∪{O∈O | O ⊆ A}
Then cl and int are interior operators on ℘(X), for which the closed and open sets are precisely C and O, respectively. The most familiar example, of course, is that in which O, C are the open and closed subsets, respectively, of a topological space. Another important special case is that in which C is the set of linear subspaces of a vector space V; in this case, the mapping span : ℘(V) → ℘(V) sending each subset of V to its span is a corresponding closure.
An adjunction between two posets P and Q is an ordered pair (f, g) of mappings f : P → Q and g : Q → P connected by the condition that, for all p ∈ P, q ∈ Q
f(p) ⊴ q if and only if p ⊴ g(q).
In this case, we call f a left adjoint for g, and call g a right adjoint for f. Two basic facts about adjunctions, both easily proved, are the following:
Proposition:
Let f : L → M be an order-preserving map between complete lattices L and M. Then
- f preserves arbitrary joins if and only if it has a right adjoint.
- f preserves arbitrary meets if and only if it has a left adjoint.
Proposition:
Let (f, g) be an adjunction between complete lattices L and M. Then
- g ○ f : L →L is a closure operator.
- f ○ g : M → M is an interior operator.