Supplement to Death

The Argument: Death and Posthumous Events Don’t Affect Us

Here is a more explicit version of 1–13 (with thanks to Curtis Brown):

Let \(s,s',\ldots\) range over subjects; \(v,v',\ldots\) over events and states; and \(t,t',\ldots\) over times. We can use the following abbreviations:

\(\SD(v,s,t)\): \(v\) is the state of \(s\) being dead at \(t\)
\(\harm 2(v,s)\): \(v\) harms \(s\)
\(\harm 3(v,s,t)\): \(v\) harms \(s\) at \(t\)
\(t \gt\) t’: \(t\) is after \(t'\)
\(t \ge t'\): \(t\) is after \(t'\) or \(t = t'\)

We can use the following function symbols:

For any subject \(s\), \(\ED(s)\) is the event of \(s\)’s death

For any event or state \(v\), T\((v)\) is the time \(v\) occurs or holds

Next come axioms:

A1.  \(\forall v\forall s(\harm 2(v,s)\) iff \(\exists t \harm 3(v,s,t))\)
A2.  \(\forall v\forall s(v\) is posthumous for \(s\) iff T\((v) \gt \T(\ED(s)))\)
A3.  \(\forall v\forall s\forall t\)(If \(\SD(v,s)\), then \(t \gt \T(\ED(s)))\)

Then premises:

P1.  \(\forall v\forall s\forall t\) (If \(v\) affects \(s\) at \(t\), then \(v\) causally affects \(s\) at \(t)\)
P2.  \(\forall v\forall s\forall t\) (If \(v\) causally affects \(s\) at \(t\), then \(s\) exists at \(t)\)
P3.  \(\forall v\forall s\forall t\) (If \(\harm 3(v,s,t)\), then \(v\) affects \(s\) at \(t)\)
P4.  \(\forall v\forall s\forall t\) (If \(v\) causally affects \(s\) at \(t\), then \(t \ge\) T\((v))\)
P5.  \(\forall v\forall s\) (If \(t \gt \T(\ED(s))\), then it is not the case that \(s\) exists at \(t)\)

Here are the conclusions to be reached:

C1.  No posthumous event harms us; i.e.,
\(\forall v\forall s\) (If \(v\) is posthumous for \(s\), then \({\sim}\harm 2(v,s))\)
C2.  We are not harmed by the state of our being dead; i.e.,
\(\forall v\forall s\forall t\) (If \(\SD(v,s,t)\), then \({\sim}\harm 2(v,s))\)
C3.  The event of death harms us, if at all, only when it occurs; i.e.,
\(\forall v\forall s\forall t\) (If \(v=\ED(s) \amp \harm 3(v,s,t)\), then \(t = \T(\ED(s)))\)

Argument for C1:

Let \(v_{1}\) be any event or state, \(s_{1}\) any subject and \(t_{1}\) any time.

1.  \(v_{1}\) is posthumous for \(s_{1}\) (assumption for conditional introduction)
2.  \(\harm 2(v_{1}, s_{1})\) (assumption for reductio ad absurdum)
3.  \(\T(v_{1}) \gt \T(\ED(s_{1}))\) (1, A2, UI, biconditional elimination)
4.  \(\harm 3(v_{1}, s_{1},t)\) (2, A1, UI, biconditional elimination, MP)
5.  \(\harm 3(v_{1}\), \(s_{1}, t_{1})\) (4, EI)
6.  \(v_{1}\) affects \(s_{1}\) at \(t_{1}\) (5, P3, UI, MP)
7.  \(v_{1}\) causally affects \(s_{1}\) at \(t_{1}\) (6, P1, UI, MP)
8.  \(t_{1} \gt \T(v_{1})\) (7, P4, UI, MP)
9.  \(t_{1} \gt \T(\ED(s_{1}))\) (8, 3, transitivity of \(\gt)\)
10.  \({\sim}s_{1}\) exists at \(t_{1}\) (9, P5, UI, MP)
11.  \(s_{1}\) exists at \(t_{1}\) (7, P2, UI, MP)
12.  \({\sim}\harm 2(v_{1}, s_{1})\) (2, 10,11, reductio ad absurdum
13.  If \(v_{1}\) is posthumous for s \(_{1}\), then \({\sim}\harm 2(v_{1}, s_{1})\) (1, 13, conditional introduction)
14.  \(\forall v\forall s\)(If \(v\) is posthumous for \(s\), then \({\sim}\harm 2(v,s))\) (13 UG)

Argument for C2:

Let \(v_{1}\) be any event or state, \(s_{1}\) any subject and t \(_{1}\) any time.

1.  \(\SD(v_{1}, s_{1}, t_{1})\) (assumption for conditional introduction)
2.  \(t_{1} \gt \T(\ED(s_{1}))\) (1, A3, UI, MP))
3.  \(v_{1}\) is posthumous for \(s_{1}\) (2, A2, biconditional elimination)
4.  \({\sim}\harm 2(v_{1}, s_{1})\) (3, C1, UI, MP)
5.  If \(\SD(v_{1}, s_{1}, t_{1})\), then
\({\sim} \harm 2( v_{1}, s_{1})\)
(1, 4, CI)
6.  \(\forall v\forall s\forall t\) (If \(\SD(v,s,t)\), then \({\sim}\harm 2(v,s))\) (5, UG)

Argument for C3:

Let \(v_{1}\) be any event or state, \(s_{1}\) any subject and \(t_{1}\) any time.

1.  \(v_{1} =\ED(s_{1}) \amp \harm 3(v_{1}, s_{1},t_{1})\) (assumption for conditional introduction)
2.  \(\harm 3(\ED(s_{1}),s_{1},t_{1})\) (1, simplication, substitution)
3.  \(\ED(s_{1})\) affects \(s_{1}\) at \(t_{1}\) (2, P3, UI, MP)
4.  \(\ED(s_{1})\) causally affects \(s_{1}\) at \(t_{1}\) (3, P1, UI, MP)
5.  \(t_{1} \ge \T(\ED(s_{1}))\) (4, P4, UI, MP)
6.  \(t_{1} \gt \T(\ED(s_{1}))\) (assumption for reductio ad absurdum)
7.  \({\sim}s_{1}\) exists at \(t_{1}\) (6, P5, UI, MP)
8.  \(s_{1}\) exists at \(t_{1}\) (4, P2, UI, MP)
9.  \({\sim}t_{1} \gt \T(\ED(s_{1}))\) (6, 8, reductio ad absurdum)
10.  \(t_{1} = \T(\ED(s_{1}))\) (5, 9, disjunctive syllogism)
11.  If \(v_{1}=\ED(s_{1})\amp \harm 3(v_{1}, s_{1} , t_{1})\), then \(t_{1} =\T(\ED(s_{1}))\) (1, 10, conditional introduction)
12.  \(\forall v\forall s\forall t\) (If \(v=\ED(s) \amp \harm 3(v,s,t)\), then \(t = \T(\ED((s))\) (11, UG)

Copyright © 2019 by
Steven Luper <sluper@trinity.edu>

This is a file in the archives of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Please note that some links may no longer be functional.
[an error occurred while processing the directive]