Intersections Between Analytic and Continental Feminism

First published Tue Dec 23, 2003; substantive revision Wed Aug 22, 2018

Continental and analytic approaches to feminism differ primarily in the theoretical resources to which they appeal: analytic approaches typically take their starting point from the English-speaking world – Frege, Russell, Moore et al. – while continental approaches typically take theirs either from Germany – Hegel, Marx, the Frankfurt School et al. – or from France – Lacan, Kristeva, Saussure, Derrida et al. But feminist philosophers are rarely wedded to one tradition over the other; quite the contrary: their work presents a good case for the theoretical advantages of crossing the lines between analytic and continental philosophy and between the two branches of continental feminism. Indeed, feminists oriented by German philosophical traditions are often closer to those oriented by Anglo-American traditions than they are to those oriented by French ones. Moreover, both analytic and continental feminists look to the French philosopher, Simone de Beauvoir’s work and both find theoretical resources in the works of J.L. Austin and Michel Foucault. Although this entry distinguishes broadly analytic and broadly continental feminist traditions, it also tries to clarify intersections, overlaps and the ways in which analytic and continental feminists build on one another’s work. The entry focuses on three topics common to the two traditions: problems of who or what women are, issues pertaining to freedom and domination, and questions of epistemic injustice.

1. Defining Women

For contemporary feminists, the question of who or what women are is not easily answered. Both analytic and continental traditions find a clear articulation of the problem in Simone de Beauvoir’s 1949 book, The Second Sex where she famously claims that “One is not born, but rather becomes a woman” (1953, 281). Elizabeth Spelman’s consideration of this claim (1988) can serve as a basis for the analytic tradition’s reflections on the question of who or what women are meant to be while Judith Butler’s analysis (1990) can do the same for the continental tradition.

1.1 The Analytic Tradition

The claim that “One is not born, but rather becomes a woman” signals a distinction between sex, comprising physical and biological aspects of bodies, and gender, comprising learned behaviors, attitudes and aspirations. While this distinction is complex and controversial enough (see the entry on feminist perspectives on sex and gender) de Beauvoir’s claim also raises what are now termed intersectional issues. Spelman notes that in parts of The Second Sex de Beauvoir recognizes that if one is not born but rather becomes a woman, it is not the same to become a white woman as it is to become a black one, for example, and not the same to become a bourgeois woman as it is to become a proletarian one. Indeed, de Beauvoir bemoans the effect this difference has for women’s struggles for freedom and equality. Women “live dispersed among the males,” she writes, “attached through residence, housework, economic condition, and social standing to certain men – fathers or husbands – more firmly than they are to other women. If they belong to the bourgeoisie, they feel solidarity with men of that class, not with proletarian women; if they are white, their allegiance is to white men, not to Negro women” (1953, xix). Not only are women’s allegiances class and race bound but their classes and races can lead to tensions and conflicts. Among other observations De Beauvoir makes, Spelman notes, are that bourgeois women can be hostile to their working class male and female servants; that upper-class girls are brought up to believe in their superiority to working class men and that during the American Civil War white Southern women defended slavery even more fiercely than their male counterparts.

In other parts of The Second Sex, however, de Beauvoir ignores the consequences of intersections of gender with class and race, and talks about women in general. In this regard, Spelman points to her contrast between women, on the one hand, and proletarians, aborigines, blacks and Jews, on the other, as well as to her ascription of women’s failure historically to reject their subordinate social position to the advantages they gain from their alliance with “a superior caste.” Here de Beauvoir seems to forget that many women are proletarians, aborigines, blacks and Jews and she writes as if all women shared the same relation to the cast of white bourgeois men she calls the “superior caste”(1953, xxi). Spelman also notes the contrast de Beauvoir sets up between men defined as citizens and women depicted as wives “shut up in the home;” the way she refers appreciatively to August Bebel’s comparison of women and the proletariat in his Women under Socialism; the use she makes of Hegel’s discussion of the relationship between master and slave to describe the relationship between men and women; and her comparison of “Negro slavery” with female slavery (Spelman 1988, 64–5).

De Beauvoir’s work thus contains a contradiction in its thinking about women: Sometimes it conceives of women as a homogenous group, uniformly subordinate to men, and sometimes it conceives of women as “dispersed,” with different relations of solidarity with, and subordination to, different groups of men. Both conceptions have problems. In conceiving of women as dispersed according to race and class de Beauvoir’s work raises the question of what similarities in experience, interest or concern might underwrite feminist struggles. Sally Haslanger calls this the commonality problem (2000, 37). What experiences does a black Sudanese Muslim woman displaced by ethnic cleansing in Dafur share with the Queen of England (Mikkola 2007, 363)? What connects white middle-class women pursuing professional careers with, say, poorer women or women of color who may take over their domestic chores (Ehrenreich 2002)? Indeed, might interests in a living wage by female childcare workers not oppose interests of more privileged women in affordable day care (Collins 1998, 223)? Moreover, in conceiving of women as a homogeneous group and contrasting them to proletarians, aborigines, blacks and Jews de Beauvoir betrays her identification of women in general with a certain group of women, namely those that are not proletarian, aboriginal, black or Jewish. Haslanger calls this the normativity problem. Talk of women as a single group falsely generalizes the interests, characteristics and concerns of specific women – mainly those that are middle-class, European, white and heterosexual – and makes them the norm for all.

Kimberlé Crenshaw (1991) draws the consequences of this false generalization for combatting violence against African American women. Civil rights groups often downplay statistics about domestic violence in African American neighborhoods because they do not want to feed stereotypes about the violence of African American men. Likewise, feminists often downplay the statistics because they do not want domestic violence to appear to be simply a crime against women of color. To this extent, African American men are the norm for civil rights advocates and white women are the norm for women’s rights advocates. Women of color simply disappear from view.

In making this point, Crenshaw underscores concerns about exclusion voiced by the Combahee River Collective, founded in 1974 as well as by writers such as bell hooks (1981, 7), Aída Hurtado (1989, 849–50) and the contributors to such influential anthologies as This Bridge Called My Back (Moraga and Anzaldua 1981) and All the Women Are White, All the Blacks Are Men, But Some of Us Are Brave: Black Women’s Studies (Hull, Scott and Smith 1982). These concerns cannot be accommodated by what Chandra Mohanty calls the “add and stir” approach (2003, 518), which tries to counter the exclusion of many women but still takes the experiences of white European heterosexual women as the base while mixing in the experiences of others, say, Indonesian Nike workers, as if they were mere seasoning. Nor can the concerns be accommodated by taking Indonesian Nike workers as normative for non-Western women any more than the concerns of mid-twentieth century Parisian women can be taken as normative for Western ones (2003, 34).

Given the commonality and normativity problems, what happens to the possibility of talking about women in general or taking up feminist goals of women’s equality and liberation? If women differ in their experiences, concerns and aims and if talk of women in general falsely generalizes the experiences, concerns and aims of only a small group of them, why talk of women at all? Recognition of the myriad intersections that subdivide the identity of women continues to expand while challenges to speaking of women as a whole include issues not only of class, race, sexuality and the like but also of issues of disability, cisgender and so on. (See Hall 2015; Bettcher and Garry 2009). Is it possible to balance diversity and interconnection or does the need to recognize discrete identities dismantle all bases of solidarity? (See McCall 2005).

Ann Garry (2011) looks to a Wittgensteinian family resemblance analysis. We can give up on the existence of some property, experience, or interest that all women share without giving up on overlapping and crisscrossing characteristics that become clear within specific social contexts. For her part, Haslanger proposes an “ameliorative” concept of women, one that can help with attempts to end sexist oppression. If gender cannot be defined in terms of characteristics or concerns common to members of a particular gender, she thinks it can nonetheless be defined “in terms of how one is socially positioned, where this is a function of, e.g., how one is viewed, how one is treated, and how one’s life is structured socially, legally, and economically.” On this account, gender categories represent hierarchical relations in which one group maintains a subordinate relation to another and the difference between the two groups is marked by “sexual difference” (2000, 38). Thus:

S is a woman iffdf S is systematically subordinated along some dimension (economic, legal, political, social, etc.) and S is “marked” as a target for this treatment by observed or imagined bodily features presumed to be evidence of a female’s biological role in reproduction (2000, 39).

Haslanger acknowledges that this definition excludes some we might intuitively think of as women such as women of inordinate privilege who are not marked for subordination by their observed or imagined bodily features. Nevertheless, she thinks that if we tailor our definition to the feminist purposes of overcoming subordination these “women” are not the ones who matter (2000, 46).

Yet Mari Mikkola (2009) claims that the confusion Haslanger’s terms would create by excluding many commonly defined as women “is unlikely to help in the task of challenging existing social conditions.” For her part, Katharine Jenkins (2016) thinks the definition excludes some trans women. Indeed, she argues it probably includes only those trans women whose gender presentation is respected because they are perceived as possessing bodily features associated with a female’s role in reproduction and hence are perceived as either cisgender or as having undergone medical interventions that have altered some of their bodily features so that they now are understood as the same sort of features cis women possess (400). According to Jenkins, Haslanger’s ameliorative project can be rescued by considering gender in terms not only of class, as Haslanger does in talking about gender, but also as identity, as Haslanger does in talking about race. Here gender and racial identities involve navigating the norms associated with those identities. There are thus two concepts that need to be the focus of an ameliorative inquiry: being classed as a woman and having a female gender identity (415–6).

1.2 The Continental Tradition

The concern with which Butler opens her 1990 and now-classic book, Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity, is the relation between construction and representation. As a political movement, feminism supposes that it represents a set of pre-existing subjects, namely women, who are uniformly oppressed by a uniform patriarchy. Yet if we follow Foucault, we have to ask who these pre-existing subjects are. More specifically, if we return to de Beauvoir’s claim that “One is not born, but rather becomes a women” we have to ask who or what it is that becomes a woman. It is misleading to think of oppression in terms of structures of power over against the subjects that precede them because subjects, as the particular subjects they are, are first constituted through specific authorizations “through the forms of power that regulate, control, represent and protect them.” Hence, “the juridical formation of language and politics that represents women as ‘the subject’ of feminism is itself a discursive formation and effect of a given version of representational politics” (1990, 2). While de Beauvoir’s claim assumes a pre-existing female sexed person who acquires the attitudes, behaviors and aspirations of a feminine gender through socialization, Butler maintains that it is through regimes of gender that we first conceive of bodies as sexed. “Gender is … the discursive/cultural means by which ‘sexed nature’ or ‘a natural sex’ is produced and established as ‘prediscursive’” (1990, 7). This discursive formation of both gender and sex is not only inevitably exclusionary and not only “the mark imposed by the oppressor” (Wittig 1992, 11) but also inconsistent and incoherent both across different historical contexts (see Riley 1988) and in relation to race, class, sexual identities and so on.

As Butler points out, Luce Irigaray (1985) complicates matters further. Here Irigaray’s reference is de Beauvoir’s claim that a woman “is defined and differentiated with reference to man and not he with reference to her; she is the incidental, the inessential as opposed to the essential. He is the Subject, he is the Absolute – she is the Other” (1953, 13). De Beauvoir insists that there is no time in history in which women were not the Other: men are always the One and women are always the Other. Moreover, as the Other, they live only in relation to the One and have no free human existence or subjectivity on their own. They occupy space in a man’s world only as relative and inessential aspects of it. Yet Irigaray explains that if women are the Other to men they cannot be defined independently of a definition of men. To define women as the Other of men is to articulate their identity within a vocabulary that takes men as its norm. But if they cannot be defined independently of men, how are they be Other from them? If women can be articulated only within a male-normed language, then language cannot get at their otherness at all. They are always, instead, part of a language system expressing the One. The “exclusion” of women, Irigaray writes, “is internal to an order from which nothing escapes: the order of (man’s) discourse. To the objection that this discourse is perhaps not all there is, the response will be that it is women who are ‘not-all’” (1985, 88). Julia Kristeva agrees. “A woman cannot be,” she writes. “It is something which does not even belong in the order of being” (1981, 137). If women disappear into various nodes of intersectionality in the analytic tradition, in the continental they cannot be thought in the first place.

Is there any way to rescue them? Butler is not wedded to the idea that we need a stable conception of women. Rather, she wonders whether we should entertain “a radical critique that seeks to free feminist theory from the necessity of having to construct a single or abiding ground,” and she asks whether “the construction of the category of women as a coherent and stable subject” is “an unwitting regulation and reification of gender relations” (1990, 5). Other feminists making use of continental sources are less sure about this conclusion. Iris Marion Young (1994) turns to Jean-Paul Sartre’s distinction between a series and a group. For Sartre, a group is a collection of people who consciously undertake a common project together where the project typically is one best taken up by this sort of group (1994, 724). Storming the Bastille is an example. In contrast, a series is less organized and not at all self-conscious; here the example is people waiting for a bus. These individuals possess a common interest in traveling along a certain route, but they have, or need have, no direct relation to one another. This series could become a group were individuals within it to start complaining about the length of time they wait for the bus, and they could undertake together some sort of collective protest. Nonetheless, without this move toward collective action, they remain isolated from one another and focused on the bus, which Sartre and Young call a practico-inert reality, rather than on each other.

Women, for Young, are a series, where one practico-inert reality is an effect of a compulsory heterosexuality that focuses on the features of a body connected to sexual reproduction. Other practico-inert realities include pronouns, verbal and visual representations, clothes, cosmetics, social spaces, and spaces associated with the sexual division of work and other activities. In each case, these realities describe structures or objects to which individuals relate themselves serially, as they relate themselves to a bus. Conceiving of women as a series thus allows for the sense in which they share certain features but in which they can also possess striking differences in their relation to the realities that make them part of that series. Women are “a serial collective defined neither by any common identity nor by a common set of attributes that all individual in the series share” (1994, 737).

In another attempt to rescue women, Linda Martín Alcoff (2005) appeals to Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Hans-Georg Gadamer to anchor women’s identity in embodiment. Bodies and bodily experiences differ for men and women. These differences can stem from cultural practices that promote different ways of moving, siting, standing, running, speaking, and throwing a ball, for instance. Moreover, because of differences in physical strength, men and women also approach the same task differently, using different parts of their bodies to do the same things. Finally, in distinction from men, women’s bodily experiences include the “experience of breasts, menses, lactation and pregnancy” (Alcoff 2005, 106). For Alcoff, these differences lead to differences in women’s orientations or what, following Gadamer, she calls horizons on themselves and their world. Alcoff does not deny that these horizons vary according to the traditions and cultures to which various women belong; nor does she deny that horizons also vary according to intersections with other factors, such as race and class. At the same time, she argues, “The possibility of pregnancy, childbirth, nursing, and in many societies, rape are parts of females’ horizons … and they exist there because of the ways we are embodied” (2005, 176). Yet, Stephanie Julia Kapusta (2016) questions Alcoff’s emphasis on biological differences and pregnancy given the way in which it can marginalize and inflict psychological, moral, or political harms on certain individuals, including trans people. Georgia Warnke (2007) proposes a different hermeneutic approach. Identities, she claims, are interpretations of, or ways of understanding, who we and others are. As such they necessarily comply with the conditions of understanding: they are culturally and historically situated, motivated by particular concerns and interests and inevitably partial. We can thus understand people as women in particular contexts without requiring their identities or commonalities to extend beyond them. Lauren Barthold (2016) takes up both Alcoff’s and Warnke’s accounts to conceive of women’s identity in Gadamerian terms as a dialogic one.

1.3 Conclusion

In de Beauvoir’s work, both broadly analytic and broadly continental feminist approaches find resources for raising questions about who women are, how they might be defined and for what purposes. Both approaches are interested in developing a definition of women that is inclusive, sensitive to intersecting oppressions and useful to feminist struggles. There are affinities in some of the ways theorists in each tradition try to accomplish these goals: for example between Garry’s appeal to family resemblances and Young’s appeal to series that can become groups. Critics within each tradition also overlap in questioning the exclusions proffered definitions involve.

2. Freedom and Domination

With regard to questions of freedom and domination, the distinction between continental feminists in the (French) post-structuralist tradition and those in the (German) tradition of critical theory is perhaps more pronounced than that between the latter and those in the analytic tradition.

2.1 The Continental Tradition

Butler (1990) begins her analysis by returning to Irigaray and Kristeva’s criticism of de Beauvoir and arguing that their insights into the closed nature of a gendered linguistic system raise issues about a substance-accident metaphysics as a whole. According to this metaphysics, both sex and gender are meant to be accidental attributes attached to a substantial subject. One is essentially a subject and only accidentally a male or female, masculine or feminine one. Yet, if women can be defined only in terms of men, as the Other of men, then sex and gender are not as much accidents as they are relations – not attributes a subject possesses but oppositions between linguistic terms: male versus female and masculine versus feminine. Furthermore, if sex and gender are not attributes, perhaps we should rethink the subject or substance to which they are meant to attach. Perhaps there is only language which, in articulating a relation between male and female, masculine and feminine, posits a substance on which to erect those terms. Butler quotes Michel Haar’s commentary on Nietzsche:

All psychological categories (the ego, the individual, the person) derive from the illusion of substantial identity. But this illusion goes back basically to a superstition that deceives not only common sense but also philosophers – namely, the belief in language and, more precisely, in the truth of grammatical categories (1977, 17–8).

In other words, language inspires us to add substantial identities to actions because verbs need subjects. Turning from Nietzsche to J.L. Austin, Butler conceives of women (and men) as “performatives.” Performative speech acts for Austin are utterances such as “the meeting is now open” or “I now pronounce you husband and wife” in which, uttered under appropriate circumstances, the speech act does something by saying something. The speech act thus brings a state of affairs into existence. Likewise, according to Butler, the language of sex and gender, appropriately institutionalized, creates men and women.

What is meant by appropriately institutionalized? For Foucault (1978) the most important sites of power lie in everyday social practices such as social work, medicine and psychiatry, in scientific and social scientific disciplines that type individuals and create categories of identity, and in institutions such as prisons, schools and hospitals. Such power is productive: social institutions and practices create modern identities such as gays, “blacks,” and manic-depressives. For Butler and others, the construction of men and women takes a similar path, as the result of compulsory heterosexuality. As a form of power, compulsory heterosexuality imposes a set of norms about how and whom we should desire and establishes a set of sanctions from this set. By doing so, it divides human populations into two genders that are in turn supposed to be connected to two sexes with two directions of sexual desire. Thus, one is a man with a male body and a desire for women or one is a woman with a female body and a desire for men. “The heterosexualization of desire,” Butler writes, “requires and institutes the production of discrete and asymmetrical oppositions between ‘feminine’ and ‘masculine,’ where these are understood as expressive attributes of ‘male’ and ‘female’” (1990, 17).

This account of identities as effects of power is obviously skeptical of our capacities for critical agency and rational reflection to which Marxists and other social critics have traditionally appealed for a purchase on relations of power and subordination. If the subject, as a woman or gay person for example, is an effect of power, the structure of oppression is already built into the identity. How can women or gay people be agents for the emancipation of, or equal justice for, women or gay people if their identity is itself an effect of unequal power relations? Indeed, if we become subjects at all only within everyday disciplinary practices, then subjects are always already effects of power. To emancipate ourselves from power would be to emancipate ourselves from ourselves. How then are we to address issues of freedom and autonomy? Butler looks to resignification. Power not only produces but reproduces itself and this constant production and reproduction serves as the opening for “resignification, redeployment, subversive citation from within, and interruption and inadvertent convergences with other [power/discourse] networks” (1995, 135). Yet other continental feminists find this approach unsatisfying. Nancy Fraser finds the positive connotations that Butler associates with resignification “puzzling.” “Why,” she asks, “is resignification good? Can’t there be bad (oppressive, reactionary) resignifications?”(1995, 67–8). If all subjectivity is a construction of power/discourse networks, why should we not simply be content with the subjects that our current disciplinary practices enforce? Or, if some resignifications are good, which ones? How do we determine which sort we should endorse?

In general, Fraser thinks feminists too eagerly turned to poststructuralist theories in the 1990s and that this turn has consequences: not only does it leave women with no prospects for change other than resignification but it also reduces gender inequality to a matter of language and culture and neglects socio-economic issues such as female poverty (2013). Here her criticism is directed at what she calls Lacanianism in feminism. The work of Lacanian feminists has some merit, she says, in that it shows gender to be a discursive construction. Sexual identity is based on the process of identification, language, and socialization in which the child enters into the symbolic order, governed by the incest taboo or what Lacan calls “the law of the Father.” Subjugation to that law and becoming a subject are thus one and the same. Given the law’s phallocentric tilt, women are pretty much condemned. Nevertheless this analysis remains too historically unspecific for Fraser. What we need from discourse theory, she maintains, are insights into how our social identities are formed and altered over time, how social groups form and disintegrate, how dominant groups retain their cultural dominance and what the prospects are for emancipatory change.

Seyla Benhabib (1995), Amy Allen (2008) and Allison Weir (2013) also question equations between identity, law and power. Benhabib distinguishes between a stronger and a weaker version of the claim that identities such as women and gay people are constructions of power (1995, 20). The stronger version insists that subjects are entirely the effects of power, particularly of a compulsory heterosexuality, and that as effects they can only accept their mode of being a subject or try to subvert it from within. A weaker version of the claim, however, would simply emphasize that infants are born into a world of existing gendered relations, hierarchies and distributions of power and are acculturated into this world by parents, teachers and the like. To say that infants are born into prevailing structures of power, however, is not to say that they are already entirely constituted by them. Hence, Benhabib claims, there remain capacities for reflection and accountability that are not simply themselves effects of power. While more sympathetic to Foucault and Butler, Allen uses Jessica Benjamin’s (1988) account of recognition to make a similar point. There may be “no outside to power, in the sense that there is no possible human social world from which power has been completely eliminated.” Nevertheless, we need not deny “moments of mutual recognition…within ongoing, dynamically unfolding, social relationships” that can provide for both the constitution of autonomous selves and a reference point for social and political critique (2008, 91). Weir likewise stresses relations of recognition, as well as of “identification, of flourishing, of meaning, of love, of different kinds of power, including empowerment and solidarity” (2013, 91). Again, resistance to domination is not just a matter of resignifying within oppressive structures. Rather it is a matter of transforming women. Indeed, she asks “What have we been doing in our women’s studies programs, associations of feminist philosophers and academics, feminist movements, lesbian communities, women’s cooperative, and culture building and other alternative communities if we haven’t been …producing women as something other than subjected?” (2013, 94).

2.1 The Analytic Tradition

Working from an Anglo-American liberal tradition, Martha Nussbaum has raised questions similar to those that Allen, Benhabib, Fraser and Weir raise about a post-structuralist feminism. Indeed, she thinks the latter is irretrievably self-involved and needs to be rejected in favor of the kind of theoretical and practical work that can end oppressive practices and institutions (1999a). Her own starting point is what she calls the “capabilities approach,” an approach that is rooted in “respect for the dignity of persons as choosers” (2000, 71–2) and that asks what individuals within a given society are able to do and to be – what their capabilities or freedoms are. Following Rawls here Nussbaum focuses on the distribution of resources and opportunities within a country or political entity. Like Amartya Sen, she adds to Rawls’ view, first, the question of what individuals’ needs for resources are and, second, the question of how they are able to convert these resources into human functionings (1999, 34). By human functionings, Nussbaum means the realization of one or more capability – the enjoyment of good health, for example. She is interested in both the basic functionings, without which we would not regard a life as human or fully human, and the less basic functionings, without which we would not regard a human life as flourishing.

The “we” here is not meant to be ethnocentric. The claim is, rather, that a just society provides individuals with capabilities for human functionings where the idea of the important capabiliities is one to which people from different traditions with different conceptions of the good could agree as necessary to the pursuit of their conception. This idea provides a checklist of capabilities against which to measure forms of oppression and discrimination in particular countries. Thus, inequalities based on gender hierarchies as well as practices such as female genital mutilation will be precluded and a defense of such practices as part of the cultural tradition will not work. If cultural tradition confines women to the house, even if widowed and without means of support, then such practices are to be condemned as violating capabilities for even basic functioning. Indeed, while egregious practices such as female genital mutilation and female confinement violate capabilities for life, nutrition and bodily integrity, all inequalities based on gender hierarchies, in Nussbaum’s view, undermine capabilities for self-respect and emotional development that are part of human functioning. Ultimately, Nussbaum’s concerns are the same as Fraser’s: that a focus on genealogy and resignification cannot do the work of undoing the social, political and economic discrimination that women suffer in far too many cultures and countries and that it is this discrimination that feminism must try to combat.

Other feminists have concerns about Nussbaum’s approach, however. Susan Moller Okin objects to the narrative approach that Nussbaum introduces in Women and Human Development insofar as it relies on retelling the experiences of two poor Indian women, Vasanti and Jayamma. Okin points out that despite the sort of cross-cultural dialogue in which Nussbaum thinks feminists should engage (Nussbaum 2000, 7), she rarely quotes these women directly and refracts their views through her own (Okin 2003, 295). From where, then, does Nussbaum’s checklist of capabilities come? Okin calls her idea of a fully human life “highly intellectualized” and maintains that the capacities central to it “seem to derive far more from an Aristotelian ideal than from any deep or broad familiarity with the lives of women in the less developed world” (203, 296). Likewise, while Alison Jagger thinks the narrative approach may be anodyne as long as it is meant simply heuristically, she argues that there is little evidence that Nussbaum’s list of capabilities reflects anything like a consensus or even overlapping consensus of “people across the world who are reasonably well-informed and uncoerced” (2006, 313). Rather, in spite of a long list of interlocutors, Jagger thinks Nussbaum pays insufficient attention to questions of inclusiveness and representation.

2.3 Conclusion

Feminists in both the analytic and continental traditions raise concerns about a post-structuralist identification of the subject, including the feminist subject, with power. If women, like gay people and others, are the effects of discourses of power how can they also be the agents of their own emancipation? Some feminists find this question to be so removed from the horrific lives many women live as to be farcical. For example, Nussbaum asks that we attend to capacities and functionings and Fraser likewise insists that we move away from what she sees as purely cultural concerns to socio-economic ones. Others try to secure theoretical grounds for agency and autonomy outside of power.

3. Epistemic Injustice

Feminism has an obvious relation to epistemology insofar as it must justify the legitimacy of its claims and the credibility of those making them. Miranda Fricker’s book, Epistemic Injustice: Power and Ethics of Knowing (2007) has grounded much of the current discussion in the analytic tradition, which has largely focused on cataloguing and categorizing instances of epistemic injustice. The continental tradition traces this issue back to concerns with ideology and power/knowledge regimes that have long been a part of emancipatory discussions.

3.1 The Analytic Tradition

Fricker takes up two varieties of epistemic injustice: testimonial and hermeneutical. Her account of the former can be seen as a development of claims Jennifer Hornsby and Rae Langton (1998) made about silencing with reference to Catharine MacKinnon’s claim that pornography interferes with women’s freedom of speech (1993). Freedom of speech involves not simply the ability to make claims but, more importantly, the ability to have illocutionary effects in which one’s audience takes up those claims. MacKinnon focuses on the ability to refuse sex by saying no. Under the influence of pornography one’s audience may not recognize what one is trying to do with one’s words and may fail to take this no as a refusal. For Fricker, structural identity prejudices in general affect one’s credibility as a speaker and conveyor of knowledge. Her example is the way, in the screenplay of “The Talented Mr. Ripley,” Marge Sherwood is unable to communicate her suspicions about Ripley to her father-in-law, Herbert Greenleaf, because of the identity prejudices he holds about women. Assuming that women tend to respond emotionally instead of rationally to a situation, he downgrades her credibility and effectively silences her. The testimonial injustice here excludes Sherwood from the social practice of pooling information.

Kristie Dotson (2011) distinguishes two different kinds of silencing practices: testimonial quieting and testimonial smothering. While testimonial quieting characterizes a failure to recognize the speaker as a knower and thus to offer the speaker appropriate uptake, Dotson describes testimonial smothering as a coerced truncation by speakers of their own testimony. Speakers recognize that their audiences are unwilling or unable to offer appropriate uptake to their testimony, and in response, limit and shape their testimony in order to “insure that the testimony contains only content for which one’s audience demonstrates testimonial competence” (2011, 244). Dotson characterizes both of these silencing practices as forms of epistemic violence, and both have dramatic effects for the epistemic pursuits of individuals and communities alike.

With regard to hermeneutical injustice, Fricker focuses on gaps in the collective hermeneutical resources that make it difficult for members of particular groups, including women, to make sense out of and articulate important areas of their experience. The available resources are either not adequate for expressing these areas of experience or they are misleading. Where this failure or inadequacy affects people differentially it is unjust, Fricker argues. As an example she points to the damage done to many women’s lives and careers after they suffered unwanted sexual advances on the job before sexual harassment was a hermeneutical resource available to make sense out of their experience (2007, 152). Fricker thinks it would be a mistake to see this gap in the collective hermeneutic resources as merely bad timing, as might be the case if one suffered from a disease that had not yet been diagnosed or understood. Rather, to the extent that the gap affected women and their sexual harassers differentially it led to an injustice. It also derived from one. Fricker argues that the hermeneutical gap was the result of “unequal hermeneutical participation” in which women were left out of or barred from engaging in the formation of the relevant collective understandings (Fricker 2007: 152). This marginalization, she argues, results from a combination of two forms of power: identity power that downgrades a speaker’s credibility and material power. In a social world in which men have more power than women, men also have more say over defining what experiences mean and the result is to render “the collective hermeneutical resource structurally prejudiced” (2007, 154–5).

Shelley Tremain (2017) finds a problem with Fricker’s distinction between hermeneutical gaps due to diseases not yet diagnosed and hermeneutical gaps that reflect hermeneutical injustice. While Fricker wants to see the former as a case of mere bad luck, Tremain points to the lack of hermeneutical resources many disabled people suffer because of social, cultural and political norms that are as inadequate and misleading as those distorting attempts to articulate the experience of sexual harassment. As she writes, “Until the relatively recent formation and rise of ‘the mad pride movement’ and related social movements, the hermeneutical resources that such disabled people required in order to collectively understand the political character of their situation were unavailable to them” (178).

Other feminists add to Fricker’s account of hermeneutical injustice just as they do to her account of testimonial injustice. Following up on Charles Mills’ account of white ignorance (1998), Gaile Pohlhaus, Jr. (2012), for example, conceives of the consequence of this structural prejudice as a willful hermeneutical ignorance in which “dominantly situated knowers…continue to misunderstand and misinterpret the world” (2012, 716). Dotson uses this idea of willful hermeneutical ignorance to identify a third feature of epistemic injustice along with testimonial and hermeneutical injustice: namely contributory injustice in which willful hermeneutical ignorance compromises a speaker’s epistemic agency and obstructs the capacity to contribute to a community’s collective hermeneutical resources (2012, 31). Fricker now distinguishes between “in-group intelligibility” within marginalized groups and their “frustratingly failed attempts to communicate” (2016, 167) with dominant groups.

3.2 The Continental Tradition

Fricker’s solution to epistemic injustice looks to a sort of virtuous listening that can undo prejudiced judgments of credibility. Feminists in the continental tradition appreciate her work but try to go beyond dyadic instances of epistemic injustice. Allen (2017) makes three recommendations. First, we can look at what Jose Medina “complex histories and chains of social interactions that go beyond particular pairs and clusters of subjects” (Medina 2013, 60). Second, we can look at Foucault’s account of power/knowledge regimes for a robust account of collective hermeneutical resources and the exclusions they enforce as well of the institutional mechanisms that determine what is and is not to count as knowledge and who is and who is not to count as a knower. Finally, we can look at Foucault’s development of genealogy as a form of critique that allows for the disruption of epistemic hierarchies that may be inherited but that are nonetheless contingent.

Feminists in the continental tradition also look to the Marxist tradition and to Habermas, conceiving of structural prejudice in the collective hermeneutical resources as the sort of ideological obfuscation that undermines a society’s capacity to understand its own creations. Thus, Habermas points to the power-relations our hermeneutical resources include and asks us not to forget that “the background consensus of established traditions … can be a consciousness forged of compulsions.” (1977, 358–9). (Also see Mills (2017.) Habermas’s early work focused on psychoanalysis as a model for a critical social theory but he later turned to a reconstructive science of communicative competence and to the possibilities of deliberative forms of democracy. Deliberative democratic theory looks to non-coercive exchanges of arguments among free and equal citizens who justify their claims and proposals by appealing to considerations that can be accepted by all those affected (1998, 458). Benhabib (1996a) thus insists that only those norms are valid that are agreed to in deliberations that have the following features:
1) participation in such deliberation is governed by norms of equality and symmetry; all have the same chances to initiate speech acts, to question, to interrogate, and to open debate; 2) all have the right to question the assigned topics of conversation; and 3) all have the right to initiate reflexive arguments about the very rules of the discourse procedure and the way in which they are applied or carried out (70).

Other feminists have sought an expanded version of deliberative theory that can take what they see as better account of impediments to the participation of women and other marginalized groups. Thus, Young substitutes communicative for deliberative democracy in order to expand the scope of considerations beyond the exchange of reasons to include story-telling as well as argumentation on grounds close to Fricker’s and Dotson’s concerns: namely that power relations can stifle speech (1996, 123). Likewise Simone Chambers looks to a melding of deliberative and diversity theory (2003, 322) while Noelle McAfee (2008) looks beyond a Habermasian proceduralism to an integrative model of public deliberation that respects the importance of multiple, partial views.

3.3 Conclusion

The concept of epistemic injustice has proved a fruitful one for feminists, as for critical race theorists, disability theorists and others. Those in the analytic tradition have focused on mapping its contours, nailing down the precise form of injustice it involves and exposing forms of socially positioned ignorance in which dominant groups continue to misapprehend the world. Those in the continental tradition conceive of such ignorance as ideology and, like those in the analytic tradition, understand it as a mechanism of both distortion and silencing. They have also probed the conditions for forms of public communication and discourse free of coercion. Moving on from Fricker’s work, feminists in both analytic and continental traditions remain interested in expanding the concept of epistemic injustice beyond dyadic relations to examine is systemic reach and consequences.

4. General Conclusion

Analytic and continental feminists share interests in avoiding exclusion in attempts to define women, in overcoming patriarchal forms of oppression and in securing the claims of women to know and to participate in epistemic projects. Analytic and continental feminists sometimes pursue these interests in different ways, sometimes in similar ways and sometimes in conversation with one another. Collectively they take up and further develop a rich history of liberal, Marxist, post-structuralist, hermeneutic and linguistic thought.

Bibliography

  • Alcoff, Linda Martín, 2005, Visible Identities: Race, Gender, and the Self, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Allen, Amy, 2000, “Power/Knowledge/Resistance: Foucault and Epistemic Injustice,” in Kidd, Ian James et al. (eds.) The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice,
  • –––, 2008, The Politics of Our Selves: Power, Autonomy, and Gender in Contemporary Critical Theory, New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Barthold, Lauren Swayne, 2016, A Hermeneutic Approach to Gender and Other Social Identities, New York: Palgrave MacMillan.
  • Benhabib, Seyla, 1996a, “Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy,” in S. Benhabib (ed.) 1996b.
  • ––– (ed.), 1996b, Democracy and Difference, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Benhabib, Seyla, Judith Butler, Drucilla Cornell, Nancy Fraser, 1995, Feminist Contentions: A Philosophical Exchange, New York: Routledge.
  • Benjamin, Jessica, 1988, The Bonds of Love: Psychoanalysis, Feminism and the Problem of Domination, New York: Pantheon Books.
  • Bettcher, Talia Mae and Ann Garry, 2009, Transgender Studies and Feminism: Theory, Politics, and Gender Realities, special issue of Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy, 24(3).
  • Butler, Judith, 1990, Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity, New York: Routledge.
  • –––, 2004, Undoing Gender, New York: Routledge.
  • Chambers, Simone, 2003, “Deliberative Democratic Theory,” in The Annual Review of Political Science, 6: 307–26,
  • Collins, Patricia Hill, 1998, Fighting Words: Black Women and the Search for Justice, Minneapolis MN.: University of Minnesota Press.
  • Crenshaw, Kimberlé, 1991, “Mapping the Margins: Intersectionality, Identity Politics and Violence Against Women,” in The Stanford Law Review, 43(6): 1241–1299.
  • De Beauvoir, Simone, 1953, The Second Sex, H.M. Parshley (trans. and ed.), New York: Knopf.
  • Dotson, Kristie, 2011, “Tracking Epistemic Violence, Tracking Practices of Silencing,” in Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy, 26(2): 237–57.
  • –––, 2012, “A Cautionary Tale: On Limiting Epistemic Oppression,” in Frontiers: A Journal of Women Studies, 33(1): 24–47.
  • –––, 2014, “Conceptualizing Epistemic Oppression,” in Social Epistemology, 28(2): 115–138.
  • Ehrenreich, Nancy, 2002, “Subordination and Symbiosis: Mechanisms of Mutual Support between Subordinating Systems,” in University of Missouri-Kansas City Law Review, 71: 251–324.
  • Fraser, Nancy, 1997, “False Antitheses: A Response to Seyla Benhabib and Judith Butler,” in Nancy Fraser, Justice Interruptus: Critical Reflections on the “Postsocialist” Condition, New York: Routledge.
  • –––, 2013, Fortunes of Feminism: From Women’s Liberation to Identity Politics to Anti-Capitalism, New York: Verso.
  • Fricker, Miranda, 2007, Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2016, “Epistemic Injustice and the Preservation of Ignorance,” in Rik Peels and Martijn Blaauw (eds.) The Epistemic Dimensions of Ignorance, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Foucault, Michel, 1978, The History of Sexuality (Volume 1), Robert Hurley (trans.), New York: Pantheon Books.
  • Garry, Ann, 2011, “Intersectionality, Metaphors, and the Multiplicity of Gender,” in Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy, 26(4): 826–850.
  • Haar, Michel, 1977, “Nietzsche and Metaphysical Language,” in The New Nietzsche: Contemporary Styles of Interpretation, David Allison (ed.), New York: Delta.
  • Habermas, Jürgen, 1977, “A Review of Truth and Method,” in Understanding and Social Inquiry, Fred Dallmayr and Thomas McCarthy (eds.), Notre Dame, IN: The University of Notre Dame Press.
  • –––, 1998, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy and Norms, William Rehg (trans.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Hall, Kim Q., 2015, New Conversations in Feminist Disability Studies, special issue of Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy, 30(1).
  • Haslanger, Sally, 2000, “Gender and Race: (What) Are They? (What) Do We Want Them To Be?,” in Noûs, 34(1): 31–55.
  • –––, 2012, Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • hooks, bell, 1981, Ain’t I a Woman: Black Women and Feminism, Boston: South End Press.
  • Hornsby, Jennifer and Rae Langton, 1998, “Free Speech and Illocution,” in Legal Theory, 4(1): 21–37.
  • Hull, Gloria T., Patricia Bell Scott and Barbara Smith (eds.), 1982, All the Women Are White, All the Blacks Are Men, But Some of Us Are Brave: Black Women’s Studies, Old Westbury, NY: Feminist Press.
  • Hurtado, Aída, 1989, “Relating to Privilege: Seduction and Rejection in the Subordination of White Women and Women of Color,” in Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, 14(4): 833–855.
  • Irigaray, Luce, 1985, “The Power of Discourse and the Subordination of the Feminine,” in Luce Irigaray, This Sex Which Is Not One, Catherine Porter (trans.) Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Jaggar, Alison M., 2006, “Reasoning About Well-Being: Nussbaum’s Methods of Justifying the Capabilities,” in The Journal of Political Philosophy, 14(3): 301–22.
  • Jenkins, Katharine, 2016, “Amelioration and Inclusion: Gender Identity and the Concept of Woman,” in Ethics, 126(2): 394–421.
  • Kidd, Ian James, José Medina, and Gaile Pohlhaus, Jr. (eds.), 2017, The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice, New York: Routledge
  • Kristeva, Julia, 1981, “Women Can Never Be Defined,” in New French Feminisms, Elaine Marks and Isabelle de Courtivron (eds.) New York: Schocken Books.
  • MacKinnon, Catharine, 1993, Only Words, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
  • McAfee, Noelle, 2008, Democracy and the Political Unconscious, New York: Columbia University Press.
  • McCall, Leslie, 2005, “The Complexity of Intersectionality,” in Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, 30(3): 1771–800.
  • Medina, José, 2013, The Epistemology of Resistance: Gender and Racial Oppression, Epistemic Injustice, and Resistant Imaginations, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Mikkola, Mari, 2009, “Gender Concepts and Intuitions,” in Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 39(4): 559–583.
  • Mills, Charles, 1998, Blackness Visible: Essays on Philosophy and Race, Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 2017, “Ideology,” in Ian James Kidd, et al. (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice, London: Routledge.
  • Mohanty, Chandra Talpade, 2003, “‘Under Western Eyes’ Revisited: Feminist Solidarity through Anticapitalist Struggles,” in Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, 28(2): 499–535.
  • Moraga, Cherrie and Gloria Anzaldua (eds.), 1981, This Bridge Called My Back: Writings by Radical Women of Color, New York: Kitchen Table: Women of Color Press.
  • Nussbaum, Martha C., 1999, “Women and Cultural Universals,” in Martha Nussbaum, Sex and Social Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 1999a, “The Professor of Parody: The Hip Defeatism of Judith Butler,” in The New Republic, February 22, 1999, 45–48.
  • –––, 2000, Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Okin, Susan Moller, 2003, “Poverty, Well-Being, and Gender: What Counts, Who’s Heard?,” in Philosophy & Public Affairs, 31(3): 280–316.
  • Pohlhaus, Gaile Jr., 2011, “Relational Knowing and Epistemic Injustice: Toward a Theory of Willful Hermeneutical Ignorance,” in Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy, 27(4): 715–735.
  • Riley, Denise, 1988, Am I that Name: Feminism and the Category of Women in History, Minneapolis MN: University of Minnesota Press.
  • Scott, Joan Wallach, 1988, Gender and the Politics of History, New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Spelman, Elizabeth, 1988, Inessential Woman: Problems of Exclusion in Feminist Thought, Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
  • Tremain, Shelley, 2017, “Knowing Disability, Differently,” in Ian James Kidd, et al. (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice, London: Routledge.
  • Warnke, Georgia, 2007, After Identity: Rethinking Race, Sex and Gender, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2014, “Hermeneutics and Feminism,” in The Routledge Companion to Hermeneutics, Jeff Malpas and Hans-Helmuth Gander (eds.), New York: Routledge.
  • Witt, Charlotte, 2011, Metaphysics of Gender, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Weir, Allison, 2013, Identities and Freedom: Feminist Theory Between Power and Connection, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Wendell, S., 1997, The Rejected Body. Feminist Philosophical Reflections on Disability, New York: Routledge.
  • Wittig, Monique, 1997, “One is Not Born a Woman,” in The Second Wave: A Reader in Feminist Theory, Linda Nicholson (ed.), New York: Routledge.
  • Young, Iris Marion, 1994, “Gender as Seriality: Thinking about Women as a Social Collective,” in Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, 19(3): 713–38.

Other Internet Resources

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Copyright © 2018 by
Georgia Warnke <georgia.warnke@ucr.edu>

This is a file in the archives of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Please note that some links may no longer be functional.
[an error occurred while processing the directive]