Mental Disorder (Illness)
Mental disorder (earlier entitled “illness” or “disease”) is ascribed to deviations from normal thoughts, reasoning, feelings, attitudes, and actions that are considered socially or personally dysfunctional and apt for treatment. Schizophrenia, depression, and bipolar disorder are core examples. The concept of mental disorder plays a role in many domains, including medicine, social sciences such as psychology and anthropology, and the humanities, including literature and philosophy. Philosophical discussions are the primary focus of the present entry, which differs from the entry on Philosophy of Psychiatry in noting several different approaches—not only those of the philosophy of science and mind, but also those arising from phenomenology and social theory.
Mental disorder is a widely contested concept and there are longstanding debates on whether disorders are biological or social in nature. Even uncontroversial disorders, such as those listed above, were not always regarded as disorders in the past (Porter 2002). Moreover, the status of mental disorder has frequently indicated ethical, as much as other deficiency (Irwin 2013). Such reminders direct our attention to contemporary medical psychiatry’s sometimes uncompromisingly neurobiological, and avowedly value-free “medical model”, with its incumbent analogies and assumptions, and to the general question of how the taxa of psychiatric classifications are to be viewed as objects of natural science. This model has received intensive philosophical scrutiny, including arguments that deny these conditions are deficiencies at all. Along with issues arising from cognitive psychology and the neurosciences, such foundational matters make up much of the following entry. Because of their focus on issues central to the philosophy of mind and ethics (e.g., the mind-body problem, moral responsibility, agency and identity), analyses of mental disorder have extensive implications for those fields. As clinical phenomena, they also reflect an inescapable, everyday, social reality, giving theoretical inquiries additionally urgent practical, moral, and legal implications.
- 1. Terminology
- 2. Folk Psychology, Conceptual Analysis, and Science
- 3. The Mental in Mental Disorder
- 4. The Disorder in Mental Disorder
- 5. Phenomenological Approaches
- 6. Classification
- 7. Natural Kind Status
- 8. Values and Mental Disorder
- 9. Particular Disorders
- 10. Anti-psychiatry, Feminist Theory, Post- and Critical- Psychiatry, Neurodiversity and Identity Politics
- 11. Future Prospects
- Bibliography
- Academic Tools
- Other Internet Resources
- Related Entries
1. Terminology
The language here is highly contentious. There are exceptions, but in a long history mental disorders or illnesses have been characterized as “evil”, “sinful”, and “willful error” or, at the very least, regarded as unwelcome misfortune.[1] With some regularity, conditions listed in the “Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders” (DSM) of the American Psychiatric Association (APA 2013) and the “International Classification of Disease” (ICD) of the World Health Organization (WHO 2020) have provided new classificatory titles and terminology, such revisions often solely aimed at reducing negative and stigmatizing associations. Authors cited in what follows use “mental disorder”, “psychiatric disability”, “psychiatric disorder”, “mental illness”, “madness”, “psychopathology”, and “neuro-atypicality”. Controversy attaches to these terms, as it does to particular diagnostic labels (such as “schizophrenia”). Because some would question whether these mental differences are forms of illness or disorder at all, the more neutral but rarely used, “mental difference” perhaps better accommodates each side of this controversy, so the choice of “disorder” here is for its greater familiarity, and not intended to promote a disorder or illness view.
Three changes of language require special attention. With increasing frequency, the term “illness” in “mental illness” has been replaced by “disorder”, apparently without a consistent rationale beyond avoiding explicitly medical associations. In a parallel recent trend “the cognitive” and “cognition” are sometimes introduced as equivalents or replacements for “the mental”. This new language around “cognition” collapses the earlier faculty psychology divisions of affection and cognition: as much as doxastic states, emotions are “cognitive”.[2] Finally, increasing use of “mental and behavioral”, sometimes shortened to “behavioral” (as in “behavioral health”), reflects substantive changes, such as the inclusion of addictions in the class of disorders and a preference for precisely measurable symptoms over subjective report.
Unless otherwise indicated, the expression “mental disorder” replaces “mental illness” in what follows, and refers not only to more “mental” conditions like psychoses and affective disorders, but also to “behavioral” conditions such as addictions and personality disorders. Frequently, the shift from “mental” to “cognitive” also indicates allegiance to substantive theoretical tenets. Here, however, “cognitive” and “cognition” are used only as terms of art within particular theoretical analyses.
2. Folk Psychology, Conceptual Analysis, and Science
Concepts of mental disorder are understood differently in the perspectives of folk psychology (which privilege common-sense understandings) and medical psychiatry (which privilege scientific understandings). Inconsistencies arising at the boundaries, where mental disorders meet other kinds of disorder, add ambiguity. Rather than traditionally mental symptoms, for example, “hysterical” (“psychosomatic”, “somatoform”, “functional” or “conversion”) syndromes exhibit bodily maladies and dysfunction (Scull 2009). Yet they remain mental disorders in common understanding, and have long found a place in standard psychiatric classifications.[3]
There are different views about the conceptual relationship between everyday and more clinical language about mental disorder, and philosophers and others have approached this matter according to varying foundational assumptions. Both commonsense psychology and conceptual analysis reflecting it, are part of what Rachel Cooper calls a broadly “descriptive” project, which engages linguistic intuitions (Cooper 2020). Opinions vary as to the value and importance of the resulting characterizations. Some insist that the concept of mental disorder employed in psychiatry’s conception and classification of disorders is too closely allied to the parallel concepts in folk psychology. Dominic Murphy (2006) argues that folk psychology is inadequate to the scientific taxonomical task of discovering the “hidden causal structure” of mental disorders, since there is no assurance that common sense understandings correspond to scientifically tractable concepts. Without a principled and systematic way to identify the class of mental disorders, these concerns suggest that any taxonomy that is employed will likely prove inaccurate and the outmoded, folk psychological category of mental disorder will eventually be rendered obsolete.
More conservatively, others have urged the practical importance of maintaining the category of mental disorder (Brülde & Radovic 2006). Everyday language and the traditional classifications built around it have provided a common framework for research and clinical practice; and with any further blurring of the boundaries between mental disorders and the brain damage and disease treated by neurologists, demarcations of professional competence would be lost. Conversely, the scientific authority of medical psychiatry has been challenged by those who express fears of overdiagnosis, granting too much power to psychiatry and the pharmacology industry, and inappropriate deference to ‘expert opinions’ on mental health and eudaimonia that may be better addressed by non-scientific perspectives (see §10).
It is not only for such considerations of practicality and custom that common sense concepts have been supported. Some analyses adhere to an account of mind and mental processing employing mentalist terms and normative presuppositions inapplicable within an exclusively neuro-physical framework (see §4, §5, and §8). Others regard mental disorders as socially constructed entities, the existence and classification of which are inextricably tied to societal and interpersonal features of the world (see §10).
A taxonomy of these varying foundational assumptions includes intersecting issues: what mental disorders are, how much we presently know about them, and different approaches to their analysis. In one set of contrasts, naturalist (or objectivist) accounts hold that—as empirically discoverable entities—mental disorders can be provided value-free description, while normative (or evaluativist) analyses deny the possibility of such description (discussed in §8.1). Revisionists, prepared to relinquish all current concepts, disagree with conservatives favoring the retention of (at least some) traditional categories. And, in a final sorting, the nature of mental disorder will be sought either through a posteriori scientific research based in neurocognitive science, or through conceptual analysis derived in part or whole from social and cultural norms.
3. The Mental in Mental Disorder
In a once-common practice, mental or “functional” disorders were diagnosed just when no somatic traits were evident. Such language is now explicitly disavowed, eclipsed by a growing recognition that all disorders involve bodily states (APA 2013: 309; O’Leary 2021). Still, the “mental” in mental disorder is variously construed.
3.1 Internal Causes and External Symptoms
On traditional, two-part models from cell pathology, dysfunctional organic processes internal to the individual are manifested in, and causally responsible for, more readily observable external symptoms. Applied to mental disorder, certain underlying processes have been delimited as mental by appeal to the traditional categories of faculty psychology (perception, affection, cognition, memory, and so on). For example, hallucinations represent dysfunctional perceptual capabilities, mania and depression disturbed affect regulation, and delusions defective cognitive processing. A disorder is thus determined to be mental (as distinct from physical) if its internal causes involve psychological faculties (Wakefield 1997). Other accounts ascribe disordered mentality—not to underlying features but—to effects on the subject’s social and personal functioning (Rashed & Bingham 2014). For example, it is because her states of sadness and self-doubt result in absenteeism, that the person with depression seeks medical help (see §4.2). More holistic and “biopsychosocial” accounts combine these features (Nordenfelt 1995; Davies & Roache 2017; Bolton & Gillett 2019; O’Leary 2021).
On two-stage accounts both internal and external features form integral parts (Graham [2013] argues that this holds for prototypical disorders). Internal and external features are each included in the DSM definition of mental disorder:
a syndrome characterized by clinically significant disturbance in an individual’s cognition, emotion regulation, or behavior, that reflects a dysfunction in the psychological, biological or developmental processes underlying mental functioning. (APA 2013: 20, emphasis added)
The different positions on mental disorder just sketched—emphasizing internal conditions, observable manifestations (“symptoms”), and both—are discussed in Section 4. Each position exhibits vulnerabilities. Accounts stressing inherent features regularly rely on hypothetical entities or processes, expecting that future discoveries will reveal knowledge of causal mechanisms presently hidden from view (This position has a long history; see Murphy 2006, Tabb 2015). Often accounted for by its status as a new science, this faith has been sorely tested, thus far, by confused classifications, apparently ill-grounded research, and other liabilities, as well as incomplete models of mental dysfunction (see §4 and §6). If these impediments can be overcome, emphasis on internal causes may be expected to yield powerful explanatory models, laying the ground for targeted interventions and effective prevention and treatment (see the entry on Philosophy of Psychiatry). Placing emphasis on disabling or dysfunctional observable symptoms has comparable vulnerabilities. One setting’s dysfunctional mental symptom may be another’s normal, admired, or useful trait; and mental disorder must be distinguished conceptually from deviance, as well as from normal responses to the normal losses and setbacks that are common in human experience (see §4, §8, and §10).
3.2 The Mark of the Mental
In some philosophical accounts (including those stemming from phenomenological traditions), the mental is distinguished by particular features: it bears a special relationship to conscious awareness and to persons, for example, or may be taken to exhibit the distinctive “aboutness” or intentionality exclusive to mental attitudes (see §5). Similarly, some theorizing emphasizes the reasons-responsiveness of all human thought and action, by which disorder can alone be explained and understood (Campbell 2013; Thornton 2007; Summers & Sinnott-Armstrong 2019).
Explanations in cognitive psychology have taken several different forms over the years: information processing models, connectionist networks, and neuroscientific approaches. Moreover, philosophical reconstructions of cognitive psychology and cognitive science must be distinguished from the cognitive psychology practiced by psychologists—although little discussion of “the mental” occurs in either. Instead, focus is on the cognitive when, as was pointed out earlier, the “cognitive” subsumes capacities, states, and processes that used to be considered non-cognitive, such as sensations and emotions. Widespread acceptance of these shifts in much theoretical and research writing on mental disorder has gone some way toward eclipsing philosophical concepts of mind and the mental, although commonsense cognitive capacities (which are assumed in philosophical accounts of intentionality) remain the starting point of the research program of cognitive science, and cognitive studies of traditional “mental states”, such as reasoning and consciousness.
The focus of cognitive psychology usually lies with computation and representation. Mental/cognitive states (representations) depict features of the outside world (as well as other mental states and abstract entities) and mental/cognitive processes operate on those inner symbols, transforming and manipulating them (see Von Eckardt 1993; Friedenberg & Silverman 2011; Cratsley & Samuels 2013, and the entry on Cognitive Science). Although demarcated by the faculties known as “mental”, the realm of the cognitive is typically construed as properties or processes with a causal role in determining behavior, or behavioral capacities, that offer no resistance to naturalistic characterization (Chalmers 1996). Candidates for a distinctive “mark of the cognitive” are debated—but so is the need for one (Varga 2018; Allen 2017).
3.3 Metaphysical Implications
Mental disorders are conditions or states attributed to persons, but this need entail neither that they are entirely non-physical in nature, nor that they must (or even can), be explained in solely neuro-scientific terms. Maintaining the separation between mental and physical disorders is compatible with some forms of weak physicalism, allowing that mental or psychological processing involved in functions such as perception, reasoning and memory, are realized in the workings of the brain (see Schaffner 2016; Jefferson 2021 and the entry on Health). Problems of supervenience and emergence have led some to defend a holistic “naturalistic dualism” entailed in a biopsychosocial model (Bolton & Gillett 2019; O’Leary 2021).
4. The Disorder in Mental Disorder
Schizophrenia, depression, and obsessions, bipolar disorder are core instances of mental disorder, but psychiatric classification recognizes many other conditions as well. From such a large and heterogeneous collection, this broad category may be regarded as a family resemblance one (Lilienfeld & Marino 1995). Indeed, through a different historical or cultural lens, the assembled variations known today as mental disorders would likely appear incoherent and arbitrary. Yet, spurred by essentialist expectations (and out of concern about the unwarranted “medicalization” of normal states and behavior), the quest for a unifying conception of mental disorder (illness, or disease) has persisted within philosophical research. Characteristic features have been identified, including disunity, irrationality, the presence of suffering and disability, several forms of dysfunction, and even adaptive function. Proposed formal analytic definitions are illustrated in Section 4.4.
4.1 Disunity and Irrationality
Works of ancient philosophy are focused more on the psyche’s health (or eudaimonia) than its illness. Nonetheless, there are hints that just as a unified soul is one that is healthy (as well as rational and virtuous), a soul lacking unity will be disturbed or mad. Offering an account of the harmonious soul, whose rational and non-rational elements achieve unity, Aristotle leaves us a picture of the warring and fractured state of an unhealthy soul, for example.[4] The emphasis on disunity is here tied to vice and irrationality: a fully unified soul is virtuous and rational, a disunified one vicious and irrational in its unhealthy divisions. This view of vices and virtues is also characteristic of the subsequent Stoic analyses (Irwin 2013), although Aristotle adhered to a different account of the passions and a more Platonic analysis of vice. A conception of mental illness as psychic disunity (as well as an association between health, rationality and virtue) reoccurs in later philosophy (in Spinoza, for example), and in psychoanalytic traditions. Within present-day disorder descriptions, some symptom clusters readily fit the classical emphasis on disunity (addictions, and bipolarity, for example); others, including most personality disorders, are less easily depicted in such terms (Worrell & Denham 2016).
Mental disorder has been understood as irrationality (or “Unreason”) after the “Age of Reason” that prized order and logic (Foucault 1965). Together with the emergence of empirical science, this emphasis is seen to have laid the foundation for our contemporary psychiatric categories and theories.[5] In the present day, cultural norms and intuitive folk psychology assign the boundaries of mental disorder, and these intuitions conflict about some particular conditions (e.g., addictions, personality disorders). Yet disturbed or disabled doxastic states and capabilities remain core examples of disorder, over which intuitive agreement is strong. Characterized by incomprehensibly disordered thought, failure to adjust beliefs in response to new evidence, inconsistencies between thought and action, and delusional convictions, psychosis and psychotic thought patterns are regularly judged prototypical features of mental disorder. So the rationalistic analysis of disorder corresponds—but only to a reduced version of the presently sprawling overall category.
Forms of doxastic irrationality are still the mainstay of much policy and legal analysis about mental disorder. Assessments of criminal responsibility, of fitness to stand trial, and of the capacity to undertake binding contracts, for example, are expressed in terms of the defendant’s ability to know and understand (Reznek 1987; Robinson 1996, 2013; Adshead 2008). Ostensibly, construing mental disorder as a want of rationality has been weakened by evidence from behavioral economics showing that holding and acting on well-grounded and reasons-responsive beliefs occurs rarely in the general population, and common prejudices and superstitions seem barely distinguishable from clinical delusions with respect not only to their prevalence but to the way they are adopted and maintained (Bortolotti 2009, 2013, 2020).
Confidence that irrationality defines mental disorder is similarly eroded if, understood as effective social function and personal flourishing, mental health lies in traits such as unwarranted optimism, and the distorting tendency to remember successes over failures in “positive illusions”(Taylor & Brown 1988; McKay & Dennett 2009; Jefferson et al. 2017). Along these lines, some illusions, delusions, and hallucinations have recently been acknowledged to be “perfectly acceptable, sometimes praiseworthy ways of being hopeful, committed to imagining and enacting a better world for oneself and others…making moral and meaningful lives” (Flanagan & Graham 2017: 309). Whether disorder is usefully characterized as a want of reason also depends on guiding, normative conceptions of mental health or eudaimonia, and on the role of reason in those conceptions—not merely on facts of the matter, or on consequentialist reasoning.
4.2 Suffering and Disability
Other depictions of disorder rely on one or both of the groups of traits around harm, suffering, and distress, on the one hand, and disability, incapacity and personal or behavioral dysfunction, on the other. These are the features noted in a series of influential prefatory remarks in the diagnostic and statistical manuals (the DSMs and ICDs). The wording of the fifth edition of the DSM introduces a disjunction:
Mental disorders are usually associated with significant distress or disability in social, occupational, or other important activities. (APA 2013 emphasis added)
A very similar passage from the ICD-11 is comparably qualified:
“Disorder”…is…a clinically recognizable set of symptoms or behavior associated in most cases with distress and with interference with personal functions. (WHO 2020, emphasis added)
Psychodynamic or psychoanalytic presuppositions may posit underlying distresses that are masked or submerged within the psyche; and the elusive phenomenology of some conditions suggests the presence of nameless existential anxieties hidden from awareness (Ratcliffe 2008, 2017). But such explanations aside, distress has been widely regarded as a ubiquitous feature of disorder. In symptom-focused accounts laying stress on the consequences of the syndrome, distress becomes prominent as a form of disabling dysfunction (Stein et al. 2010). Instead of separate criteria (and either singly or jointly sufficient for disorder, as in the respective DSM and ICD definitions above), suffering and dysfunction are conjoined on a “distress-impairment” analysis, where disorder status is assigned with (and defined by) distress that is “unmanageable or disabling” (Bolton 2013). The plausibility of this analysis increases with what have been called “distress related conditions”, such as depression and anxiety, that are “more constitutive of the illness” (Bolton 2012: 10; also see §4).
To accommodate exceptions that seem neither distressing nor disabling (such as manic states), mental disorder is sometimes characterized not by distress and dysfunction but by raised risk of such outcomes (Gert & Culver 2004). But risk of disorder is not disorder, and risk language invites troubling ethical issues around over-diagnosis and false positives (Schwartz 2008; Stein et al. 2010; Bolton 2013; Broome, Fugar-Poli, & Wuyts 2013; Radden 2018).
Loosely understood, moreover, distresses are an inescapable part of the human condition and normal responses to life’s vicissitudes. When and whether normal (and even appropriate) suffering reflects pathology has long been the source of philosophical—and societal—disagreement (Wilkinson 2000; Horwitz & Wakefield 2007). In the discussions of “normal sadness” that accompanied the revision of the fifth edition of the DSM, the grief exclusion that had (temporarily) exempted from diagnosis the suffering around mourning and grief, was challenged, its proposed elimination charged with “medicalizing” or “pathologizing” normal and appropriate human feelings (Zachar 2014; Wakefield 2012). The separation of normal from pathological distress will be indicated by distress emanating from the disorder itself, rather than from other contingencies. But presently, distresses resulting from the stigma and discrimination that follow diagnosis and treatment, as well as a host of other, frequently negative, consequences in jarring and alarming disruptions to personal lives, selves, and relationships, prove difficult to disentangle (Tekin 2011).
Some predict that biological markers will eventually allow us to distinguish distress that is a symptom of depression, for example, from that which is a normal response to external contingencies (Horwitz & Wakefield 2007). Such biomarkers may be welcomed by those decrying over-diagnosis (Stegenga 2008, ch. 6), although an evaluative interpretation as to whether, and when, such biomarkers occur in healthy and unhealthy form will be required.
Some argue that the subjective experience of distress and the extent of impairment of the person’s day-to-day functioning are intrinsic properties of disorders like depression: conceptually, disorder attributions are made on the basis of “consequences of the syndrome as they manifest for the subject” (Rashed & Bingham 2014: 245). Psychological symptoms may constitute a mental disorder, even as it is caused by biological or social factors. In the absence of known biomarkers, depression is attributed based on psychological symptoms alone; and were known biomarkers present without evidence of any psychological symptoms, our intuitions suggest, disorder attribution would be withheld. These intuitions may shift with time, it is recognized, depending on how most people and most psychiatrists now understand, define, diagnose, and treat, depression. In current practices, attributions of depression are made without biomarkers (Cooper 2020).
Analyses characterizing felt distress as a property constitutive of some given psychiatric condition (e.g., depression) are also compatible with recent models focused on the causally interconnected statistical networks making up symptom clusters. These clusters are depicted as reinforced through feedback loops that serve to link together assorted symptoms independent of any underlying, antecedent, common, cause. In the case of depression, a range of symptoms arise from diverse sources and, through their looping interactions, form, worsen, and maintain the disorder as a relatively stable entity and conceptual whole (Kendler, Zachar, & Craver 2011; Borsboom & Cramer 2013; Borsboom 2017).
Symptom-focused accounts may combine suffering with disability. But a conception in terms of what the affected person is prevented from doing, or unable to do as well as others, captured in the ideas of disability, impairment, incapacity and personal or behavioral dysfunction, offers an alternative characterization that can acknowledge disorders without apparent personal suffering (notably, mania and narcissistic personality disorder).
Dysfunction and disability have been allied or treated as rough equivalents; but sometimes disability is placed in opposition to dysfunction. Instead of being construed as internal to the person, disabilities are often represented as conditional impairments, dependent on context (including physical and social arrangements). They impose limitations on the person’s ability to perform everyday activities and participate as more typically-abled people do and call for appropriate accommodation analogous to ramps for those using wheelchairs (Oliver 2004; Polvora 2011). The analogies linking psychiatric with other disabilities is incomplete, however, nor can accommodations be achieved as easily as installing ramps (Amundson & Tresky 2007; Rashed 2019).
Like disability, the deviance eliciting societal censure and condemnation is also placed in contrast to dysfunction, although efforts to further characterize that contrast have thus far been incomplete (Aftab & Rashed 2021).
4.3 Dysfunction in Two Stage Analyses
Dysfunction forms a central element of the most widely discussed analytic definition of mental disorder, introduced in §3. The notion of dysfunction applies in two distinct ways in Wakefield’s harmful dysfunction analysis, one way avowedly objective and the other not (see §4.4). In the first, dysfunction occurs in some part or parts of a bodily or neural system. That dysfunction in turn causes dysfunction in some part of the individual’s social and personal system (grounding normative judgments of harmfulness). The first kind of dysfunction allegedly permits factual description.
The characteristic dysfunction of mental disorder is here part of a standard, idiopathic model, as we saw, with disabling traits understood as symptoms or manifestations of an underlying pathological process. The suitability of this model for psychiatric conditions has received persistent critique (see §10.1). Recent challenges rest on the persuasiveness of network models (introduced in §4.2), where symptomatic dysfunction does not emanate from some disabled inner mechanism, but instead emerges piecemeal from interacting experiences that cumulatively build clusters of disabling symptoms out of feedback loops (Kendler, Zachar, & Craver 2011; Borsboom & Cramer 2013). Support for this alternative model stems from evidence that a range of factors combine to bring about disorder: individualistic risk factors, but also aspects of the broader context in which the individual finds herself (Bolton 2010; Kirmayer, Lemelson, & Cummings 2015). A more fundamental critique rejects the dysfunction analysis of disorder, favoring instead a madness-as-strategy account, which draws from adaptationism (Garson 2022; see §4.4 and the entry on Adaptationism).
4.4 Formal Definitions
Eschewing a more formal definition, analyses such as the “distress-impairment” one introduced earlier rely on prototypical cases (Graham 2013), or point to intrinsic vagueness that must thwart such efforts (Keil, Keuck & Hauswald 2017). Others are more ambitious, proposing analytic definitions in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions and even encompassing other medical conditions as well as mental disorders (for those stressing the inseparability and interdependence of mental and bodily disorder, no important distinction is acknowledged between mental and physical disorders [Pârvan 2015]). Definitions (i)–(vi) below are a sample of these efforts. More recent definitions reflect increasing recognition that the diversity of the category must frustrate efforts at a covering definition.
- A disease is the interference of a normal biological function that detracts from the person’s survival or reproduction (Boorse 1977). More recent elaborations on this early version of the definition emphasize biological function and statistical normality, so that on a bio-statistical theory, diseases are internal states that depress a functional ability below species-typical levels (relative to age and sex) (Boorse 1997). Critiques of this definition have challenged its aspiration to be value free; its introduction of an arbitrarily selected reference class; and its failure to honor the accepted distinction between “disease” (with its implied defectiveness) and mere difference (Bolton 2008).
- A condition is a mental disorder if and only if (a) the condition causes some harm or deprivation of benefit to the person as judged by the standards of the person’s culture, and (b) the condition results from the inability of some internal mechanism to perform its natural function, wherein a natural function is an effect that is part of the evolutionary explanation of the existence and structure of the mechanism (Wakefield 1992, 1997). Critiques of this definition occur later in this section and in Section 5. In addition, definitions in evolutionary theoretic terms introduce a category of innate risk factors that is belied by the way natural, social, and individual factors are inextricably interwoven in disorder (Bolton 2008). And the formulation relies on unsubstantiated, empirical assumptions about the way natural selection underlies natural function (Lilienfeld & Marino 1995; Murphy & Stich 2000). The cultural relativism in (a) has also been challenged (Gert & Culver 2004: 421; Bolton 2008). And rather than exhibiting dysfunction, at least some mental disorders may be explained relationally, by traits that are mismatched in the person’s context, due to their developmental or evolutionary features (Garson 2015).
- A mental malady is a condition of a person, other than his rational beliefs and desires, such that he is suffering, or at increased risk of suffering, an evil (death, pain, disability, loss of freedom or opportunity, or loss of pleasure), in the absence of a distinct sustaining cause (Gert & Culver 2004). The concept of a sustaining cause is unacceptably vague and inclusive, permitting conditions to count as disorders that are not, intuitively, disorders at all (Murphy 2006). For example, some disorders leave permanent, non-pathological alterations in the character that outlast any immediate stressors.
- A condition is pathological if and only if it is an abnormal bodily/mental condition that requires medical intervention and that harms standard members of the species in standard conditions (Reznek 1987: 163–4). For criticisms of this definition’s appeal to baseline population norms, and to medical intervention, see comments on (i), (ii) and (iv) above. Reference to required medical intervention fails to acknowledge risks of over-medicalization and over-diagnosis and invokes concerns over enhancement (Savulescu, ter Meulen, & Kahane 2011)
- Diseases involve deprivation, but a disease is a depriving relation rather than a depriving entity, depending on the patient for its existence…the person is not conceived as ontologically diminished or defective because it suffers the deprivation. Drawing on Augustine’s ontology of disease, bodily integrity, and the human person, Alexandra Pârvan (2015, 2016) argues that disease stands in ontologically necessary connection with the patient as person (from this she derives a treatment approach based on how the person relates to the disease, and a goal of reconfiguring the person as deprived but not diminished). This account is limited in its required adherence to its Augustinian ontology.
- Mental disorders are biological kinds whose effects lead to harmful consequences … more natural kinds of mental disorders (e.g. schizophrenia, bipolar disorder) are biological kinds primarily underwritten by biological mechanisms. More artificial kinds (e.g., hysteria, voyeuristic disorder) are social kinds primarily underwritten by social mechanisms (Tsou 2021: 2–3).
- … at least some of the forms (of madness) … are strategies for solving problems, coping with aspects of the environment, regulating one’s mental economy … the creative problem-solving activity of the human mind, or God’s stern but benevolent hand, or the healing impetus of nature, or an evolutionary adaptation, a purpose-driven process, a well-operated machine … (Garson 2022: 10). If neuropsychiatry ever succeeds in identifying the defective mechanisms it seeks, Garson’s analysis must be weakened. Moreover, it seems vulnerable to some of the accusations of complexity-defying oversimplification that have dogged other adaptationist just-so stories.
5. Phenomenological Approaches
The symptoms of mental disorder are primarily, if not exclusively, states about which their subject can claim a sort of authority. Since subjects can intentionally or unintentionally misreport symptom states, such phenomenological reports—however necessary—are epistemically limited as data (Kontos 2016). Psychology can provide reliable behavioral assessments of disorder and indicate its presence through laboratory performance tests. But no mental disorder is thus far independently verifiable (though blood tests or scans, for example). Hence, first person reports play a special part in understanding mental disorders, for clinicians, researchers, and philosophers alike (Flanagan 2011; Varga 2015). Karl Jaspers’ General Psychopathology, which combines detailed clinical description with the existential and phenomenological methods of Husserl and Heidegger, has been widely discussed. This pairing of clinical and philosophical knowledge makes Jaspers (1913[1963]) one of the undisputed originators of the research field known as the philosophy of psychiatry and psychopathology. The “phenomenological” clinical approaches following this broadly Jasperian tradition, however, vary in their adherence to the tenets of phenomenology (Parnas & Sass 2008).
The phenomenological strand of philosophical analysis influenced by thinkers like Husserl and Heidegger focuses on immediate, first person reports. Analyses have examined self-experience in psychosis (Parnas & Sass 2008; Madeira, Pienkos, et al. 2019), disordered temporal experience (Fuchs 2005, 2013), delusional states (Parnas & Sass 2008; Gallagher 2005, 2013), and affective disturbances (Ratcliffe 2008; Ratcliffe & Stephan 2014; Jacobs et. al. 2014). In these traditions neither psychology nor psychopathology are empirical sciences in the usual sense because they involve distinctive forms of explanation. Arising within nineteenth century social science, the hermeneutical approach involving meanings calls for Verstehen (understanding), a distinctive, interpretive way of apprehending human action (Jaspers 1913[1963]; Phillips 2013, Wiggins & Schwartz 2011; Spitzer & Uehlein 1992). These differences of approach bring differing orientations towards fundamentals, and approaches following German and French traditions have been contrasted with the “Anglo-empiricist” approaches, which display a greater emphasis on objectivity and empirical science (Mullen 2011; Gergel 2012).
These differences bring contrasting theories about psychology as science. Some argue that the subjective life of the patient should be the main or even sole locus of attention (Stanghellini 2004). Others argue that the experiences associated with psychosis must be categorically divorced from more typical psychological processes (Sass 2001; Parnas & Sass 2008). Emphasizing the unique challenges imposed by interpretation in psychiatry, Somogy Varga (2015) argues for a hermeneutics distinctive to psychiatry that is grounded in ideas about the self-interpreting aspect of human beings, “mental disorder” thus standing in an asymmetrical relation that supervenes on our self identities.
There is disagreement over the correct application of phenomenological method (Mishara 2007; Sass, Parnas, & Zahavi 2011). But psychopathology likely offers a challenge so great as to call for a range of approaches (Ratcliffe 2011; Wiggins and Schwartz 2011; Gallagher 2013). Attempts have also been made to combine phenomenological with empirical approaches: Matthew Ratcliffe’s work on affective states employs social research methods (Ratcliffe 2008; Ratcliffe & Stephan 2014). And efforts to tie in phenomenological theorizing with findings in neuroscience have yielded the hybrid methodology of phenomenological clinical neuroscience advocating an initial study of subjective experience to only then be probed for its underlying neurobiology (Mishara 2007: 34).
The merging of empirical and phenomenological methodologies is represented by the fields of embodied and enactive cognition. Conceptions of the embodied, embedded, and sense-making enactive mind bring emphasis on the way, shaped by perceptual experience, consciousness and the first person perspective form the basis of all mental processing (Varela, Thompson, & Rosch 1991; Durt, Fuchs, & Tewes 2017; Di Paolo & De Jaegher 2017). Applied to mental disorder, this departure from classical cognitivist assumptions and analogies suggests that at least some disorder grows out of disturbances in embodied interaction with the environment, and not from dysfunctions occurring in high-level cognitive mechanisms (Drayson 2009; Stanghellini 2004, 2016; Maiese 2016).[6]
6. Classification
While Section 3 focused on what might separate mental from non-mental disorders, and Section 4 was concerned with how to separate disordered from non-disordered states, this section addresses controversies over how different types of putative mental disorders should be distinguished from one another. These controversies, like so many about psychiatry, span the disciplines of medicine, science (including neuroscience and psychology), and philosophy.
The DSM and ICD share broad features in providing categorical taxonomies: each disorder is idiopathic in arising at least in part from morbid factors within the person, and each is identified “descriptively”, using polythetic (disjunctive) criteria identified with clinical observation (including patients’ self-reports). Aside from serving the institutions providing services, their uniformity is aimed to enhance inter-diagnostician reliability; and research based on these reliable classifications, it had been hoped, should eventually allow validation of the categories, although failure to formulate valid diagnostic categories has been conspicuous and spurned the creation of alternative classification systems (e.g., RDoC, HiTOP).
Following early work by Carl Hempel (1961) that depicted psychiatry’s claim to scientific status as depending on the empirical testability of classificatory concepts, much of the subsequent philosophical discussion of classification has been critical. These criticisms concede little usefulness to psychiatric classification, are skeptical of the promise of validity, doubtful of its methodology and claims to scientific authority, unpersuaded by the categorical system employed, skeptical about its individualistic and idiopathic assumptions, and dubious over its claims to value-freedom. Philosophical analysis has often focused on particular symptom descriptions, disregarding or disavowing the diagnostic categories of which they are presumed to be clinical manifestations, in some cases introducing and employing revised categories such as “distress related conditions” (Bolton 2012), “body image disorders” (Morris 2013), and “real hallucinations” (Ratcliffe 2017). Others have accepted the entities so classified (Sass et al. 2011).
Criticisms of the DSM and the ICD question their research purposes and usefulness, categorical approach to taxonomy, and supposed value-neutrality (see §8). These criticisms emphasize the presence of multiple overarching values, including the methodological values intended to facilitate reliability and validity. Unsupportable values (e.g., homophobia, misogyny) have also been identified.
6.1 Research Purposes and Usefulness
Even by those within psychiatry, it has been widely concluded that as tools for research, the prevailing classifications are flawed, producing findings that tend to be inconsistent, non-replicable, non-specific, or ambiguous, with the categories involved exhibiting problems of construct and predictive validity, as well as imprecise phenotypic definitions, widespread heterogeneity, and extensive comorbidity (Cuthbert & Insel 2013; Poland 2014; Poland & Von Eckardt 2013; Tsou 2021). In partial defense of DSM-type classifications, Elizabeth Lalumera (2016) points out that mental disorders may correspond to theoretically informed, albeit incompletely understood, concepts, in contrast to descriptive conceptions sufficient for identification practices in diagnosis and care.
In response to the DSM’s failure to formulate valid categories, the Research Domain Criteria (RDoC) defines constructs at lower levels of analysis than the DSM’s favored level of “mental disorders”. Separate units of analysis (genes, cells, circuits, self reports, etc.) are each employed in specific research domains (e.g., positive and negative valence systems, cognitive systems, systems for social processes, and arousal/regulatory systems), and the intersections of units of analysis with research domains produce segments of a spectrum linking normal and atypical features. Whether RDoC’s goals are compatible has been questioned, but its aim is to promote both more accurate research and more effective treatments (Cuthbert & Insel 2013; Tabb 2015, 2019; Perring 2016; Morris et. al. 2022). RDoC has in turn been criticized, e.g., for assigning disorder to individuals rather than social context, neglecting personal agency, and assuming an outdated individualistic model of the self (e.g., see Poland & Tekin 2017; Tabb 2019).
6.2 Categorical and Dimensional Approaches
The DSM and ICD have largely followed a nineteenth century, Kraepelinian model, where each disease is a discretely bounded entity, made up of a symptom cluster emanating from underlying organic states or processes within the individual patient. But the applicability of this model to mental disorder has been challenged. Some suggest replacing the broad ideal of validity (involving a relation between classificatory name and underlying disease) with the narrower concept of predictive or prognostic validity (Schaffner 2012; Tsou 2015, 2021). Rather than being classified as discrete diseases, some argue that disorders should be classified dimensionally, e.g., defining depression by severity levels (Zachar 2014; Poland & Tekin 2017; Machery 2017).
Some diagnostic conditions (e.g., PTSD) apparently arise from their subject’s surrounding social, economic, and cultural context. Even those with more claim to idiopathic genetic, neurological, or biological causes as predisposing factors are recognized to exhibit a course more strongly influenced by environmental and epigenetic than any fixed inherent factors, thereby putting further pressure on the “common cause” hypothesis, whereby a syndrome is explained by a single biological feature or set of features (Borsboom & Cramer 2013). Against biological reductionistic approaches, the Network Model approach (Borsboom 2017) classifies psychopathology in terms of interacting networks of biological, psychological, and social factors.
With their hypothesized common causes awaiting discovery, categorical analyses present problems. But dimensional approaches highlight the so-called boundary problem (Rashed 2021) of where to assign the line between normal variation and disorder. Theoretically, the “common cause” in categorical analyses serves as an anchor uniting the disparate and variable observable symptoms making up a given disorder, which justifies the nomological approach of diagnostic classifications. Aside from this theoretical solution, categorical models are similarly beset by boundary (fuzzy edges) problems. The presence of disorder is preceded and followed by a halo of prodromal and postdromal symptoms, over which clinical (and everyday) judgements are often unresolved. In an explicitly normative attempt to resolve an aspect of the boundary problem as it occurs in social and political contexts, Mohammed Rashed (2019, 2021) employs criteria governing recognition of social identities as a guide to pathological status.
The collection of disorders enumerated and described in psychiatric classification systems has prompted alarm over the boundaries of mental disorder, the erosion of normal mentally healthy states and variations, and the inappropriate role played by medical psychiatry (and science) in dictating norms of healthy psychic functioning. Philosophical criticisms of “medicalization” emphasize the increasing influence of neuroscience in transforming cultural expectations and diminishing individual agency and the power of dictating psychological norms by the psychopharmacological industry (Phillips 2009, 2013; Rose & Abi-Rached 2013; Moncrieff 2008; Sadler 2005, 2013, Whitaker & Cosgrove 2015).
In contrast to these commonly-voiced apprehensions about over-medicalization, there remains the persistent charge of under-diagnosis and under-treatment of those with diagnosable mental disorder, often attributed to stigma, and to the socioeconomic status of under-served communities. Epidemiological findings about the incidence of disorder, as distinct from its diagnosis, are notoriously insufficient, however, quite apart from a want of independent biomarkers, due to self-stigma and fear of discrimination, for example, but also to distorting placebo effects, and to research methods misleadingly susceptible to false positives (Jopling 2009; Horwitz & Wakefield 2007; Poland & Von Eckardt 2013). The actual epidemiological data remains opaque and equivocal, leaving these debates unresolved.
DSM and ICD classifications have been remarkably influential worldwide: today, they appear almost immovably permanent. But viewed within their broader moral, political, and social context, which includes psychiatry’s apparently uneven provision of effective treatment, the appropriate stance to adopt towards them, as Christian Perring (2016: 87) has urged, remains critical and skeptical.
7. Natural Kind Status
Philosophers of science have explored whether all or some mental illnesses might be classified as natural kinds, the claim made about particular diagnostic categories or symptom clusters (depression, schizophrenic disorder, and autism, for example), as well as about separate symptoms (Cooper 2007; Samuels 2009; Tsou 2021). With recognition that even the category of biological species would not meet an essentialist criterion for natural kind status, a “homeostatic property cluster” account of natural kinds has been proposed (Ellis 2001, Murphy 2006, Cooper 2007, Samuels 2009, Tsou 2016; also see the entry on Species). A natural kind must be able to ground explanations and inductive inferences, and enable effective human intervention. Linked by mechanisms (e.g., molecular, neurobiological, developmental) that cluster together, the homeostatic aspect of HPC kinds ensures that disorders are sufficiently stable to yield projectable inferences and be explanatory (Kincaid and Sullivan 2014, Tsou 2022).
Psychological categories may resemble biological species in some respects. However, significant differences are suggested by three distinct arguments: (i) Some have taken psychological categories to represent a different order of being (see §5), with its own distinctive forms of causal explanation (Jaspers 1913[1963]; Bolton 2008; Wiggins & Schwartz 2011; Kusters 2016). (ii) Others point out that psychological categories can alter, and eventually even be altered by, the persons they classify, forming “interactive” kinds through such looping effects. Hacking (1995, 1999) argues that mental disorders cannot be natural kinds because the looping effects generated by their classifications render them inherently unstable. And (iii), some have tried to show that the relation between mental illnesses and biological kinds differs according to the role played by values in establishing the taxa of mental illness (Wakefield 1992; see §8). None of these differences has gone uncriticized. A thoroughgoing mind to brain reductionism would reject (i). Regarding (ii), Tsou (2007) argues that classificatory feedback does not necessarily render mental disorders unstable, and Khalidi (2010) argues that that some natural science classifications (e.g., dog) generate looping effects that require classificatory revisions. In response to (iii), it has been argued that values also enter into the classification of biological species, but once we reach the categories of interest, non-evaluative traits form the observable taxa of such species (Cooper 2007).
Although the diverse ends to which disorder taxonomies can be put argue against finding a single answer about the kind status of mental disorders, focus on the purposes served by disorder language and categories has proven fruitful: (i) Mental disorders have been assigned to a category of “practical kinds”, where membership in this class depends on some external criterion that is pragmatically relevant in the clinical context, such as a certain degree of functional impairment, and remains unrelated to the underlying structure of the kind (Zachar 2014). Moreover, they may be further classified according to their status as dimensional, discrete, and fuzzy kinds, and there is little reason to suppose that each and all conform to any one of these (Haslam 2002, 2014). (ii) Whether or not they exhibit the stability required of classifications into true natural kinds, these disorders do possess the properties relevant, and sufficiently stable, to guide clinical treatment, Şerife Tekin illustrates, using the lack of illness awareness (“insight”) common in patients with some diagnoses (Tekin 2016).
8. Values and Mental Disorder
Values have unfailingly played a role in the way mental disorders are classified, conceptualized, experienced as personal diagnosis, and treated. Philosophical accounts differ over the possibility of a value-free science of psychiatry (§8.1). Values also affect societal and personal attitudes towards disorder and diagnosis, in ways that are more immediate, considerably more urgent, and morally consequential (§8.2). Some of these issues are dealt with in bioethical research directed specifically towards psychiatry (§8.3).
8.1 Evaluativism (Normativism) and Objectivism (Naturalism)
Present day conceptions, classifications, and attributions of mental disorder contain many values, some explicit, others implicit, some moral, others non-moral. Unacceptable bias has been repeatedly identified, exemplified in categories such as homosexuality (with its homophobia), pre-menstrual syndrome (unwarrantedly assigning disorder status to normal function), masochistic personality disorder (pathologizing misogynist gender roles), and oppositional defiant conduct disorders (exhibiting racial bias) (Sadler 2005, 2013; Potter 2014; Poland 2014, Gagné-Julien 2021). As in all medicine, the prefixes of “illness”and “disorder,” like “disease,” already declare values such as the preference for health over ill-health. A theory of values based medicine (VBM) emphasizes that values governing mental health are particularly contentious, requiring distinctive forms of negotiation in clinical practice (Fulford 2004, 2014).
A central philosophical question is whether moral values are inescapably attached to the conceptualization and classification of mental disorders at the level of theorizing, forming an inherent part of their definition. Such “evaluativism” (“normativism”, or “constructivism”) is placed in contrast to “objectivism” (“naturalism”), which seeks a value-free account of mental disorder. Debates over these questions have long dominated philosophical research on mental disorder, many played out around attempts to define mental disorder in ways that are value-free (see §4; also see the entry on Philosophy of Medicine, §1).
As discussed in Section 4.4, philosophical definitions aiming to avoid all values appeal to allegedly value-neutral statistical norms, and adaptive function, respectively. The vulnerability in Boorse’s (1997) statistical definition, where normal function is determined according to the person’s reference class identified by such criteria as age, and sex, lies both with assigning the appropriate reference class, a process that re-introduces values, and at the point on a continuous distribution curve where deviance from the mean is granted the status of dysfunctional (Bolton 2008). Recognizing that a trait may be dysfunctional in evolutionary terms without being disvalued, and disvalued without being evidence of dysfunction, Wakefield’s two-part definition explicitly accommodates the evaluative element marking the category. This attempt to provide a naturalistic and value free evolution-based account of “function” and “dysfunction” has been subject to a range of damaging objections, including the claim that with its preference for evolutionary fitness, biological dysfunction is not, as promised, value neutral, even in the first half of the definition. Discerning what would be the maximal response in terms of perpetuating the species represents another of these objections, since no agreed-upon conclusion about this can be drawn in a value-neutral, or perhaps any, way (Murphy & Stich 2000; Faucher & Forest 2021; Tsou 2021; Garson 2022). Critiques of more general disease definitions are also applicable mental disorder (Powell & Scarffe 2019).
Evaluativism and objectivism are customarily depicted as incompatible contraries, although the different domains where claims about disorder occur (including ordinary usage; conceptually clean versions of “health” and “disease”; the operationalization of dysfunction and the justification for that operationalization) indicate the need for a more nuanced analysis of the role of values in health and disease (Kingma 2014). The broad contrast between evaluativism and objectivism has also been resisted for other reasons. Judgments about mental disorder need not be entirely arbitrary and subjective as long as those values are taken to be real features of the world along the lines of McDowell’s secondary property value realism, for example. In this relaxed naturalism, objectivism implies that there is no privileged perspective for identifying the correct values relevant for psychopathology (Thornton 2007).
8.2 Societal and Personal Attitudes Towards Disorder and Diagnosis
The present discussion concerns evaluations that are primarily negative, although as we saw earlier, positive evaluations arise in traditions valorizing madness, and many in the neuro-diversity movement insist that autism spectrum and other mental disorders are unexceptional human variations analogous to differences of gender, which ought to be granted respectful accommodation, not clinical treatment (Hoffman 2019; Chapman & Carel 2022). Negative social attitudes towards observable disorder have led to stigma, self-stigma, and discrimination (Hinshaw 2009). The madman and madwoman have been the subject of fear, misunderstanding, disparagement and condemnation, their failings exaggerated and humanity denied (Gilman 1985). With modernity, care and protection apparently replaced earlier, moralistic and neglectful arrangements (the reforms’ real effects and costs remain an unsettled matter of historical debate).[7] At the same time formal exceptions and protections, such as the insanity defense, recognized mental disorder as an exculpating excuse for wrongdoing and negligence. Despite such attitudinal change, however, these issues around responsibility remain contentious and unresolved (Pouncey & Lukens 2010; Singh, Sinnott-Armstrong & Savulescu 2013; Schramme 2014).
The consequences of being diagnosed has been demonstrated to be extensive, often personally transformative, and usually not benign. The extent of these effects has drawn research attention to first-person report and to the eloquent madness memoirs increasingly available for study. It has led to theorizing within formal philosophical writing, and also within the rhetoric of social movements and identity-focused political interest groups (see §10). The Recovery movement, for example, stresses the way the self and identity are diminished by diagnosis, which erodes and occludes equally important and more positive, attributes making up the whole person (Davidson 2013). Critiques of diagnosis place emphasis on its dehumanizing and “objectifying” effects that, magnified by stigmatizing societal attitudes, engender self-stigma (Hoffman & Hansen 2017; Hinshaw 2009; Thornicroft 2006). More recently, however, social media and our hyperconnected contemporary existence have contributed to a less stigmatizing and discriminatory world, by shifting discussions about ‘pathological diagnoses’ to positive social identities (Sulik 2011).
8.3 Psychiatric Bioethics and Neuroethics
Societal attitudes towards mental disorders (including features associated with disorders themselves) have given rise to a distinctive psychiatric bioethics that differs from traditional medical bioethics. Widespread stigma about disorders raises extra privacy and confidentiality issues, for example. Because of the powerful and disruptive effects of the experience of disorder, conceptions of disorder and its treatment are often linked to the self and identity of the subject in distinctive ways (Tekin 2019). The compromised perceptual, affective, and reasoning capabilities that at least temporarily mark severe disorder are seen to jeopardize the widely-valued traits of rational autonomy, responsibility, and coherent and unified personhood, leading to challenges over agency and decisional capacity (Radoilska 2012; Sadler, Fulford, & van Staden 2015). Finally, the fact that psychiatric treatment sometimes involves coercion raises unique ethical issues.
Coercive practices are judged of serious moral concern. For example, coercive treatment seems to jeopardize rights proclaimed by the United Nations Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (2006). Important philosophical issues here include whether there are person-centered or paternalist principles that would respectively obviate or justify coercive treatment; how to define coercion; what constitutes valid consent; and identifying links between coercion and stigma (Kallert, Mezzich, & Monahan 2011; Szmukler 2016; Cratsley 2019; Pouncey & Mertz 2019). Recent theorists have discussed “mental disorder exceptionalism” (different treatment for mental and physical conditions) and proposed potential tests for drawing relevant distinctions (Szmukler & Dawson 2011).
Aside from legal and moral liability, disorders affecting volition (e.g., addictive and compulsive disorders) have been considered in light of the moral capacities associated with attributing full adult responsibility. Efforts to ground the intuition that sufferers from these conditions are less than fully responsible agents have appealed to “deep self” and also “reasons responsiveness” theories of responsibility. Neither theory alone has been found to readily accommodate the collection of symptoms associated with this group of disorders (Schramme 2014; Summers & Sinnott-Armstrong 2019).
The related field of neuroethics explores developments and prospects in neuroscience that are particularly urgent and relevant for psychopathology (Bluhm, Jacobson, & Maibom 2012; Roskies 2007; Glannon 2015; Caruso & Flanagan 2018). For example, encroachment on “mental privacy” can be expected to disproportionately affect those with stigmatized genders, disorders and symptoms; and a future can be envisioned in which the semantic authority of first person symptom descriptions is undermined by diagnoses independently verified through imaging or other technologies (Maibom 2012). More generally, this new knowledge seems likely to foster a trend from the treatment of disorder to its prediction based on observed risk factors, which in turn permits initiatives such as the identification and treatment of early onset, “prodromal” conditions in younger subjects (children and youth), likely affecting identity development and self-management (Broome, Fusar-Poli, & Wuyts 2013; Whitaker & Cosgrove 2015; Radden 2018; also see the entries on Philosophy of Neuroscience and Neuroethics).
Concepts of responsibility, together with concepts of personhood, autonomy, diminished capacity, and individual rights, make up an inescapable aspect of the broad field of psychiatric ethics. Areas of recent research concern responsibility and blame. Attitudes of blame are customarily treated as an appropriate sequel to assigning responsibility (Watson 2004), but Hanna Pickard (2011) uncouples responsibility from blame. For the apparently willful behavior of those diagnosed with disorders affecting agency, she argues, the proper stance for the care-giver is grounded in an empathetic attitude (that assigns responsibility without blaming), which is conducive to improvement and recovery.
Closely related responsibility issues involve the personality disorders that—due to their long-recognized relationship to more normal character weaknesses and their evidently dimensional nature—sit uneasily within psychiatric classifications (Sinnott-Armstrong 2008; Pickard 2011, 2016). One DSM grouping (cluster B personality disorders, including borderline, narcissistic and antisocial), are better approached using persuasion and methods reminiscent of the “moral treatment” of earlier times (Charland 2004).
Philosophical challenges to customary moral, ethical, and medical presuppositions introduced in this section have been influenced by, and are difficult to separate from, critiques of medical psychiatry that have taken place not only within academe, but also beyond it (see §10).
9. Particular Disorders
While often more ambitious and encompassing, philosophical attempts to define or characterize mental disorder have also provided finer-grained analyses (See Fulford et al., 2013; Moseley & Gala 2016; Tekin & Bluhm 2019). Beyond research into schizophrenia, which is the most plausible candidate of a natural kind, analyses have been offered for anorexia and other eating disorders (Gadsby 2017a, 2017b, 2020; Bordo 1993; Giordano 2005, 2019; Svenaeus 2013; Morris 2013; Tan, Hope & Stewart 2003; Tan et al. 2010; Radden 2021); addiction (West 2006; Poland & Graham 2011; Flanagan 2017; Vohs & Heatherton 2000; Levy, 2006, 2011, 2013; Foddy & Savalescu 2010; Holton & Berridge 2013; Kennett 2013; Lewis 2015; Summers 2015; Pickard 2016; Sripada 2018; Westin 2020; Glackin, Roberts, & Krueger 2021); anti-social personality disorder (Fuchs 2001, 2005, 2013; Roskies 2003; Levy 2007; Kennett & Fine 2008; Sinnott-Armstrong 2008; Adshead 2013; Maibom 2014; Schramme 2014; Justman 2021); depressive and manic-depressive conditions (Horwitz & Wakefield 2007; Radden 2009, 2013; Biegler 2011; Bluhm 2011; Bluhm, Jacobson, & Maibom 2012; Radoilska 2012; Wakefield 2012; Bolton 2013; Ratcliffe & Stephan 2014; Varga 2016; Hoffman & Hansen 2017; Browne 2018); scrupulosity, obsessive-compulsive, and other volitional disorders (Glas, 2013; Szalai 2016; Summer & Sinnott-Armstrong 2019); anxiety (Horwitz & Wakefield 2012); autism spectrum conditions (Adams 2013; Baron-Cohen, Lombardo, & Tager-Flusberg 2013); dissociative disorders (Maiese 2016; Worrell & Denham 2016); defiance disorders (Potter 2014); borderline personality disorder (Potter 2009); and premenstrual dysphoric disorder (Gagné-Julien 2021).
The category of psychosis—which includes delusions (false beliefs that resist reality testing) and hallucinations (most often auditory)—has received considerable philosophical attention. With almost unfailing consequences for their subject in clinical, legal, social, and personal settings, the severity of hallucinations and delusions distinguishes them from the more controversial disorders noted thus far. The incidence of and pathology associated with hallucinations has been questioned, as has their origins and phenomenology (Leudar & Thomas 2000; Henriksen, Raballo, & Parnas 2015; Ratcliffe 2017). And delusions have attracted the particular attention of philosophers for their incomprehensibility and challenges for theories about meaning, language, belief, and intention (Coltheart & Davies 2000; Bortolotti 2009, 2020; Fletcher & Frith 2009; Miyazono 2019; Evans 2023). They have also been the impetus for important collaborative work between several sciences: in addition to being psychiatric disorders, delusions occur as symptoms of neurological diseases and brain injury, which have made them subject to considerable empirical study. Philosophical research on delusions primarily addresses issues their intelligibility, their status in relation to more normal doxastic states, and their place in explanatory models.
The intelligibility of delusions remains contested. Delusions are expressed using unexceptional syntax, and some involve content that, while inaccurate or implausible, is entirely comprehensible. These, Jaspers insisted, are secondary delusions; primary delusions, in contrast, are distinguished by their meaninglessness: attributing meaning to them is a misapplication of the hermeneutic approach (Jaspers 1913 [1963]; Gorski 2012). Others argue that all delusions are meaningless utterances (Berrios 1991), which is supported by findings from neuroscience (Gerrans 2014). In contrast, some argue that delusions are always comprehensible, but only when contextualized to a person’s entire life, ideas, and values (Bentall 2004; Mullen & Gillett 2014; Glover 2014; Wickham & Bentall 2016; Jeppsson 2021; Gipps 2022).
Delusions are belief-like, but disagreements arise over whether they are beliefs, imaginings, an incomplete form of one of these two, or a distinct hybrid form. The doxastic position (delusions are beliefs) must somehow accommodate the fact that delusions are not responsive to countervailing evidence and are only weakly behavior guiding (see Flores 2021 and the entry on Delusion). Associated more with imagining than with believing, these same features have led to the assertion that delusions are imaginings mistakenly identified as beliefs (Currie & Ravenscroft 2002; Broome & Bortolotti 2009) or the hybrid concept of “bimagining” (Egan 2009).
Increasingly, explanations of delusions are multi-factorial. Influential early models that grew out of research on single-themed delusions resulting from brain damage (e.g., Capgras) hypothesized two deficiencies. The first factor is an initiating aberrant experience or perception due to brain dysfunction, combined with some failure of the system of “belief fixation” by which initial beliefs are critically reviewed in light of other information (Davies et al. 2001; Aimola Davies & Davies 2009; Young 2011). The second factor in such “two factor” theories is faulty inference, which in some accounts is conceptualized as differing in degree (alone) from normal forms of reasoning error, such as attribution bias (Bentall 2004). In “prediction error” models, perceptual aberrations conflict with prior (Bayesian) expectations when accompanied by reasoning bias, giving rise to delusions (Stone & Young 2007; Mishara & Corlett 2009). The “polythematic” and complex delusions more often seen in the psychiatry clinic—which are partially driven by social and environmental factors—present significant challenges for cognitive science since they involve the higher cognitive systems that apparently resist modular analysis and decomposition.
10. Anti-psychiatry, Feminist Theory, Post- and Critical- Psychiatry, Neurodiversity and Identity Politics
10.1 Anti-psychiatry
“Anti-psychiatry” has come to stand for ideas from mid-twentieth century thinkers such as Thomas Szasz, R.D. Laing, and Michel Foucault. Many of these involved social and political critiques and calls to action, with real-world consequences that have been linked to deinstitutionalization, human rights movements, and a shift towards more autonomy-focused mental health care. Szasz and Laing rejected the appropriateness of analogizing particular “problems in living” (Szasz) with medical disorders, insisting that misapplication of the medical model to mental health was emblematic of the overreach of psychiatry. The practices and discourses within society and its institutions making up the era’s episteme are depicted historically by Foucault, the focus on the exercise of psychiatric power that, arising with modern science, is increasingly exerted through mechanisms of protection, surveillance, and control. With modernity, on this account, power is no longer brute force. Instead, it takes a more diffused and subtle form that imperceptibly disciplines and controls not only bodies, but selves (Foucault 1965; Rose 2009; Bracken & Thomas 2010, 2013; Iliopoulos 2012). Foucault’s sweeping ideas remain central to the “post psychiatry” and “critical psychiatry” that emerged during the beginning of the twenty-first century.
10.2 Feminist Theory
Interwoven with these ideas have been critiques from feminism and feminist theory. These include acknowledgment of the women’s actual and unwarranted institutionalization, emphasis on the harms of disempowerment and silencing (Kristeva 1987 [1989]), and discussions of epistemic injustice (Dotson 2011; Kidd, Spencer & Carel 2022; also see the entry on Feminist Social Epistemology). In a legacy affecting mental disorder even today, binary conceptualizations have assigned women and the feminine to illogicality, emotionality, subjectivity, the body, and madness—in contrast to men’s more valued traits (Lloyd 1984; Potter 2009). Feminist thinkers have focused on the medicalization of women’s normal traits; neglected and distorted research into gender-linked disorders; separate and unequal treatments for women; the mental health vulnerabilities associated with traditional women’s roles and identities; and diagnosis and treatment understood as tools of patriarchal social control (Russell 1995; Ussher 2011; Gagné-Julien 2021).
Feminism has consistently rejected traditional causal explanations of women’s disorder derived from allegedly natural biological predispositions, pointing instead to the effects of women’s oppressive socialization and to the consequences of devaluing women’s characteristics and abilities (Bluhm 2011). Some have emphasized the embodiment (and relationality) of the self and avoided the methodological individualism associated with psychiatric medicine (Bluhm, Jacobson, & Maibom 2012). Influenced by social theory and phenomenological approaches, more recent work focuses on the intersection of gender with marginality, invisibility, non-normativity, and oppression in lived experience (Nissim-Sabat 2013; Zeiler & Folkmarson Käll 2014).
10.3 Post and Critical Psychiatry
Proponents of post psychiatry reject both the modernist presuppositions of psychiatry and the assumption that disorder reflects flawed brain mechanisms or processes, arguing that these assumptions only serve to enhance the status of psychiatry and disempower those diagnosed with disorder (Bracken & Thomas 2005, Iliopoulos 2012). The new brain sciences will magnify this disempowerment, it is argued, with the agency and authority previously assigned to persons will be replaced by a bio-scientific “management of the mind” (Phillips 2009, 2013; Rose and Abi-Rached 2013). A more recent descendant of critical mid-twentieth century writing is critical psychiatry: critiques of the influence of the pharmacological industry (Phillips 1996, 2013; Moncrieff 2008; Whitaker & Cosgrove 2015; Karp 2017); a discourse around mental disorder that, influenced by hermeneutics, aims to be more sensitive to the meaning of symptoms (Bracken & Thomas 2010); and the promotion of a more equal and collaborative relationship between carers and those they treat (Double 2006; Cohen & Timimi 2008).
Associated with these ideas is growing recognition of the unique expertise of “service users” or “survivors” for understanding mental disorder and the importance of its inclusion for research (Faulkner & Leyzell 2000; Gergel 2012; Cooper 2017; Bueter 2018). These innovations have appealed to resources from critical theory, narrative research methods, the impediments to representational authority, and the co-production of knowledge (Voronka 2016; Russo & Sweeney 2016).
10.4 Neurodiversity
As the most recent among this range of broadly ‘anti psychiatry’ positions, neurodiversity offers a coherent account and has come of age within a cultural episteme that seems hospitable to it. Mental differences, it asserts, are equally natural and valuable, and no one type of functioning is more correct or valid than another. Analogies are drawn with differences of gender, ethnicity, and culture—including analogies involving social power inequalities. From its ready application to disorders on the autism spectrum, efforts have been made to apply the neurodiversity position more broadly, including to the symptoms of schizophrenia (Washington 2016, Chapman 2019, Chapman & Carel 2022).
10.5 Identity Politics
Claims arising from political movements made up of recipients of psychiatric care call for a seat at the policy-makers’ table; representational authority in the co-production of knowledge based on first person experience of psychiatric symptoms and treatment; attention to complaints of unjust treatment by the “survivors” of diagnosis and care; equality of mental health care with other disabilities or medical conditions; recognition of neuro-atypicality from proponents of a neurodiversity model of disorder (Ortega 2009; Polvora 2011); and from “mad pride”, the claim that madness is an attribution from which to draw strength and cultural identity. Largely neglected until now within psychiatry or philosophical writing, the claims of mad pride have recently been critically evaluated and related to the social theory of philosophers, such as Axel Honneth and Charles Taylor (Rashed 2019, 2021).
11. Future Prospects
Where might we expect philosophical work on mental disorder to go from here? One issue must be what role remains for conceptual analysis and commonsense psychology. Relatedly, whose standards should determine mental health? Modern science, and the merciless dictates of biology, or some richer eudaemonic vision? Even granted the authority to determine ideals of mental health, philosophers would encounter hard questions. How should we relinquish evaluative thinking in view of liberal traditions around responsibility and self identity? How generously should we be in attributing normalcy and diversity, rather than deficiency? How should we navigate the boundary of disorder and risk? New ways to understand, identify, and ameliorate mental disorders—along with technological advances that simultaneously permit new analyses of big data and exacerbate the hyperconnectedness of society—can only augment and extend such questions, perhaps in unimagined directions.
Bibliography
- Adams, Marcus P., 2013, “Explaining the Theory of Mind Deficit in Autism Spectrum Disorder”, Philosophical Studies, 163(1): 233–249. doi:10.1007/s11098-011-9809-z
- Adshead, Gwen, 2008, “Psychopaths and Moral Identity”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 20(4): 339–343. doi:10.1353/ppp.2013.0056
- Aftab, Awais and Mohammed Abouelleil Rashed, 2021, “Mental Disorder and Social Deviance”, International Review of Psychiatry, 33 (5): 478–485. doi:10.1080/09540261.2020.1815666
- Aimola Davies, Anne M. and Martin Davies, 2009, “Explaining Pathologies of Belief”, in Matthew Broome and Lisa Bortolotti (eds.), Psychiatry as Cognitive Neuroscience: Philosophical Perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 285–323.
- Allen, Colin, 2017, “On (Not) Defining Cognition”, Synthese 194(11): 4233–4249. doi:10.1007/s11229-017-1454-4
- Amundson, Ron and Shari Tresky, 2007, “On a Bioethical Challenge to Disability Rights”, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 32(6): 541–561. doi:10.1080/03605310701680924
- [APA] American Psychiatric Association, 2013, Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, fifth edition, Washington DC: American Psychiatric Association.
- Baron-Cohen, Simon, Michael Lombardo, and Helen Tager-Flusberg (eds.), 2013, Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives from Developmental Social Neuroscience, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199692972.001.0001
- Berrios, German E., 1991, “Delusions as ‘Wrong Beliefs’: A Conceptual History”, British Journal of Psychiatry, 159(S14): 6–13. doi:10.1192/S0007125000296414
- Berrios, German E. and Roy Porter (eds.), 1995. A History of Clinical Psychiatry: The Origin and History of Psychiatric Disorders, London: Athlone Press.
- Bentall, Richard P., 2004, Madness Explained: Psychosis and Human Nature, London: Penguin.
- Biegler, Paul, 2011, The Ethical Treatment of Depression: Autonomy through Psychotherapy, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262015493.001.0001
- Bluhm, Robyn, 2011, “Gender Differences in Depression: Explanations from Feminist Ethics”, IJFAB: International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics, 4(1): 69–88. doi:10.3138/ijfab.4.1.69
- Bluhm, Robyn, Anne Jaap Jacobson, and Heidi Lene Maibom (eds.), 2012, Neurofeminism: Issues at the Intersection of Feminist Theory and Cognitive Science, London: Palgrave Macmillan UK. doi:10.1057/9780230368385
- Bolton, Derek, 2008, What is Mental Disorder?: An Essay in Philosophy, Science, and Values, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780198565925.001.0001
- –––, 2010, “Conceptualisation of Mental Disorder and Its Personal Meanings”, Journal of Mental Health, 19(4): 328–336. doi:10.3109/09638237.2010.492483
- –––, 2012, “Classification and Causal Mechanisms: A Deflationary Approach to the Classification Problem”, in Philosophical Issues in Psychiatry II: Nosology, Kenneth S. Kendler and Josef Parnas (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 6–11. doi:10.1093/med/9780199642205.003.0002
- –––, 2013, “What Is Mental Illness?”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 434–450. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0028
- Bolton, Derek and Gillett, Grant, 2019, The Biopsychosocial Model of Health and Disease: New Philosophical and Scientific Developments. Zurich: Springer Nature.
- Boorse, Christopher, 1977, “Health as a Theoretical Concept”, Philosophy of Science, 44(4): 542–573. doi:10.1086/288768
- –––, 1997, “A Rebuttal on Health”, in James M. Humber and Robert F. Almeder (eds.), What is Disease?, Totowa, NJ: Humana Press, pp. 1–134. doi:10.1007/978-1-59259-451-1_1
- Borsboom, Denny and Angélique O.J. Cramer, 2013, “Network Analysis: An Integrative Approach to the Structure of Psychopathology”, Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 9(1): 91–121. doi:10.1146/annurev-clinpsy-050212-185608
- Borsboom, Denny, 2017,“A Network Theory of Mental Disorder”, World Psychiatry, 16(1): 5–13. doi:10.1002/wps.20375
- Bordo, Susan, 1993, Unbearable Weight: Feminism, Western Culture, and the Body, Berkeley: University of California Press.
- Bortolotti, Lisa, 2009 , Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780199206162.001.1
- –––, 2013, “Rationality and Sanity: The Role of Rationality Judgements in Understanding Psychiatric Disorders”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 413–433. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0030
- –––, 2020, The Innocence of Beliefs, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Bracken, Patrick and Philip Thomas, 2005, Postpsychiatry: Mental Health in a Postmodern World, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780198526094.001.0001
- –––, 2010, “From Szasz to Foucault: On the Role of Critical Psychiatry”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 17(3): 219–228.
- Broome, Matthew and Lisa Bortolotti (eds.), 2009, Psychiatry as Cognitive Neuroscience: Philosophical Perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780199238033.001.0001
- Broome, Matthew, Paolo Fusar-Poli, and Philippe Wuyts, 2013, “Conceptual and Ethical Issues in the Prodromal Phase of Psychosis”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 779–802. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0046
- Browne, Tamara Kayali, 2018, Depression and the Self: Meaning, Control and Authenticity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781316481578
- Brülde, Bengt and Filip Radovic, 2006, “What is Mental about Mental Disorder?”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 13(2): 99–116. doi:10.1353/ppp.2007.0001
- Bueter, Anke, 2018, “Public Epistemic Trustworthiness and the Integration of Patients in Psychiatric Classification”, Synthese 198 (Supplement 19): 4711–4729. doi:10.1007/s11229-018-01913-z
- Campbell, John, 2013, “Causation and Mechanisms in Psychiatry”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 935–949. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0055
- Carel, Havi, 2023, “Vulnerabilization and De-pathologization: Two Philosophical Suggestions”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 30(1): 73–76. doi.10.1353/ppp.2023.0013
- Caruso, Gregg and Owen Flanagan (eds.), 2018, Neuroexistentialism: Meaning, Morals, and Purpose in the Age of Neuroscience, New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780190460723.001.0001
- Castel, Pierre-Henri, Angela Verdier, and Louis Sass, 2014, “A New History of Ourselves, in the Shadow of Our Obsessions and Compulsions”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 21(4): 299–309. doi:10.1353/ppp.2014.0047
- Chalmers, David J., 1996, The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Chapman, Robert, 2019, “Neurodiversity Theory and Its Discontents: Autism, Schizophrenia, and the Social Model of Disability”, in Tekin and Bluhm (eds.) 2019: 371–390.
- Chapman, Robert and Havi Carel, 2022, “Neurodiversity, Epistemic Injustice, and the Good Human Life”, J. Social Philosophy, 53(4): 614–631. doi:10.1111/josp.12456
- Charland, Louis C., 2004, “Character: Moral Treatment and the Personality Disorders”, in Radden 2004: 64–77.
- Cohen, Carl I. and Sami Timimi (eds.), 2008, Liberatory Psychiatry: Philosophy, Politics and Mental Health, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511543678
- Coltheart, Max and Martin Davies (eds.), 2000, Pathologies of Belief, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
- Cooper, Rachel, 2007, Psychiatry and Philosophy of Science, Chesham: Acumen.
- –––, 2017, “Classification, Rating Scales, and Promoting User-Led Research”, in Poland and Tekin 2017: 197–220.
- –––, 2020, “The Concept of Disorder Revisited: Robustly Value-laden Despite Change”, Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 94(1): 141–161. doi:10.1093/arisup/aka010
- Cratsley, Kelso, 2019, “The Ethics of Coercion and Other Forms of Influence”, in Tekin and Bluhm 2019: 283–304.
- Cratsley, Kelso and Richard Samuels, 2013, “Cognitive Science and Explanations of Psychopathology” in Fulford et al. 2013: 413–433. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0027
- Currie, Gregory and Ian Ravenscroft, 2002, Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238089.001.0001
- Cuthbert, Bruce N. and Thomas R. Insel, 2013, “Toward the Future of Psychiatric Diagnosis: The Seven Pillars of RDoC”, BMC Medicine, 11(1): 126. doi:10.1186/1741-7015-11-126
- Davidson, Larry, 2013, “Cure and Recovery”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 197–213. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0015
- Davies, Martin, Max Coltheart, Robyn Langdon, and Nora Breen, 2001, “Monothematic Delusions: Towards a Two-Factor Account”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 8(2): 133–158. doi:10.1353/ppp.2001.0007
- Davies, Will and Rebecca Roach, 2017, “Reassessing Biopsychosocial Psychiatry”, British Journal of Psychiatry, 210(1): 3–5. doi:10.1192/bjp.116.182873
- Di Paolo, Ezequiel and Hanne De Jaegher, 2017, “Neither Individualistic, Nor Interactionist”, in Durt, Fuchs, and Tewes 2017: 87–104.
- Dotson, Kristie, 2011, “Tracking Epistemic Violence, Tracking Practices of Silencing”, Hypatia, 26(2): 236–257. doi:10.1111/j.1527-2001.2011.01177.x
- Double, D. B. (ed.), 2006, Critical Psychiatry: The Limits of Madness, London: Palgrave Macmillan UK. doi:10.1057/9780230599192
- Drayson, Zoe, 2009, “Embodied Cognitive Science and Its Implications for Psychopathology”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 16(4): 329–340. doi:10.1353/ppp.0.0261
- Durt, Christoph, Thomas Fuchs, and Christian Tewes (eds.), 2017, Embodiment, Enaction, and Culture: Investigating the Constitution of the Shared World, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262035552.001.0001
- Egan, Andy, 2009, “Imagination, Delusion and Self-Deception”, in Tim Bayne and Jordi Fernández (eds.), Delusion and Self-Deception: Affective and Motivational Influences on Belief Formation, New York: Psychology Press, pp. 263–280.
- Ellis, Brian, 2001, Scientific Essentialism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Evans, Amanda, 2023, “Anorexia Nervosa; Illusion in the Sense of Agency”, Mind & Language, 38(2): 480–494. doi:10.1111/mila.12385
- Faucher, Luc and Denis Forest (eds.), 2021, Defining Mental Disorder: Jerome Wakefield and His Critics, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Faulkner, Alison and Sarah Layzell, 2000, “Strategies for Living: A Report of User-Led Research into People’s Strategies for Living with Mental Distress”, London: Mental Health Foundation.
- Flanagan, Owen, 2011, “What is it Like to be an Addict?”, in Poland and Graham 2011: 269–292. doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262015509.003.0011
- –––, 2017, “Addiction Doesn’t Exist, but it is Bad for You”, Neuroethics, 10(1): 91–98. doi:10.1007/s12152-016-9298-z
- Flanagan, Owen and George Graham, 2017, “Truth and Sanity: Positive Illusions, Spiritual Delusions, and Metaphysical Hallucinations”, in Poland and Tekin 2017: 293–313.
- Fletcher, Paul C. and Chris D. Frith, 2009, “Perceiving is Believing: A Bayesian Approach to Explaining the Positive Symptoms of Schizophrenia”, Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10(1): 48–58. doi:10.1038/nrn2536
- Flores, Carolina, 2021, “Delusional Evidence Responsiveness”, Synthese, 199 (3–4): 6299–6330. doi:10.1007/s11229-021-03070-2
- Foddy, Bennett and Julian Savulescu, 2010, “A Liberal Account of Addiction”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 17(1): 1–22. doi:10.1353/ppp.0.0282
- Foucault, Michel, 1965, Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason, Richard Howard (trans.), New York: Vintage; abridged translation of the 1961 French original Folie et Déraison: Histoire de la folie à l’âge classique.
- Friedenberg, Jay and Gordon Silverman, 2011, Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Study of Mind, Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications.
- Frith, Christopher D., 1992, The Cognitive Neuroscience of Schizophrenia, Hillsdale NJ: Erlbaum.
- Fuchs, Thomas, 2001, “Melancholia as a Desynchronization: Towards a Psychopathology of Interpersonal Time”, Psychopathology, 34(4): 179–186. doi:10.1159/000049304
- –––, 2005, “Corporealized and Disembodied Minds: A Phenomenological View of the Body in Melancholia and Schizophrenia”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 12(2): 95–107.
- –––, 2013, “The Phenomenology of Affectivity”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 612–631. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0038
- Fulford, K. W. M., 2004. “Facts/Values: Ten Principles of Value-based Medicine”, in Radden 2004: 205–234.
- –––, 2014, “Values-Based Practice: The Facts”, in Michael Loughlin (ed.), Debates in Values-Based Practice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3–19. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139855976.003
- Fulford, K. W. M., Martin Davies, Richard G. T. Gipps, George Graham, John Z. Sadler, Giovanni Stanghellini, and Tim Thornton (eds.), 2013, The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.001.0001
- Gadsby, Stephen, 2017, “Distorted Body Representations in Anorexia Nervosa”, Consciousness and Cognition, 51: 17–33. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2017.02.015
- –––, 2017, “Anorexia Nervosa and Oversized Experiences”, Philosophical Psychology, 30(5): 594–615. doi:10.1080/09515089.2017.1315083
- –––, 2020, “Self-Deception and the Second Factor. How Desire Causes Delusion in Anorexia Nervosa”, Erkenntnis, 85(3): 609–626. doi:10.1007/s10670-018-0039-z
- Gagné-Julien, Anne-Marie, 2021, “Wrongful Medicalization and Epistemic Injustice in Psychiatry: The Case of Premenstrual Dysphoric Disorder”, European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 17(2): S5–S36. doi:10.31820/ejap.17.3.3
- Gallagher, Shaun, 2005, How the Body Shapes the Mind, Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/0199271941.001.0001
- –––, 2013, “Intersubjectivity and Psychopathology”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 258–274. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0019
- Garson, Justin, 2015, “Psychiatry and the Mismatched Mind”, in Justin Garson, The Biological Mind: A Philosophical Introduction, Abingdon: Routledge, pp. 169–187.
- –––, 2022, Madness: A Philosophical Exploration. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Gergel, Tania L., 2012, “Medicine and the Individual: Is Phenomenology the Answer?”, Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 18(5): 1102–1109. doi:10.1111/j.1365-2753.2012.01926.x
- Gerrans, Philip, 2014, The Measure of Madness: Philosophy of Mind, Cognitive Neuroscience, and Delusional Thought, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262027557.001.0001
- Gert, Bernard and Charles M. Culver, 2004, “Defining Mental Disorder”, in Radden 2004: 415–425.
- Gilman, Sander L., 1985, Difference and Pathology: Stereotypes of Sexuality, Race, and Madness, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
- Giordano, Simona, 2005, Understanding Eating Disorders: Conceptual and Ethical Issues in the Treatment of Anorexia and Bulimia Nervosa, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0199269742.001.0001
- –––, 2019, “Anorexia Nervosa: A Case for Exceptionalism in Ethical Decision Making”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 26(4): 315–331. doi:10.1353/ppp.2019.0047
- Gipps, Richard G. T., 2022, On Madness: Understanding the Psychotic Mind, London: Bloomsbury Publishing.
- Glackin, Shane, Tom Roberts, and Joel Kruger 2021, “Out of Our Heads: Addiction and Psychiatric Externalism”, Behavioral Brain Research, 398: article 112936. doi/10.1016/jbbr.2020.112936
- Glannon, Walter (ed.), 2015, Free Will and the Brain: Neuroscientific, Philosophical, and Legal Perspectives, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139565820
- Glas, Gerrit, 2013, “Anxiety and Phobias: Phenomenology, Concepts, Explanations”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 551–573. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0035
- Glover, Jonathan, 2014, Alien Landscapes: Interpreting Disordered Minds, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
- Gorski, Mike, 2012, “Karl Jaspers on Delusion: Definition by Genus and Specific Difference”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 19(2): 79–86. muse.hju.edu/article/484341
- Graham, George, 2013, The Disordered Mind: An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Mental Illness, New York: Routledge.
- Hacking, Ian, 1995, “The Looping Effects of Human Kinds”, in Dan Sperber, David Premack, and Ann James Premack (eds.), Causal Cognition: A Multidisciplinary Debate, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 351–383. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198524021.003.0012
- –––, 1999, The Social Construction of What?, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
- Haslam, Nick, 2002, “Kinds of Kinds: A Conceptual Taxonomy of Psychiatric Categories”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 9(3): 203–217. doi:10.1353/ppp.2003.0043
- –––, 2014, “Natural Kinds in Psychiatry: Conceptually Implausible, Empirically Questionable, and Stigmatizing”, in Kincaid and Sullivan 2014: 11–28.
- Haslam, Nick and Erlend P. Kvaale, 2015, “Biogenetic Explanations of Mental Disorder: The Mixed-Blessings Model”, Current Directions in Psychological Science, 24(5): 399–404. doi:10.1177/0963721415588082
- Hempel, Carl Gustav, 1961, “Introduction to Problems of Taxonomy”, in Joseph Zubin, (ed), Field Studies in Mental Disorders, New York: Grune and Stratton, pp. 3–22.
- Henriksen, Mads Gram, Andrea Raballo, and Josef Parnas, 2015, “The Pathogenesis of Auditory Verbal Hallucinations in Schizophrenia: A Clinical-Phenomenological Account”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 22(3): 165–181. doi:10.1353/ppp.2015.0041
- Hinshaw, Stephen P., 2009, The Mark of Shame: Stigma of Mental Illness and an Agenda for Change, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med:psych/9780199730926.001.0001
- Hoffman, Ginger A., 2019, “‘Aren’t Mental Disorders Just Chemical Imbalances?,’ ‘Aren’t Mental Disorders Just Brain Dysfunctions?’, and Other Frequently Asked Questions about Mental Disorders”, in Tekin and Bluhm 2019: 59–92.
- Hoffman, Ginger A. and Jennifer L. Hansen, 2017, “Prozac or Prosaic Diaries?: The Gendering of Psychiatric Disability in Depression Memoirs”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 24(4): 285–298. doi:10.1353/ppp.2017.0041
- Holton, Richard and Kent Berridge, 2013, “Addiction Between Compulsion and Choice”, in Levy 2013: 239–268. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199862580.003.0012
- Horwitz, Allan V. and Jerome C. Wakefield, 2007, The Loss of Sadness: How Psychiatry Transformed Normal Sorrow into Depressive Disorder, New York: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2012, All We Have to Fear: Psychiatry’s Transformation of Natural Anxieties into Mental Disorders, New York: Oxford University Press.
- Iliopoulos, John, 2012, “Foucault’s Notion of Power and Current Psychiatric Practice”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 19(1): 49–58. doi:10.1353/ppp.2012.0006
- Irwin, Terence H., 2013, “Mental Health as Moral Virtue: Some Ancient Arguments”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 37–46. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0004
- Jacobs, Kerrin, Achim Stephan, Asena Paskaleva-Yankova, and Wendy Wilutzky, 2014, “Existential and Atmospheric Feelings in Depressive Comportment”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 21(2): 89–110. doi:10.1353/ppp.2014.0021
- Jaspers, Karl, 1913 [1963], General Psychopathology, J. Hoenig and Marian W. Hamilton (trans.), Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Translation of the seventh edition of Allgemeine Psychopathologie, first edition published 1913.
- Jefferson, Anneli, Lisa Bortolotti, and Bojana Kuzmanovic, 2017, “What is Unrealistic Optimism?”, Consciousness and Cognition, 50: 3–11. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2016.10.005
- Jefferson, Anneli, 2021, “On Mental Illness and Broken Brains”, Think, 20(58): 103–112. doi.10.1017/S1477175621000099
- Jeppsson, Sofia, 2021, “Psychosis and Intelligibility”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 28(3): 233–249.
- Jopling, David A., 2008, Talking Cures and Placebo Effects, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780199239504.001.0001
- Justman, Stewart, 2021, “The Guilt-Free Psychopath”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 28(2): 87–104. doi.10.1353/ppp.2021.0014
- Kallert, Thomas W., Juan E. Mezzich, and John Monahan (eds.), 2011, Coercive Treatment in Psychiatry: Clinical, Legal and Ethical Aspects, Chichester, UK: Wiley-Blackwell. doi:10.1002/9780470978573
- Karp, David Allen, 2017, Speaking of Sadness: Depression, Disconnection, and the Meanings of Illness, updated and expanded edition, New York: Oxford University Press. First edition in 1996.
- Keil, Geert, Keuck, Lara, Hauswald, Rico, 2017, Vagueness in Psychiatry, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Kendler, Kenneth S., Peter Zachar, and Carl Craver, 2011, “What Kinds of Things Are Psychiatric Disorders?”, Psychological Medicine, 41(6): 1143–1150. doi:10.1017/S0033291710001844
- Kendler, Kenneth S. and Peter Zachar, 2015, “The Incredible Insecurity of Psychiatric Nosology”, in Kenneth S. Kendler and Josef Parnas (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Psychiatry: Explanation, Phenomenology & Nosology, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press, pp. 368–382.
- Kennett, Jeanette, 2013, “Just Say No? Addiction and the Elements of Self-Control”, in Levy 2013: 144–164. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199862580.003.0008
- Kennett, Jeanette and Cordelia Fine, 2008, “Internalism and the Evidence from Psychopaths and ‘Acquired Sociopaths’”, in Sinnott-Armstrong 2008: 173–190.
- Khalidi, Muhammad Ali, 2010, “Interactive Kinds”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61(2): 335–360.
- Kidd, Ian James, Lucienne Spencer, and Havi Carel, 2022, “Epistemic Injustice in Psychiatric Research and Practice”, Philosophical Psychology, first online 20 December 2022. doi:10.1080/09515089.2022.215633
- Kincaid, Harold and Jacqueline A. Sullivan (eds.), 2014, Classifying Psychopathology: Mental Kinds and Natural Kinds, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Kirmayer, Laurence J., Robert Lemelson, and Constance A. Cummings (eds.), 2015, Re-Visioning Psychiatry: Cultural Phenomenology, Critical Neuroscience, and Global Mental Health, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139424745
- Kingma, Elselijn, 2014, “Naturalism about Health and Disease: Adding Nuance for Progress”, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 39(6): 590–608. doi:10.1093/jmp/jhu037
- Kontos, Nicholas, 2016, “Can What’s in Your Head be All in Your Head?” in Moseley and Gala 2016: 7–28.
- Kristeva, Julia, 1987 [1989], Soleil Noir: Dépression et mélancolie, Paris: Gallimard. Translated by Leon S. Roudiez as Black Sun: Depression and Melancholia, New York: Columbia University Press, 1989.
- Kusters, Wouter, 2016, “Philosophy and Madness. Radical Turns in the Natural Attitude to Life”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 23(2): 129–146. doi:10.1353/ppp.2016.0012
- Lalumera, Elisabetta, 2016, “Saving the DSM-5? Descriptive Conceptions and Theoretical Concepts of Mental Disorders”, Medicina & Storia, 16(9–10): 109–127.
- Leudar, Ivan and Philip Thomas, 2000, Voices of Reason, Voices of Insanity: Studies of Verbal Hallucinations, London: Routledge.
- Levy, Neil, 2006, “Autonomy and Addiction”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 36(3): 427–447. doi:10.1353/cjp.2006.0018
- –––, 2007, “The Responsibility of the Psychopath Revisited”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 14(2): 129–138. doi:10.1353/ppp.0.0003
- –––, 2011, “Addiction, Responsibility, and Ego Depletion”, in Poland and Graham 2011: 89–112. doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262015509.003.0004
- ––– (ed.), 2013, Addiction and Self-Control: Perspectives from Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199862580.001.0001
- Lewis, Benjamin R., 2015, “‘The Drugs Didn’t Mix’: On the Overvaluation of Misvaluation”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 22(1): 41–43. doi:10.1353/ppp.2015.0013
- Lilienfeld, Scott O. and Lori Marino, 1995, “Mental Disorder as a Roschian Concept: A Critique of Wakefield’s ‘Harmful Dysfunction’ Analysis”, Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 104(3): 411–420. doi:10.1037/0021-843X.104.3.411
- Lloyd, Genevieve, 1984, The Man of Reason : “Male” and “Female” in Western Philosophy, London: Methuen.
- Machery, Edouard, 2017, “Kinds or Tails?” in Poland and Tekin 2017: 15–35.
- Madeira, Luis, Elizabeth Pienkos, Teresa Filipe, Mariana Melo, Guilherme Queiroz, Joao Eira, Cristina Costa, Maria Luisa Figueira, and Louis Sass, 2019, “Self and World Experience in Non-Affective First Episode of Psychosis”, Schizophrenia Research, 211: 69–78. doi:10.1016/j.shres.2019.07.001
- Maibom, Heidi Lene, 2014, “To Treat a Psychopath”, Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 35(1): 31–42. doi:10.1007/s11017-014-9281-9
- Maiese, Michelle, 2016, Embodied Selves and Divided Minds, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780199689231.001.0001
- McKay, Ryan T. and Daniel C. Dennett, 2009, “The Evolution of Misbelief”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32(6): 493–561. doi:10.1017/S0140525X09990975
- Miyazono, Kengo, 2019, Delusions & Beliefs: A Philosophical Inquiry, London: Routledge.
- Mishara, Aaron L, 2007, “Missing Links in Phenomenological Clinical Neuroscience: Why We Still Are Not There Yet”:, Current Opinion in Psychiatry, 20(6): 559–569. doi:10.1097/YCO.0b013e3282f128b8
- Mishara, Aaron L. and Phil Corlett, 2009, “Are Delusions Biologically Adaptive? Salvaging the Doxastic Shear Pin”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32(6): 530–531. doi:10.1017/S0140525X09991464
- Moncrieff, Joanna, 2008, The Myth of the Chemical Cure: A Critique of Psychiatric Drug Treatment, London: Palgrave Macmillan.
- Morris, Katherine J.,2013, “Body Image Disorders”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 592–611. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0037
- Morris, Sarah E., Charles A. Sanislow, Jenni Pacheco, Uma Vaidyanathan, Joshua A. Gordon, and Cuthbert, Bruce, N., 2022, “Revisiting the Seven Pillars of RDoC”, BMC Medicine, 20(1): 220. doi:10.1186/s12916-022-02414-0
- Moseley, Daniel D. and Gary Gala (eds.), 2016, Philosophy and Psychiatry: Problems, Intersections, and New Perspectives, New York: Routledge.
- Mullen, Richard, 2011, “Psychopathology Divergent: Phenomenology and Empiricism”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 18(2): 157–161. doi:10.1353/ppp.2011.0020
- Mullen, Richard and Grant Gillett, 2014, “Delusions: A Different Kind of Belief?”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 21(1): 27–37. doi:10.1353/ppp.2014.0002
- Murphy, Dominic, 2006, Psychiatry in the Scientific Image, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Murphy, Dominic and Stephen Stich, 2000, “Darwin in the Madhouse: Evolutionary Psychology and the Classification of Mental Disorders”, in Peter Carruthers and Andrew Chamberlain (eds.), Evolution and the Human Mind: Modularity, Language and Meta-Cognition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 62–92. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511611926.005
- Nissim-Sabat, Marilyn, 2013, “Race and Gender in Philosophy of Psychiatry: Science, Relativism, and Phenomenology”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 139–158. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0012
- Nordenfelt, Lennart, 1995, On the Nature of Health: An Action-Theoretic Approach, 2nd edition, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, first edition 1987. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-0241-4
- O’Leary, Diane, 2021 “Medicine’s Metaphysical Morass” Synthese, doi:10.1007/s11229-020-02869-9
- Oliver, Mike, 2004, “The Social Model in Action: If I had a Hammer”, in Colin Barnes and Geof Mercer (eds), Implementing the Social Model of Disability: Theory and Research, Leeds: Disability Press, pp. 18–31. [Oliver 2004 available online (pdf)]
- Ortega, Francisco, 2009, “The Cerebral Subject and the Challenge of Neurodiversity”, BioSocieties, 4(4): 425–445. doi:10.1017/S1745855209990287
- Parnas, Josef and Louis A. Sass, 2008, “On Varieties of ‘Phenomenology’: On Description, Understanding, and Explanation in Psychiatry”, in Kenneth S. Kendler and Josef Parnas (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Psychiatry: Explanation, Phenomenology, and Nosology, Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, pp. 239–277.
- Pârvan, Alexandra, 2015, “Patients’ Substantialization of Disease, the Hybrid Symptom and Meta Physical Care”, Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 21(3): 380–388. doi:10.1111/jep.12250
- –––, 2016, “Monistic Dualism and the Body Electric: An Ontology of Disease, Patient and Clinician for Person-Centred Healthcare: Monistic Dualism and the Body Electric”, Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 22(4): 530–538. doi:10.1111/jep.12570
- Perring, Christian, 2016, “Commentary on Kinghorn: Evaluating Traditions in Psychiatry”, in Moseley and Gala 2016: 80–88.
- Phillips, James 1996, “Key Concepts: Hermeneutics”, Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 3(1): 61–9.
- Phillips, James (ed.), 2009, Philosophical Perspectives on Technology and Psychiatry, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780199207428.001.0001
- –––, 2013, “Technology and Psychiatry”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 176–196. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0014
- Pickard, Hanna, 2011, “Responsibility Without Blame: Empathy and the Effective Treatment of Personality Disorder”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 18(3): 209–224. doi:10.1353/ppp.2011.0032
- –––, 2016, “Denial in Addiction: Denial in Addiction”, Mind and Language, 31(3): 277–299. doi:10.1111/mila.12106
- Poland, Jeffrey, 2014, “Deeply Rooted Sources of Error and Bias in Psychiatric Classification”, in Kincaid and Sullivan 2014: 29–63.
- Poland, Jeffrey and Barbara Von Eckardt, 2013, “Mapping the Domain of Mental Illness”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 735–752. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0044
- Poland, Jeffrey and George Graham (eds.), 2011, Addiction and Responsibility, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262015509.001.0001
- Poland, Jeffrey and Şerife Tekin (eds.), 2017, Extraordinary Science and Psychiatry: Responses to the Crisis in Mental Health Research, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262035484.001.0001
- Polvora, 2011, “Diagnosis ‘Human’”, Wax and Feathers: The Icarus Project Zine, April 2011. [Polvora 2011 available online (pdf)]
- Porter, Roy, 2002, Madness: A Brief History, New York: Oxford University Press.
- Potter, Nancy Nyquist, 2009, Mapping the Edges and the In-Between: A Critical Analysis of Borderline Personality Disorder, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780198530213.001.0001
- –––, 2014, “Oppositional Defiant Disorder: Cultural Factors That influence Interpretations of Defiant Behavior and their Social and Scientific Consequences”, in Kincaid and Sullivan 2014: 175–194.
- Pouncey, Claire L. and Jonathan M. Lukens, 2010, “Madness versus Badness: The Ethical Tension between the Recovery Movement and Forensic Psychiatry”, Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 31(1): 93–105. doi:10.1007/s11017-010-9138-9
- Pouncey, Claire and Jon F. Mertz, 2019, “Informed Consent in Psychiatry: Philosophical and Legal Issues”, in Tekin and Bluhm 2019: 257–282.
- Powell, Russell, and Eric Scarffe, 2019, “Rethinking ‘Disease’: A Fresh Diagnosis and a New Philosophical Treatment”, Journal of Medical Ethics, 45: 579–588. doi:10.1136/medethics-2019-105467
- Radden, Jennifer (ed.), The Philosophy of Psychiatry: A Companion, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2009, Moody Minds Distempered: Essays on Melancholy and Depression, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2013, “The Self and Its Moods in Depression and Mania”, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 20(7–8): 80–102.
- –––, 2018, “Public Mental Health and Prevention”, Public Health Ethics, 11(2): 126–138. doi:10.1093/phe/phx011
- –––, 2021, “Capturing the Anorexia Nervosa Phenotype: Conceptual and Normative Issues in ICD-11”, Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 28(5): 807–813. doi:10.1111/jep.13586
- Radoilska, Lubomira, (ed) 2012, Autonomy and Mental Disorder, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780199595426.001.0001
- Rashed, Mohammed Abouelleil, 2019, Madness and the Demand for Recognition a Philosophical Inquiry into Identity and Mental Health Activism, New York: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2021 “An Approach to the Boundary Problem: Mental Health Activism and the Limits of Recognition”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 28(4): 297–313. doi:10.1353/ppp.2021.0047
- Rashed, Mohammed Abouelleil and Rachel Bingham, 2014, “Can Psychiatry Distinguish Social Deviance from Mental Disorder?”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 21(3): 243–255. doi:10.1353/ppp.2014.0043
- Ratcliffe, Matthew, 2008, Feelings of Being: Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the Sense of Reality, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780199206469.001.0001
- –––, 2011, “Phenomenology is Not a Servant of Science”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 18(1): 33–36. doi:10.1353/ppp.2011.0001
- –––, 2017, Real Hallucinations: Psychiatric Illness, Intentionality, and the Interpersonal World, (Philosophical Psychopathology), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Ratcliffe, Matthew and Achim Stephan (eds.), 2014, Depression, Emotion and the Self Philosophical and Interdisciplinary Perspectives, Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic.
- Reznek, Lawrie, 1987, The Nature of Disease, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
- Robinson, Daniel N, 1996, Wild Beasts and Idle Humours: The Insanity Defense from Antiquity to the Present, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
- –––, 2013, “The Insanity Defense as a History of Mental Disorder”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 18–36. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0003
- Rose, Nikolas, 2009, “Normality and Pathology in a Biomedical Age”, Sociological Review, 57 (Supplement 2): 66–83. doi:10.1111/j.1467-954X.2010.0188
- Rose, Nikolas S. and Joelle M. Abi-Rached, 2013, Neuro: The New Brain Sciences and the Management of the Mind, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
- Roskies, Adina L., 2003, “Are Ethical Judgments Intrinsically Motivational? Lessons from ‘Acquired Sociopathy’”, Philosophical Psychology, 16(1): 51–66. doi:10.1080/0951508032000067743
- –––, 2007, “Neuroethics beyond Genethics. Despite the Overlap between the Ethics of Neuroscience and Genetics, There Are Important Areas Where the Two Diverge”, EMBO Reports, 8(S1): S52–S56. doi:10.1038/sj.embor.7401009
- Russo, Jasna and Angela Sweeney, 2016, Searching for a Rose Garden Challenging Psychiatry, Fostering Mad Studies, Wyastone Leys, UK: PCCS Books.
- Russell, Denise, 1995, Women, Madness, and Medicine, Cambridge: Polity Press.
- Sadler, John Z., 2005, Values and Psychiatric Diagnosis, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780198526377.001.1
- –––, 2013, “Values in Psychiatric Diagnosis and Classification”, in Fulford et al. 2013: 753–778. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199579563.013.0045
- Sadler, John Z., K. W. M. Fulford, and C. W. Van Staden (eds.), 2015, The Oxford Handbook of Psychiatric Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198732365.001.0001
- Samuels, Richard, 2009, “Delusion as a Natural Kind”, in Broome, and Bortolotti 2009: 49–80. doi:10.1093/med/9780199238033.003.0004
- Sass, Louis Arnorsson, 2001, “Self and World in Schizophrenia: Three Classic Approaches”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 8(4): 251–270. doi:10.1353/ppp.2002.0026
- Sass, Louis, Josef Parnas, and Dan Zahavi, 2011, “Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia: Contemporary Approaches and Misunderstandings”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 18(1): 1–23. doi:10.1353/ppp.2011.0008
- Savulescu, Julian, Ruud ter Meulen, and Guy Kahane (eds.), 2011, Enhancing Human Capacities, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. doi:10.1002/9781444393552
- Schaffner, Kenneth F. 2012. “A Philosophical Overview of the Problems of Validity for Psychiatric Disorders”, in Kenneth S. Kendler and Josef Parnas (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Psychiatry II: Nosology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 169–189.
- –––, 2016, Behaving: What’s Genetic, What’s Not, and Why Should We Care?, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195171402.001.0001
- Schramme, Thomas (ed), 2014, Being Amoral: Psychopathy and Moral Incapacity, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Schwartz, Peter H., 2008, “Risk and Disease”, Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 51(3): 320–334. doi:10.1353/pbm.0.0027
- Scull, Andrew, 2009, Hysteria: The Biography, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Shorter, Edward, 2006, “Hysteria and Catatonia as Motor Disorders in Historical Context”, History of Psychiatry, 17(4): 461–468. doi:10.1177/0957154X06073012
- Singh, Ilina, Walter P. Sinnott-Armstrong, and Julian Savulescu (eds.), 2013, Bioprediction, Biomarkers, and Bad Behavior: Scientific, Legal, and Ethical Challenges, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199844180.001.0001
- Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (ed.), 2008, Moral Psychology, volume 3: The Neuroscience of Morality: Emotion, Brain Disorders, and Development, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Spitzer, Manfred and Friedrich A. Uehlein, 1992, “Phenomenology and Psychiatry”, in Manfred Spitzer, Friedrich Uehlein, Michael A. Schwartz, and Christoph Mundt (eds.), Phenomenology, Language & Schizophrenia, New York: Springer-Verlag, pp. 35–45. doi:10.1007/978-1-4613-9329-0_3
- Stanghellini, Giovanni, 2004, Disembodied Spirits and Deanimated Bodies: The Psychopathology of Common Sense, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780198520894.001.0001
- –––, 2016, Lost in Dialogue: Anthropology, Psychopathology, and Care, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Stegenga, Jacob, 2008, Care and Cure: An Introduction to Philosophy of Medicine, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Stein, Dan J., Katharine A. Phillips, Derek Bolton, K. W. M. Fulford, John Z. Sadler, and Kenneth S. Kendler, 2010, “What is a Mental/Psychiatric Disorder? From DSM-IV to DSM-V”, Psychological Medicine, 40(11): 1759–1765. doi:10.1017/S0033291709992261
- Stone, Tony and Andrew W. Young, 2007, “Delusions and Brain Injury: The Philosophy and Psychology of Belief”, Mind & Language, 12(3–4): 327–364. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.1997.tb00077.x
- Summers, Jesse S., 2015, “What is Wrong with Addiction”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 22(1): 25–40. doi:10.1353/ppp.2015.0011
- Summers, Jesse S., Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, 2019, Clean Hands: Philosophical Lessons from Scrupulosity, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Sulik, Gayle A., 2011, “Our Diagnoses, Our Selves: The Rise of the Technoscientific Illness Identity”, Sociology Compass, 5(6): 4463–477. doi:10.1111/j.1751-9020.211.00374.x
- Svenaeus, Fredrik, 2013, “Anorexia Nervosa and the Body Uncanny: A Phenomenological Approach”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 20(1): 81–91.muse.jhu.edy/article/511263
- Szalai, Judit, 2016, “Agency and Mental States in Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 23(1): 47–59. doi:10.1353/ppp.2016.0001
- Szmukler, George, 2016, “Coercion in Psychiatric Treatment and Its Justifications”, in Moseley and Gala 2016: 125–146.
- Szmukler, George and John Dawson, 2011, “Reducing Discrimination in Mental Health Law—The ‘Fusion’ of Incapacity and Mental Health Legislation”, in Kallert, Mezzich, and Monahan 2011: 97–119. doi:10.1002/9780470978573.ch7
- Tabb, Kathryn, 2015, “Psychiatric Progress and the Assumption of Diagnostic Discrimination”, Philosophy of Science, 82(5): 1047–1058. doi:10.1086/683439
- –––, 2019, “Philosophy of Psychiatry after Diagnostic Kinds”, Synthese, 196(6): 2177–2195. doi.10.1007/s11229-017-1659-6
- Tan, Jacinta O. A., Tony Hope, and Anne Stewart, 2003, “Anorexia Nervosa and Personal Identity: The Accounts of Patients and Their Parents”, International Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 26(5): 533–548. doi:10.1016/S0160-2527(03)00085-2
- Tan, Jacinta O. A., Anne Stewart, Raymond Fitzpatrick, and Tony Hope, 2010, “Attitudes of Patients with Anorexia Nervosa to Compulsory Treatment and Coercion”, International Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 33(1): 13–19. doi:10.1016/j.ijlp.2009.10.003
- Taylor, Shelley E. and Jonathon D. Brown, 1988, “Illusion and Well-Being: A Social Psychological Perspective on Mental Health”, Psychological Bulletin, 103(2): 193–210. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.103.2.193
- Tekin, Şerife, 2011, “Self-Concept Through the Diagnostic Looking Glass: Narratives and Mental Disorder”, Philosophical Psychology, 24(3): 357–380. doi:10.1080/09515089.2011.559622
- –––, 2016, “Are Mental Disorders Natural Kinds?: A Plea for a New Approach to Intervention in Psychiatry”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 23(2): 147–163. doi:10.1353/ppp.2016.0013
- –––, 2019, “The Missing Self in Scientific Psychiatry”, Synthese, 196: 2197–2215. doi:10.1007/s11229-017-1324-0
- Tekin, Şerife and Robyn Bluhm (eds.), 2019, The Bloomsbury Companion to the Philosophy of Psychiatry, London: Bloomsbury Academic.
- Thornicroft, Graham, 2006, Shunned: Discrimination against People with Mental Illness, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Thornton, Tim, 2007, Essential Philosophy of Psychiatry, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780199228713.001.1
- Tsou, Jonathan Y., 2007, “Hacking on the Looping Effects of Psychiatric Classifications: What is an Interactive and Indifferent Kind?”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Sciencec, 21(3): 329–344. doi:10.1080/02698590701589601
- –––, 2015, “DSM-5 and Psychiatry’s Second Revolution: Descriptive vs. Theoretical Approaches to Psychiatric Classification”, in Steeves Demazeux and Patrick Singy (eds.), The DSM-5 in Perspective: Philosophical Reflections on the Psychiatric Babel, Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 43–63. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-9765-8_3
- –––, 2016, “Natural Kinds, Psychiatric Classification and the History of the DSM”, History of Psychiatry, 27(4): 406–424. doi:10.1177%2F0957154X16656580
- –––, 2021, Philosophy of Psychiatry, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781108588485
- –––, 2022, “Biological Essentialism, Projectable Human Kinds, and Psychiatric Classification”, Philosophy of Science, 89(5): 1155–1165. doi:10.1017/psa.2022.64
- United Nations, 2006, Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (CRPD), Department of Economic and Social Affairs. [United Nations 2006 available online]
- Ussher, Jane M., 2011, The Madness of Women: Myth and Experience, (Women and Psychology), New York: Routledge.
- Varela, Francisco J., Evan Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch, 1991, The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Varga, Somogy, 2015, Naturalism, Interpretation, and Mental Disorder, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780198747253.001.0001
- –––, 2016, “Evolutionary Approaches to Depression: Prospects and Limitations”, in Alexandra Alvergne, Crispin Jenkinson, and Charlotte Faurie (eds.), Evolutionary Thinking in Medicine, Cham: Springer International Publishing, 347–356. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-29716-3_22
- –––, 2018, “Demarcating the Realm of Cognition”, Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 49(3): 435–450. doi:10.1007/s10838-017-9375-y
- Vohs, Kathleen D. and Todd F. Heatherton, 2000, “Self-Regulatory Failure: A Resource-Depletion Approach”, Psychological Science, 11(3): 249–254. doi:10.1111/1467-9280.00250
- Von Eckardt, Barbara, 1995, What is Cognitive Science?, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Voronka, Jijian, 2016, “Disciplines, Difference, and Representational Authority: Making Moves Through Inclusionary Practices”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 23(3): 211–214. doi:10.1353/ppp.2016.0020
- Wakefield, Jerome C., 1992, “The Concept of Mental Disorder: On the Boundary between Biological Facts and Social Values”., American Psychologist, 47(3): 373–388. doi:10.1037/0003-066X.47.3.373
- –––, 1997, “Diagnosing DSM-IV—Part I: DSM-IV and the Concept of Disorder”, Behaviour Research and Therapy, 35(7): 633–649. doi:10.1016/S0005-7967(97)00018-1
- –––, 2012, “Editorial: DSM-5: Proposed Changes to Depressive Disorders”, Current Medical Research and Opinion, 28(3): 335–343. doi:10.1185/03007995.2011.653436
- Washington, Natalia, 2016, “Culturally Unbound: Cross-Cultural Cognitive Diversity and the Science of Psychopathology”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 23(3): 165–179.
- Watson, Gary, 2004, Agency and Answerability: Selected Essays, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199272273.001.0001
- West, Robert, 2006, Theory of Addiction, Oxford: Blackwell.
- Westin, Anna, 2020, An Existential Phenomenology of Addiction. London: Bloomsbury Press.
- Whitaker, Robert and Lisa Cosgrove, 2015, Psychiatry under the Influence: Institutional Corruption, Social Injury and Prescriptions for Reform, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
- [WHO] World Health Organization, 2020, The ICD-11 Classification of Mental and Behavioural Disorders, Geneva: World Health Organization.
- Wickham, Sophie and Richard Bentall, 2016, “Are Specific Early-Life Adversities Associated With Specific Symptoms of Psychosis?: A Patient Study Considering Just World Beliefs as a Mediator”, The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 204(8): 606–613. doi:10.1097/NMD.0000000000000511
- Wiggins, Osborne P. and Michael A. Schwartz, 2011, “Phenomenological Psychiatry Needs a Big Tent”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 18(1): 31–32. doi:10.1353/ppp.2011.0013
- Wilkinson, Stephen, 2000, “Is ‘Normal Grief’ a Mental Disorder?”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 50(200): 289–304. doi:10.1111/j.0031-8094.2000.00186.x
- Worrell, Franklin and Alison Denham, 2016, “Fragments of the Self: Dissociation, Agency, and Integration”, in Moseley and Gala 2016: 214–237.
- Young, Garry, 2011, “Beliefs, Experiences and Misplaced Being: An Interactionist Account of Delusional Misidentification”, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 10(2): 195–215. doi:10.1007/s11097-010-9168-9
- Zachar, Peter, 2014, A Metaphysics of Psychopathology, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Zeiler, Kristin and Lisa Folkmarson Käll (eds.), 2014, Feminist Phenomenology and Medicine, Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Academic Tools
How to cite this entry. Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society. Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.
Other Internet Resources
Acknowledgments
Several colleagues offered suggestions about earlier drafts of this entry, for which the authors are extremely grateful: Edward Harcourt, Lisa Bortolotti, Jeff Poland, Derek Bolton, Somogy Varga, Kelso Cratsley, John Sadler, George Graham, Alexandra Pârvan, Şerife Tekin, and Christian Perring. Special thanks for invaluable comprehensive critique are owed to Ginger Hoffman and two anonymous readers assigned by the Encyclopedia.