Supplement to Proof Theory
E. Combinatorial Independence Results
Results that have been achieved through ordinal analysis mainly fall into four groups: (1) Consistency of subsystems of classical second order arithmetic and set theory relative to constructive theories, (2) reductions of theories formulated as conservation theorems, (3) combinatorial independence results, and (4) classifications of provable functions and ordinals. In this appendix we shall just provide a few examples of (3).[56] (4) is to be discussed in Appendix F.
Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems raised the question of
whether there is a strictly mathematical example of an incompleteness
in first-order Peano arithmetic and stronger systems, one which is
mathematically simple and interesting and does not require the
numerical coding of metamathematical notions. The first such examples
were found by Gentzen and Goodman. Recall from
section 3
the ordinal representation for
Theorem E.1 (Gentzen 1938b)
- The theory of primitive recursive arithmetic,
PRA, proves that PRWO
implies the consistency of PA. - Assuming that PA is consistent,
PA does not prove PRWO
.
This theorem is not explicitly stated in his 1938b but it is an immediate
consequence of his consistency proof of
PA.[57]
Goodstein, upon studying Gentzen’s 1936, established a
connection between descending sequences of ordinals below
where
For example
In 1944 Goodstein defined what came to be called Goodstein sequences.
Definition E.2 For naturals
Given any natural number m and non-decreasing function
with
where
We shall call
The case when f is just a shift function has received special
attention. Given any m we define
Goodstein proved that all Goodstein sequences are finite. From his work combined with that of Gentzen 1938b he could have concluded the following result (see Rathjen 2015: Theorem 2.9).
Theorem E.3 Termination of primitive recursive Goodstein sequences is not provable in PA.
Already the termination of special Goodstein sequences, i.e., those
where the base change is governed by the shift function, is not
provable in PA. This result was obtained only much
later by Kirby and Paris (1982) using model-theoretic tools. The
latter prompted Cichon (1983) to find a different (short) proof that
harked back to older proof-theoretic work of Kreisel (1952) which
identified the so-called
Mathematical independence results enjoyed great popularity in the
1970s and 1980s. Perhaps the most elegant of these is a strengthening
of the Finite Ramsey Theorem due to Paris and Harrington (1977). The
original proofs of the independence of combinatorial statements from
PA all used techniques from non-standard models of
arithmetic. Only later on alternative proofs using proof-theoretic
techniques were found. However, results from ordinal-theoretic proof
theory turned out to be pivotal in providing independence results for
theories stronger than PA, and even led to a new
combinatorial statement. The stronger theories referred to are
Friedman’s system
Definition E.4 A finite tree is a
finite partially ordered set
- B has a smallest element (called the root of
); - for each
the set is a totally ordered subset of B.
Definition E.5 For finite trees
We write
Theorem E.6 (Kruskal’s
theorem) For every infinite sequence of trees
Theorem E.7 Kruskal’s Theorem is not
provable in
The proof of the above independence result exploits a connection
between finite trees and ordinal representations for ordinals
A hope in connection with ordinal analyses is that they may lead to
discoveries of new combinatorial principles which encapsulate
considerable proof-theoretic strength. Examples are still scarce. One
case where ordinal notations led to a new combinatorial result was
Friedman’s extension of Kruskal’s Theorem, EKT, which
asserts that finite trees are well-quasi-ordered under gap
embeddability (see Simpson 1985). The gap condition imposed on the
embeddings is directly related to an ordinal notation system that was
used for the analysis of
Definition E.8 For
- for each
we have ; - if b is an immediate successor of
, then for each in the interval we have .
The condition (ii) above is called a gap condition.
Theorem E.9 For each
Theorem E.10
The proof of Theorem E.10 employs the ordinal representation system of
section 5.3.1.
for the proof-theoretic ordinal of
As to the importance attributed to the graph minor theorem, let us quote from a book on Graph Theory:
Our goal […] is a single theorem, one which dwarfs any other result in graph theory and may doubtless be counted among the deepest theorems that mathematics has to offer: in every infinite set of graphs there are two such that one is a minor of the other. This minor theorem, inconspicuous though it may look at first glance, has made a fundamental impact both outside graph theory and within. Its proof, due to Neil Robertson and Paul Seymour, takes well over 500 pages. (Diestel 1997: 249)
Definition E.11 Let
If X is obtained from Y by first deleting some vertices and edges, and then contracting some further edges, X is said to be a minor of Y. In point of fact, the order in which deletions and contractions are applied is immaterial as any graph obtained from another by repeated deletions and contractions in any order is its minor.
Theorem E.12 (Robertson and Seymour 2004) If
As a corollary to the graph minor theorem one obtains positive answers to two famous conjectures.
Corollary E.13
- (Vázsonyi’s conjecture) If all the
are trivalent, then there exist so that is embeddable into . - (Wagner’s conjecture) For any 2-manifold M there are only finitely many graphs which are not embeddable in M and are minimal with this property.
Theorem E.14 (Friedman, Robertson, and Seymour 1987)
- GMT implies EKT within, say,
. - GMT is not provable in
.
A further independence result that ensues from ordinal analysis is due
to Buchholz (1987). It concerns an extension of the hydra game of
Kirby and Paris. It is shown in that paper that the assertion that
Hercules has a winning strategy in this game is not provable in the
theory
It would be very desirable to also find mathematically fruitful
combinatorial principles hidden in stronger representation systems
such as the ones based on Mahlo cardinals and weakly compact cardinals
used for analyzing Kripke-Platek set theory with a recursively Mahlo
universe and with