1.
Probably the best all-purpose understanding of what logics are would
take them as equivalence classes of proof systems under the relation
of having mutually interderivable rules, though even this ignores
issues about translational equivalence across differing languages. For
many practical purposes it is sufficient to individuate logics more
coarsely, as consequence relations or generalized consequence
relations, or even, as is common in some areas, simply sets of
formulas.
2.
There has been much controversy as to how well this or that set of
rules governing implication or disjunction, for example, manages to
capture the (putatively) corresponding natural language
analogue—if-then, or (in the cases
cited)—but this entry will not be considering such
connective-specific issues.
3.
This coincides with the algebraically defined notion of a context
given above.
4.
Sometimes we will speak of as truth-functional over a class of
valuations instead of truth-functional with respect to the class, when
the immediate linguistic context contains another occurrence of the
phrase “with respect to”.
5.
See Leblanc (1966), p. 169 and n. 14; also Sundholm (2001), p.
38.
6.
We could make the same point apropos of the consequence relation,
say, determined by the class of all
-Boolean valuations. (See the opening paragraph of Section
5
for pointers to more information on all of this.)
7.
Had the historical development of logic run differently and the
framework we would naturally call Fmla-Set
come to initial prominence, we would have been
fussing about the consistent valuations being closed under disjunctive
combinations, and the sequent-undefinability of the class of
-Boolean valuations. As it is, we shall be hearing no more of
and .
9.
A somewhat similar range of properties is the focus of Williamson
(2006a), though with definitions that make the concepts in question
apply to arbitrary linguistic contexts and not just to connectives
(see
Section 1
above), and without the explicit relativity to logics (consequence
relations or generalized consequence relations).
10.
Additional background on these matters is mentioned in the opening
paragraph of Section
5.
For an articulation of the issues from an algebraic perspective,
Caicedo and Cignoli (2001), Caicedo (2004), and Ertola Biraben and San
Martín (2011).
11.
The fact that a generalized consequence relation is a binary relation
means that we need to distinguish symmetric and non-symmetric such
relations, as in general, and means that it is an unwise
terminological decision to call generalized consequence relations
symmetric consequence relations, as in Dunn and Hardegree
(2001), Chapter 6. There seems to be a confusion here between whether
a binary relation is symmetric and whether the treatment of
its two relata is symmetrical. Note, incidentally, that it is
binary relations that are symmetric, not binary operations
(connectives or otherwise), pace Restall (1999), p. 385, who
writes of a binary operation corresponding to a kind of conjunction
that it is “idempotent, symmetric, and associative”. The
word wanted is ‘commutative’. (Of course a connective
qua syntactic operation can never literally be commutative;
what is meant is that the corresponding
‘Lindenbaum-algebraic’ operation on synonymy-classes of
formulas is commutative.) Restall is in famous—if
muddled—company here; compare Quine (1951), describing
conjunction as transitive on one page (p. 18) and associative on the
next. The present point is not that one should never use terminology
appropriate to binary relations when speaking of
connectives—since there is, for instance, for any valuation
the relation , say, holding
between and just in case
and for Boolean valuations at least, this relation is symmetric. It
is just that a clearer head is called for than Quine and
Restall—and many other writers—have displayed in jumbling
up the binary relational terminology (reflexive, symmetric,
transitive,…) with the binary operational terminology
(idempotent, commutative, associative, …). Among the
‘others’ are Dunn and Hardegree (again), who write on p.
215 of Dunn and Hardegree (2001) of the “symmetry of
conjunction”. For (pointers to) more on all this, see the
opening paragraph of Section
5.
12.
Just as the sequents of Set-Fmla
can be thought of as those Set-Set
sequents with having exactly one element, those of Fmla
have the further feature that is empty,
making these sequents stand in a one-to-one correspondence with the
formulas of the language, with which for practical purposes we may
identify them, explaining the following words of the main text. There
are still two possibilities here, though. When the axiomatic or
‘Hilbert’ approach is taken, the rules are
formula-to-formula rules and the objects proved are formulas. On the
other hand, in our initial presentation of natural deduction, before
assumption discharging rules got into the act, the rules were again
presented as formula-to-formula rules, but with the things proved with
these rules were in effect Set-Fmla
sequents: meaning that the rules enabled us to
pass from a set of initial assumptions to a final formula. Should we
say that the logical framework here is Set-Fmla
on the basis of
what ends up being proved, or that it is Fmla,
on the basis of what the premisses and conclusions of the rules
involved are? Now that the distinction has been duly noted, there is
no urgent need to supply an answer to this question.
13.
The two views contrasted here are distinguished in Meyer (1974).
14.
In fact for any rules is derivable
from together with these structural rules if and only if
.
15.
Note that the operations and on valuations give least
upper bounds and greatest lower bounds with respect to this partial
order.
16.
In fact, Garson works with a variation on the framework Set-Fmla
which allows
sequents with infinite, and this feature
is essential to his proof of the claim here reported. Whether it is
essential for the correctness of the claim, I do not know.
17.
See the opening paragraph of Section
5.
18.
The condition for was given incorrectly in Garson (2001);
Garson (1990) should be consulted for the correct formulation.
19.
Dummett (1991) provides an extended discussion of such positions.
There is an interesting proposal in Peacocke (1987) for “reading
off” (Boolean) valuational semantics from inference rules found
‘primitively compelling’ by reasoners (as a necessary
condition for their possessing the concepts expressed by and,
or, etc.), which for some cases may be introduction rules and
others elimination rules. This attractive suggestion has unfortunately
come in for worrying criticism more recently: for example in
Williamson (2006b), (2013). It may be necessary to retreat from a
claim about possession of the concepts concerned, to a claim
about something like mastery of those concepts, with the
attendant obligation to spell out what the latter consists in, in a
way that does not make the claim vacuous.
20.
Thus the consequence relation associated with the present natural
deduction system is trivial—“almost inconsistent”,
as it sometimes put—in the sense introduced apropos of
Rautenberg’s maximality theorem in
Section 2.
(For a proper formulation of the natural deduction rules here the
above formula-to-formula rules should be explicitly represented as
sequent-to-sequent rules with a set parameter, “”
sitting on the left of a .) The provable sequents
and represent conditions on
this consequence relation induced by the determinants for
in the former case and for , in the latter. Thus any valuation consistent with this
consequence relation must respect each of two opposite
determinants—making Tonk
overdetermined—, taking and
taking . The only valuations that
respect both these determinants are , assigning
to every formula, and assigning to every
formula, and the logic determined by
is the smallest
trivial consequence relation on the language concerned. This is our
semantic gloss on the example. It would
be quite wrong to diagnose the problem in terms of the non-existence
of a truth-function corresponding to ,
or to say, as Stevenson (1961), p. 127, does,
that the problem is that Prior “gives the meanings of
connectives in terms of permissive rules, whereas they should be
stated in terms of truth-function statements in a metalanguage.”
(Prior 1976 replies to Stevenson, and inter alia suggests
that the consequence relation just described can be thought of as
“one-valued logic”—cf. Hamblin 1967; the
better term would be constant-valued logic.) There is nothing
incoherent about non-truth-functional—or more accurately, not
fully determined—connectives: the problem arises from being
overdetermined. The same objection, as Read (1988), p. 168, observes,
appears to apply to the remark in Peacocke (1987) that the
“semantical objection to tonk is that there is no
binary function on truth values which validates both its introduction
and its elimination rules”, though there is more room for
manoeuvre here: the implicit suggestion is that coherence requires
soundness, not soundness and completeness, under some truth-functional
interpretation. This amounts to deeming unintelligible any connective
which is ‘strongly contra-classical’, in the sense of not
being thus interpretable. But what does soundness under ‘some
truth-functional interpretation’ mean? It will not do to say:
soundness with respect to some over which the connective in
question is truth-functional, since the there may not be enough
variety in the truth-values supplied by to the formulas of
the language, in which case its elements may respect the determinants
for a truth-function only vacuously because some possibilities do not
arise. (For an extreme case, consider .) One
natural thing to require is that all combinatorially possible
truth-value assignments to the propositional variables are provided,
i.e., that . Note that this makes uncountable. For
most purposes, including the present one, a much weaker condition
suffices, namely that should be non-constant in
the sense that contains some valuation distinct from
and .
21.
One such example is mentioned in the opening paragraph of Section
5.
22.
The same phenomenon occurs with the proof system for the 1-ary
‘anticipation’ connective discussed in Ertola Biraben
(2012), as was first observed by Brian Weatherson.
23.
Of necessity, some examples in this paragraph have been mentioned
without the explanation that would accompany them in a fuller
treatment of this material. There is also a philosophical complication
ignored in the use, above and below, of such phrases as
‘adherent of intuitionistic logic’, in that they seem at
least to presume the incorrectness of a position that has been called
logical pluralism and defended under that name in Beall and Restall
(2006).
24.
Cf. Koslow (1992), base of p. 129.
25.
Requiring in blocks the proof of
the quantum-logically contested distribution sequent ; see Dummett (1991),
p.205f., and also, of ‘sequent calculus’ interest: p. 42,
especially three-quarters down the page. The general acceptability of
the distribution laws has also recently been questioned for reasons
independent of quantum-logical considerations in Holliday and
Mandelkern (2022), Holliday (2023). (In respect of
interactions, even the more fundamental absorption laws have
been known to raise eyebrows for certain equivalence relations of
logical interest, though we do not go into this here.)
26.
Rules for multiplicative and additive conjunction are given in
note 46.
See Troelstra (1992) for further information about linear logic.
27.
Actually a bit more is needed to obtain , in that
distribution of additive conjunction over additive disjunction is part
of which does not follow from the description
given. Further details can be found in Avron (1988).
28.
Here we see that the empty succedent is something of a luxury in
intuitionistic logic, rather than a necessity, since we could always
use to fill it—or rather, , as one would say,
since there are no -vs. subtleties to worry
about.
29.
Actually, there is a complication (being ignored here) because of the
contraction rule. One disadvantage of the set-based frameworks is
that, loosely speaking, applications of this rule become
invisible.
30.
Notice that with “” replaced by “” the inset sequents
are available by (Id) and (Weakening) on the left and right. Since the
comma here is not a connective, however, there is no formula—in
the absence of which could serve as
a cut formula on the basis of these two sequent premisses. On one
usage of the term ‘connective’, that associated with
Belnap’s Display Logic (see Restall (2000), Chapter 6) something
corresponding to the comma and many more somewhat analogous devices
are sometimes referred to as ‘structure connectives’ (as
opposed to ‘formula connectives’). This whole topic lies
outside of our purview.
31.
This example appears in a slightly different form, but explicitly
contrasted with that of in the same way,
on p. 164 of Došen and Schroeder-Heister (1985).
32.
This idea is essentially that of Setlur (1970), where a variation on
the theme of Helena Rasiowa’s, of taking hybrids in the
framework Fmla—holding fixed the
remaining connectives—is to be found. The device of taking
direct products of matrix tables which works in Fmla
does not fare so well in the richer frameworks;
some remarks on the comparison with Set-Fmla
in this respect can be found in Rautenberg
(1985), pp. 7–9, and (1989), esp. p. 532. (Or see the reference
given in the opening paragraph of Section
5.)
In an earlier publication, not listed in the bibliography, I used the
term ‘products’ instead of ‘hybrids’ for the
greatest lower bounds with respect to the subconnective relation,
oblivious to the confusion this might engender. It did at least have
one advantage, not shared by ‘hybrids’, of calling readily
to mind a word—namely sums—for the corresponding
least upper bounds, as illustrated by
below (for and .
33.
The term harmony has been used mostly, and subject to
various degrees of technicalization, for the relation of mutual
appropriateness of elimination and introduction rules in natural
deduction rather than, as here, to left and right rules in a sequent
calculus. See
Section 5
for references.
34.
The idea that we could use a rule of introduction or
insertion on the right with a proviso to the effect that formulas on
the left be ‘fully modalized’, and use this in the
reduplicated system to argue that since is provable, the duplicated version of this rule
allows the transition to , on the grounds that the formula on the
left is ‘fully modalized’, involves an illicitly equivocal
use of the latter phrase. Something close to a model-theoretic version
of this mistake would be involved in the suggestion that since
is determined by the class of models in which the
accessibility relation is universal, and there is only one universal
relation on any given set, is uniquely characterized by this
logic. The mistake here is to think that because we can simplify the
completeness result for from
equivalence-relational models to universal models, the same applies to
the bimodal “reduplicated ” logic that
is at issue for the unique characterization claim. (“Something
close”, because the syntactical argument would also apply in the
case of too, where nothing like the fallacy in
this model-theoretic reasoning is likely to seem tempting.)
35.
As with talk of the commutativity of conjunction, etc., what is meant
is that the corresponding operation in the Lindenbaum algebra of
formulas is a left inverse of that corresponding to .
36.
Substitution-invariance implies that the class of propositional
variables is not special; the latter is equivalent to
substitution-invariance given closure under uniform
variable-for-variable substitutions, a weakening of
substitution-invariance usually satisfied even by proposed logics not
closed under arbitrary (uniform) substitution—in which case,
accordingly, the propositional variables are special. An interesting
recent example of a logic (or range of logics) not even satisying this
weaker substitution condition is provided by those sporting
pattern connectives (van Toor, 2022), forming compounds whose
truth-values are sensitive not only to the truth-values of their
components (on a given a valuation) but to which of those components
are occurrences of the same formulas as are other other
components.
37.
One could understand this in terms of the constancy of an associated
truth function, but also purely syntactically: is constant according
to if all formulas with # as main connective are
-equivalent.
38.
There is a natural notion of conservative extension which applies
directly to (pairs of) consequence relations, but to avoid going into
that here, we have adopted a formulation in terms of conservative
extension as a relation between proof systems. Such a formulation
would not be ideal here anyway because the fact that the initial
consequence relation is -classical does not imply that the
extended consequence relation is, by contrast with the situation in
Set-Set, since the
conditional condition corresponding to is not guaranteed to be
preserved under extensions.
39.
This is sometimes put by saying that enjoys the Deduction
Theorem, generalizing some terminology from a particular way of
defining consequence relations on the basis of rules and axioms in
logic treated by the axiomatic approach.
41.
For (a reference to) more on this aspect of contraries and
subcontraries, see the opening paragraph of Section
5.
42.
This example comes from Humberstone (1995), though in 2019 Konrad
Turzyński observed (personal communication) that the four-valued
table for demi-negation – values denoted by 1, 2, 3, 4 –
given on the right of Figure 2 (p. 5) there, coincides with the
table – in values respectively denoted by – for the
‘initiation’ connective (written as a capital N with a
right-pointing arrow on top of it) of Leonard Sławomir Rogowski
in publications in Polish in 1961 and 1964 on the four-valued
‘directional logic’ he saw as motivated by some Hegelian
considerations. (Turzyński informs me that this coincidence had
also been noticed by Fabien Schang.) Exact references to Rogowski’s
papers, along with the table for initiation, can be found in
Turzyński (1990). (Alternatively, the 1964 piece, together with
the table in question, is given some attention in Kalinowski 1967.)
For more on demi-negation, see further p. 174f. of Humberstone
(2016) and references given there, as well as Paoli (2019), and, for
related material, Hitoshi and Wansing (2018). There have been many
other interesting recent developments and variations on the negation
front, several of them touched on in the discusison (and in items
cited in the bibliography) of Wansing, Olkhovikov, and Omori (2021);
see also De and Omori (2014) and – despite its title featuring
conditionals (the main theme) rather than negation
– Niki and Omori (2022). A more wide-ranging general
introduction to the field is provided by Horn and Wansing (2022).
43.
This is because there is no 1-ary truth-function with
and .
44.
As it happens, the (published) quantum-mechanically motivated work on
antedates the philosophically motivated
work by six years: see Deutsch (1989). Note that the phrase “the
proposed connective” is used unapologetically here—as in
the hybrids cases—in the absence of any suggestion that the
conditions to which we have subjected it suffice for unique
characterization.
45.
See §§3 and 4 of Humberstone (2000) for further discussion
and references, as well as sources cited in the first paragraph of the
Notes and Sources section (§5 of this entry).
46.
Contraction can be understood as the structural rule of that name in
the multiset-based frameworks or, for the axiomatic approach in Fmla,
as the schema . The sequent calculus rules for
(additive) are Left) as given in
Section 2,
with capital Greek letters reconstrued as multiset-variables, along
with Right) taking us from and to , while those for (multiplicative) are as
follows. The left insertion rule takes us from to , while
the right insertion rule takes us from and to . The Mset-Fmla
rules suited to Intuitionistic
Linear Logic are obtained from these Mset-Mset
rules by the
obvious restrictions on the right-hand sides.
47.
In linear logic already we have provable
without its converse, for instance.
48.
In a sequent calculus presentation one would instead add the inverted
form, sometimes called Expansion, of the structural rule of
Contraction.
49.
Theorem 5.8 in Blok and Pigozzi (1989) gives the desired and
for a given as and respectively. The proof on p. 49 of Blok and Pigozzi
(1989) is seriously garbled, though the result is correct. Speaking of
errors, let me mention that Dunn and Hardegree’s attempt to
explain what Blok and Pigozzi mean by “algebraizable”, at
Definition 7.13.3 of Dunn and Hardegree (2001), rather misses the
point, leaving out the requirement for two-way invertible translations
between and , and ends up
singling out the consequence relations which, in Blok and
Pigozzi’s terminology, “have an algebraic semantics”
(the algebraizable ones being those having what Blok and Pigozzi call
an equivalent algebraic semantics).
50.
This point is explained on p. 23 of Davies and Humberstone
(1980), where relevant work by Dummett is cited – not that
precisely this terminology is used there to make the point. Further
references to Dummett on this topic, and discussion of his preferred
approach to it via matrix methodology, can be found in §4 of
Humberstone (1998). The connection with the present semantic setting
is provided by thinking of frames with distinguished points (one per
frame), underlying the models considered in the first paragraph,
above, and recalling that any such frame gives rise to a matrix whose
elements are sets of points from the frame. One takes the set of all
such points as the sole designated element to capture the general
validity of formulas (to have validity in the matrix correspond to
validity on the frame), and takes all of sets of points containing the
distinguished point as the designated elements in order to capture the
real-world (or diagonal) validity of formulas. For the validity of
sequents (or the characterization of consequence relations) in the
general and real-world styles a more roundabout description –
not given here – is called for, since in either case it is the
local rather than global consequence relations that we are concerned
with here.
51.
Fusco (2019), p. 17, writes, concerning the favoured interpretation
of as (1)/(2),
“This semantic value for disjunctions comes from the classic
literature on disjunctive questions (Groenendijk and Stokhof, 1982;
Lewis, 1982).” The gloss here is fine if “comes
from” means “is inspired by, ” though not if it
means “coincides with that to be found in”. The details in
all three cases differ, as we can illustrate by comparing, below, the
semantic values they assign (relative to any model) to what we shall
write as in
all three cases. The semantic value of a formula/sentence we
take as a propositional concept in the sense of Stalnaker 1978: a
function mapping worlds to propositions sets of worlds),
whose argument is the reference world/world-taken-as-actual and whose
value is the set of worlds (of evaluation’ at which is
true relative to that reference world (in the model in question).
Since all we need to know about the reference world for this purpose
in the case in which is constructed from sentence letters
(as here, since the of current interest
is .
Fusco’s notation is used for all three cases, the third
being that described in Fusco (2015) (as well as in the
Stalnaker-style matrix in Figure 8 in Fusco 2019, which coincides with
Figure 3 of Fusco 2015), and ; is the set of worlds
at which the Boolean formula is true.
Lewis’s :
.
Groenendijk–Stokhof’s :
.
Fusco’s :
.
The Groenendijk–Stokhof characterization of the propositional
concept in question is based on lines 5–7 of p. 180 of
Groenendijk and Stokhof (1982). The first case listed under
Lewis’s name here is a ‘don’t care’ case for
him:
What happens if (…) more than one of the presented alternatives
are true? Then I think a presupposition required for the proper use of
the ‘whether’-clause has failed, with the result that no
clear-cut data on truth-conditions are available and so we may as well
handle the case in the most technically convenient way.
Perhaps the same should be said of the case in which neither
alternative is true (or no alternative it, as Lewis would put it,
since he thinks of the whether/ construction as
involving a multigrade – rather than a binary –
connective).
To obtain, from the specification of the propositional concepts as
above, a Boolean(ctually) representation having
a given such function as its semantic value – thereby spelling
out the understanding of
for the case in question, replace
the “maps to” arrow with with an implicational arrow, for
each of the four state-descriptions
, putting the antecedent
of the implication thus formed into the scope of
and dropping the s to
obtain its consequent . Thus
becomes
.
One then conjoins the four cases to give the desired representation.
Alternatively, since the antecedents
in a given case are mutually
exclusive and jointly exhaustive, we can replace the implications with
conjunctions and the conjunctions with disjunctions to obtain an
unrestrictedly equivalent representation. This is essentially the
relation between (1) and (2) in the main text (replacing the schematic
letters with sentence letters), except that in (1) Fusco has
simplified the representation by collapsing the
and
cases into a single
case, since the conditionals
with these -prefixed antecedents have the same consequent
(namely , with (2) following suit
in this regard.
The use of the -notation in
the three cases above should not be taken to suggest that Lewis and
Groenendijk–Stokhof were following Fusco’s general
strategy, of tailoring the received wisdom as to how disjunction works
across the board (namely as so as to give a single all-purpose
account working equally well for its bread-and-butter occurrences as
for certain problematically embedded occurrences, namely the
deontically embedded occurrences. It is not as though the main aim of
Lewis and Groenendijk–Stokhof had been to provide a similarly
uniform account, except with a different range of problematic cases,
namely the indirect question embeddings. Rather, their aim was simply
to provide some satisfactory compositional account of the
problematic constructions. (On this they make different proposals,
even restricting attention to the case in which exactly one of the
alternatives posed by an alternative question obtains –
, say, out of . To know, in
this case, whether or , understood
‘alternatively‘ – rising-then-falling intonation, as
opposed to knowing whether or not it is the case that or
– Lewis requires the subject simply to know that
, whereas Groenendijk and Stokhof require the subject to
know that and also that not, and quite
generally, for them knowing whether this is the case or that is the
case is a matter of knowing whether this is the case and
knowing whether that is the case, with alternative questions thus
reduced to multiple polar questions.) In a final section, Lewis (1982)
toys (not very enthusiastically) with a treatment of “whether
or ” as
whethwheth,
where wheth is interpreted as
. Here is an
operator that reduplicates the world of evaluation as the reference
world in the same way that reduplicates the reference world
as the world of evaluation, found in Stalnaker 1978, Davies and
Humberstone 1980 (note 16), Fusco 2019, as well as in work by Lewis
not in our bibliography, and elsewhere. This “”
has no effect on purely Boolean formulas, which is why were able to
state (3) in the main text without including it (given the restriction
on there). Also, the contemporary descendant of the
approach in Groenendijk and Stokhof (1982), namely inquisitive
semantics – see §7.1 of Aloni (2016) and §2 of Cross
and Roelofsen (2018) for more detail and further references –
manages considerable advances in unifying various expressions across
what might have been thought to be radically discontinuous uses across
declarative and interrogative contexts, though as an incidental
by-product in what may seem like the opposite direction, it makes
available at least three different disjunction-like connectives each
taken as the main form of disjunction in some piece of work in the
genre: see §6 in Humberstone 2019 for a comparative
discussion of them, as well as §7 there for further
(one-dimensional) aspects of the logic and semantics of
whether, with some examples of missteps in this area given in
Humberstone 2016 (see the index entries under knowing
whether).
52.
We ignore a slight complication here over -Elimination for one of
the consequence relations described in Fusco (2015) – that given
in Definition 13 there – because of an interaction between the
supervaluational treatment of that consequence relation and the
presence of an operator for what Fusco calls settled truth
and notates using as a solid black box.
53.
Footnote 36 in Fusco (2015) is potentially confusing on this score.
How best to reformulate it for Fusco’s purposes is not a
question that we can to go into here, because of the multiplicity of
consequence relations involved. Although the present selective
presentation of ideas from Fusco (2015) has focused on two such
relations – general consequence and diagonal consequence –
there are in fact four consequence relations in play in the discussion
there: see p. 20, left-hand column. (The preceding note alluded
to one of the consequence relations sidelined here.)
54.
This is not to say there are no difficulties in the vicinity. In
particular, expressed with a casual informality here, the following
difficulty arises. If it is supposed to be a priori knowable
that – for example, that
there are actually pandas in Lhasa if and only if there are pandas in
Lhasa, then how can
represent knowing
whether ? We presumably cannot know a priori
whether or not there are pandas in Lhasa. This problem is noted, and a
solution suggested, in Rabinowicz and Segerberg (1994). (These
authors, incidentally, use the terms strong and weak
validity for general and real-word/diagonal validity. A fuller listing
of the terminologies employed for this distinction by different people
is given in note 177 of Humberstone 2016, p. 219, with additional
background in note 45 on p. 60 of the same work.)
55.
If you do not have access to a diagram of the kind mentioned here,
see the opening paragraph of Section
5.
56.
Subsequent moves in a similar direction for cases for logics other
than (varying what counts as compositionality from
case to case) are made in Bonnay and Westerståhl (2023), Tong
and Westerståhl (2023).
57. Here we are saying , but didn’t the paragraph above (beginning
‘Accordingly’), end by speaking of
’s verifying the formula ? Yes, but
that was in the course of a Reductio proof that began by supposing
to have a truth-function associated with it on the valuation
a supposition we saw led to a contradiction. Here we are
simply following the definition of conjunctive combination: iff and , for
which this second conjunct fails, as .
58.
This perspective has been urged by many theorists with otherwise
differing inclinations, including Michael Dummett, Dana Scott, and
Roman Suszko. When dealing with a two-element matrix exactly one of
which is designated, as in Rautenberg’s maximality result in
Section 2,
the distinction between and
collapses.